Skip to main content
Log in

On the neural enrichment of economic models: tractability, trade-offs and multiple levels of description

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the recent literature at the interface between economics, biology and neuroscience, several authors argue that by adopting an interdisciplinary approach to the analysis of decision making, economists will be able to construct predictively and explanatorily superior models. However, most economists remain quite reluctant to import biological or neural insights into their account of choice behaviour. In this paper, I reconstruct and critique one of the main arguments by means of which economists attempt to vindicate their conservative position. Furthermore, I develop an alternative defense of the thesis that economists justifiably rely on a methodologically distinctive approach to the modelling of choice behaviour.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The expression “decision making” is often used to denote both observed choice behaviour and the underlying cognitive and computational processes. In what follows, I employ such an expression to refer to observed choice behaviour, without taking a position as to whether economists qua economists should be concerned with those processes.

  2. Broadly defined, the domain of biological entities, events and processes would include the neural and the psychological domains as proper subsets. For the purpose of this paper, however, I use the term “biological” more narrowly to indicate the portion of the biological domain which is strictly distinct from the neural and the psychological ones.

  3. NE has been characterized in dissimilar ways both by economists and by other researchers. My use of the term is intended to be sufficiently general to encompass most of these characterizations. For a methodological comparison of different conceptions of NE, see e.g. Ross 2008 and Fumagalli 2010.

  4. The proponents of NE advocate the integration of neural insights in relation to both economic models and economic theory. The notions of “model” and “theory” have been characterized in several ways in the economic literature (see e.g. Mäki 1996, Sect. 5; Morgan and Morrison 1999, Chaps. 1–3), with most accounts making important distinctions between them. In this article, however, I speak of a neural enrichment of economic models and economic theory interchangeably, as the cogency of my considerations does not hinge on the difference between these two notions.

  5. In this paper, I use the expression “predictive power” to refer to both predictive accuracy, which denotes the exactness of a model’s observable implications regarding the investigated phenomena, and predictive reliability, which relates to the stability of a model’s predictive performance across distinct choice contexts.

  6. For instance, consider how the predictive gains offered by generalized expected utility models led many economists to alter the more tractable expected utility framework (see e.g. Starmer 2000, for a detailed review).

  7. See e.g. Mäki (1988, 1990, and 1992), on different senses in which the terms “realism” and “realisticness” are used in economics; see also Weisberg (2007a) and Matthewson and Weisberg (2009), on distinct notions of “generality” in biology.

  8. For example, as noted by Glimcher et al. (2005, p. 214), several NEs aim at constructing neurally enriched models that are highly parsimonious and predictive in a wide range of decision contexts. Parsimony and predictive power so frequently pull in contrasting directions that it is an open question whether NEs will manage to accomplish such an ambitious goal.

  9. Kahneman is far from being a strenuous defender of the traditional economic theory of choice. In fact, he was awarded the 2002 Nobel Prize in Economics “for having integrated insights from psychological research into economic science” (Nobel Press Release 2002).

  10. Various authors offer less convincing accounts of economists’ predilection for tractable models. To give one example, consider the observation by Gabaix and Laibson (2008, p. 295) that economists elevated modelling attributes such as tractability out of people’s tendency to “celebrate the things they do best”. Invoking this psychological propensity hardly accounts for the great importance economists attach to tractability. In particular, it fails to substantiate the claim that the reason why economists value this desideratum is because of their excellence at building tractable models.

  11. See e.g. Cartwright (1994), and Jones (2005), on abstractions; Mäki (1992), and Sugden (2000), on isolations; Cartwright (1983), McMullin (1985), Nowak (1972), and Weisberg (2007a), on idealizations.

  12. For example, NEs might replace the economists’ intertemporal discount rate with variables representing the activation patterns of neural areas whose operations influence agents’ intertemporal preferences.

  13. Various questions may be raised regarding how descriptive accuracy is most appropriately defined. My approximate characterization is sufficiently precise to enable me to examine the trade-offs I mention in this paper.

  14. For instance, economists typically aim at knowing not just whether observed choices are consistent with their predictions, but also why that is the case, since “it is only when we know that a theory works for the right reasons that we can be confident that it will continue to work” in different contexts (Schotter 2008, p. 79; see also Weisberg 2007a, p. 17, for a similar claim in the literature on biological modelling).

