Skip to main content
Log in

Interdisciplinary modeling: a case study of evolutionary economics

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Biologists and economists use models to study complex systems. This similarity between these disciplines has led to an interesting development: the borrowing of various components of model-based theorizing between the two domains. A major recent example of this strategy is economists’ utilization of the resources of evolutionary biology in order to construct models of economic systems. This general strategy has come to be called “evolutionary economics” and has been a source of much debate among economists. Although philosophers have developed literatures on the nature of models and modeling, the unique issues surrounding this kind of interdisciplinary model building have yet to be independently investigated. In this paper, we utilize evolutionary economics as a case study in the investigation of more general issues concerning interdisciplinary modeling. We begin by critiquing the distinctions currently used within the evolutionary economics literature and propose an alternative carving of the conceptual terrain. We then argue that the three types of evolutionary economics we distinguish capture distinctions that will be important whenever resources of model-based theorizing are borrowed across distinct scientific domains. Our analysis of these model-building strategies identifies several of the unique methodological and philosophical issues that confront interdisciplinary modeling.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By “borrowing” we merely mean making use of an element of model based theorizing in the construction of a model in a domain other than the one in which it was originally developed.

  2. Witt’s 2008 paper is a culmination of an influential series of papers evaluating evolutionary approaches to economics (Witt 1992, 1999b, 2003a).

  3. Indeed, Witt’s paper is aimed at elucidating what various economists within the literature have taken to be an “evolutionary” approach to economics. The influence of Witt’s analysis of evolutionary economics can be seen, for example, in Aldrich et al. (2008).

  4. We use the term interdisciplinary modeling to refer to any type of model building in which two or more scientific disciplines are involved in the construction of a scientific model. This is to be distinguished from constructing a model that applies within two or more disciplines or is somehow involved with a topic at the intersection of two or more scientific domains.

  5. Witt’s example of such an influence is the influence of human genetic endowment on economic behavior.

  6. In addition, Witt causes some confusion by calling the distinction between monism and dualism an ontological one. Both camps agree on how the world is, but disagree about the import of biological evolution for economic inquiry. As such the distinction is a heuristic one not an ontological one. Recognizing this difference is important because ontological claims and heuristic strategies require very different methods of evaluation.

  7. An important part of Darwin’s view is the claim that everything, including intentionality, must be explained within a naturalistic causal framework. This belief is similar to that held by Veblen (Witt’s paradigmatic monist), who suggested that human intentionality must be explained in causal terms and these causes would inevitably include reference to biological systems.

  8. Dennett never actually uses the phrase “Universal Darwinism”, but it is clear that the core of his view is the same as those defended by Dawkins and Campbell.

  9. This is not intended to imply that all evolutionary systems will have to be Darwinian in this sense. For example, Hodgson (2002) has argued that some systems in economics are Darwinian while others are Lamarckian. The Universal Darwinist only claims that the principles of Darwinian evolution are not domain-specific, but are substrate neutral.

  10. Dennett gives the example of long division, which works equally well with pencil and paper as with skywriting (Dennett 1995, p. 50).

  11. An account of the relationship between metaphors and analogies in science is beyond the scope of the paper.

  12. It is true that such an identity entails an analogy between all systems in which it holds. However, Universal Darwinists are interested in the operation of the principles themselves, not in the analogy between two similar systems.

  13. Of course one is employing biological concepts in some sense, but only insofar as the results of biological evolution are important for the study of economic systems. The concepts themselves are not borrowed in the sense of being used to describe anything about the economic system.

  14. The use of biological analogies has a long history within economics (see Hodgson 1993 for an extended discussion). Two particularly clear early attempts to utilize biological analogies in order to construct an economic model are given by Alchain (1950) and Penrose (1952).

  15. It is important to note that the common use of the term analogy would suggest that one could certainly draw an analogy with a system without using that similarity to aid in the construction of a model. Indeed, analogies can play other important roles in science, such as aiding in description or suggesting novel ways to test, describe, or explain a model or theory. Our focus here, however, is the use of analogy in the construction of models since this is where biology actually shapes the economic model or theory. Other uses of analogy (e.g. description) are primarily cognitive aids.

  16. Our term “theoretical modeling”, though not unrelated, should not be confused with Achinstein’s use of the term (Achinstein 1964, 1965, 1968). Achinstein uses the term within the context of the debate over scientific realism. We intend only to make a claim concerning whether a modeler believes their model is true of some target system.

  17. Precisely what it means for a model to be true is a matter of debate that is beyond the scope of this paper. For a further discussion of this complicated issue see (Mäki 2009).

  18. This distinction is similar to Michael Ruse’s distinction between the heuristic and justificatory roles of analogies (Ruse 1986, pp. 32–35). An analogy-as-heuristic employs an analogy without implying the same kinds of causal relationships within the two contexts. An analogy-as-justification, however, involves the transfer of claims of truth from one domain to the other.

  19. Although these authors discuss four Darwinian principles, the struggle for scarce resources is almost always subsumed by the principle of selection. Indeed, this struggle is usually precisely why selection occurs. Later on, Aldrich and Ruef actually ignore this fourth principle when applying Darwinian principles at the level of organizations.

  20. For example, agent-based economic modeling incorporates assumptions concerning the decision-making limitations of economic agents. These limits on agents’ rationality are often informed by biology.

  21. Holding to the theory of Universal Darwinism does not commit one thinking economics in particular is a place where the Darwinian algorithm applies. Our focus here, however, is on those who do endorse this claim.

  22. For instance, Cordes (2006) argues that in order for Darwinism to apply within other domains it will have to be watered down to the point where it is in danger of being explanatorily powerless.

References

  • Achinstein P (1964) Models, analogies, and theories. Philos Sci 31(4):328–350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Achinstein P (1965) Theoretical models. Br J Philos Sci 16(62):102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Achinstein P (1968) Concepts of science. Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchian AA (1950) Uncertainty, evolution, and economic theory. J Polit Econ 58(3):211–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich HE, Ruef M (2006) Organizations evolving, 2nd edn. SAGE Publications Ltd, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich HE, Hodgson GM, Hull DL, Knudsen T, Mokyr J, Vanberg VJ (2008) In defence of generalized Darwinism. J Evol Econ 18(5):577–596

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom TC (2002) Evolution of social behavior: individual and group selection. J Econ Perspectives 16(2):67–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1969) Variation and selective retention in socio-cultural evolution. Gen Syst 14:19–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C (2006) Darwinism in economics: from analogy to continuity. J Evol Econ 16:529–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1983) Universal Darwinism. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to men. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 403–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Simon and Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Frenken K (2006) A fitness landscape approach to technological complexity, modularity, and vertical disintegration. Struct Change Econ Dyn 17:288–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman D (1998) On economic applications of evolutionary game theory. J Evol Econ 8(1):15–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2006) The strategy of model-based science. Biol Philos 21(5):725–740

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Models and fictions in science. Philos Stud 143:101–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (1993) Economics and evolution. The University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2002) Darwinism in economics: from analogy to ontology. J Evol Econ 12(3):259–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006a) The nature and units of social selection. J Evol Econ 16(5):477–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006b) Why we need a generalized Darwinism, and why generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ 61(1):1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull D (2001) Science and selection: essays on biological evolution and the philosophy of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehtinen A, Kuorikoski J (2007) Unrealistic assumptions in rational choice theory. Philos Soc Sci 37(2):115–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54(4):421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2009) Models and the locus of their truth. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9566-0

  • Matthewson J, Weisberg M (2009) The structure of tradeoffs in model building. Synthese 170(1):169–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1978) Optimization theory in evolution. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 9(1):31–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McPherson JM, Ranger-Moore JR (1991) Evolution on a dancing landscape: organizations and networks in dynamic blau space. Social Forces 70(1):18–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McPherson JM, Popielarz PA, Drobnic S (1992) Social networks and organizational dynamics. Am Soc Rev 57(2):153–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2005) Idealized, inaccurate but successful: a pragmatic approach to evaluating models in theoretical ecology. Biol Philos 20(2):231–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose ET (1952) Biological analogies in the theory of the firm. Am Econ Rev 42(5):804–819

    Google Scholar 

  • Plotkin H (1994) Darwin machines and the nature of knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabin M (1998) Psychology and economics. J Econ Lit 36(1):11–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Robson AJ (2002) Evolution and human nature. J Econ Perspect 16(2):89–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson AJ, Kaplan HS (2006) Viewpoint: the economics of hunter-gatherer societies and the evolution of human characteristics. Can J Econ 39(2):375–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson AJ, Samuelson L (2011) The evolutionary foundations of preferences. In: Benhabib J, Bisin A, Jackson M (eds) The social economics handbook. Elsevier Press, San Diego, pp 221–305

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (1994) Does evolutionary theory give comfort or inspiration to economics? In: Mirowski P (ed) Natural images in economic thought: markets read in tooth and claw. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 172–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1986) Taking Darwin seriously: a naturalistic approach to philosophy. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruth M (1996) Evolutionary economics at the crossroads of biology and physics. J Soc Evol Syst 19(2):123–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter J (1934) The theory of economic development. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen T (1898) Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Camb J Econ 22(4):403

    Google Scholar 

  • Vromen JJ (2001) The human agent in evolutionary economics. In: Laurent J, Nightingale J (eds) Darwinism and evolutionary economics. Edward Elgar Publishing Limited, Northhampton, pp 184–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007a) Three kinds of idealization. J Philos 104(12):639–659

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007b) Who is a modeler? Br J Philos Sci 58(2):207–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1992) Evolutionary concepts in economics. East Econ J 18(4):405–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1999a) Bioeconomics as economics from a Darwinian perspective. J Bioecon 1(1):19–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1999b) Evolutionary economics and evolutionary biology. In: Koslowksi P (ed) Sociobiology and bioeconomics. The theory of evolution in biological and economic theory. Springer, Berlin, pp 279–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2003a) Evolutionary economics and the extension of evolution to the economy. In: Witt U (ed) The evolving economy. Essays on the evolutionary approach to economics. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, pp 3–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2003b) The evolving economy: essays on the evolutionary approach to economics. Edward Elgar Publishing, Northampton

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2008) What is specific about evolutionary economics? J Evol Econ 18(5):547–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank André Ariew and Randall Westgren for helpful discussion and comments on earlier drafts of this paper. This research was partially funded by the Al and Mary Agnes McQuinn Chair of Entrepreneurial Leadership.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Collin Rice.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rice, C., Smart, J. Interdisciplinary modeling: a case study of evolutionary economics. Biol Philos 26, 655–675 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9274-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9274-2

Keywords

Navigation