  15. For example, while rational choice theorists represent observed choices as the maximization of a utility function under some suitably defined constraints, cognitive psychologists account for those data in terms of specific heuristics and cognitive mechanisms, computational neuroscientists attempt to identify what neural algorithms underlie the observed decisions, and so on.

  16. I speak of “higher-level” and “lower-level” insights following an entrenched terminological convention in the philosophy of science literature. My doing so does not commit me to endorse the hierarchical view of the structure of science often held by those who employ these expressions.

  17. Similar remarks have been put forward in the recent literature on NE. For instance, Kuorikoski and Ylikoski (2010, p. 223) argue that the range of what if -questions that can be answered on the basis of the hitherto identified correspondences between neural areas’ activations and observed decisions is “very limited”. In their view, modelling agents’ choices in psychological terms enables one to answer a “broader range of what if -questions concerning possible alterations in the agent’s valuations, knowledge and how the relevant information is presented”.

  18. Among the constraints which will not abate with scientific advances, Matthewson and Weisberg (2009, p. 188) include strict trade-offs, increase trade-offs and Levins trade-offs. Two attributes display a strict trade-off “when an increase in the magnitude of one desideratum necessarily results in a decrease in the magnitude of the second, and vice versa”. An increase trade-off occurs when the magnitudes of two desiderata cannot be simultaneously increased. Finally, two attributes exhibit a Levins trade-off “when the magnitude of both of these attributes cannot be simultaneously maximized”.

References

  • Anderson ML (2006) Evidence for massive redeployment of brain areas in cognitive function. Proc Cogn Sci Soc 28:24–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson ML (2007) The massive redeployment hypothesis and the functional topography of the brain. Philos Psychol 21(2):143–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydinonat NE (2010) Neuroeconomics: more than inspiration, less than revolution. J Econ Methodol 17(2):159–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barraza JA, Zak PJ (2009) Empathy toward strangers triggers oxytocin release and subsequent generosity. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1167:182–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib J, Bisin A (2008) Choice and process: theory ahead of measurement. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics. A handbook, pp 320–335

  • Bernheim BD (2009) On the potential of neuroeconomics: a critical (but hopeful) appraisal. Am Econ J Microecon 1(2):1–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabeza R, Nyberg L (2000) Imaging cognition II: an empirical review of 275 PET and fMRI studies. J Cogn Neurosci 12:1–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF (2008a) The case for mindful economics. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics. a handbook, pp 43–69

  • Camerer CF (2008b) The potential of neuroeconomics. Econ Philos 24:369–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF, Loewenstein G (2004) Behavioral economics: past, present, future. Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton University Press, New York, pp 3–51

  • Camerer CF, Loewenstein G, Prelec D (2004) Neuroeconomics: why economics needs brains. Scand J Econ 106(3):555–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF, Loewenstein G, Prelec D (2005) Neuroeconomics: how neuroscience can inform economics. J Econ Lit 43(1):9–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwight N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwight N (1994) Nature’s capacities and their measurements. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Alexandrova A (2008) No revolution necessary: neural mechanisms for economics. Econ Philos 24:381–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli R (2010) The disunity of neuroeconomics: a methodological appraisal. J Econ Methodol 17(2):119–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabaix X, Laibson D (2008) The seven properties of good models. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 292–299

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A, Varian HR (1978) Economic models. J Philos 75(11):664–677

    Google Scholar 

  • Glimcher PW, Dorris MC, Bayer HM (2005) Physiological utility theory and the neuroeconomics of choice. Games Econ Behav 52:213–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul F, Pesendorfer W (2008) The case for mindless economics. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 1–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Guth W, Schmittberger R, Schwarze B (1982) An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining. J Econ Behav Organ 3(4):367–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless DW, Camerer CF (1994) The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica 62:1251–1289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison G (2008a) Neuroeconomics: a critical reconsideration. Econ Philos 24:303–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison G (2008b) Neuroeconomics: rejoinder. Econ Philos 24:533–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison G, Ross D (2010) The methodologies of neuroeconomics. J Econ Methodol 17(2):185–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks FA (2005) Unobservability, tractability and the battle of assumptions. J Econ Methodol 12(3):383–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks FA (2006) Tractability assumptions and the Musgrave-Mäki typology. J Econ Methodol 13(4):401–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houser D, Schunk D, Xiao E (2007) Combining brain and behavioral data to improve econometric policy analysis. Anal Kritik 29:86–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones RM (2005) Idealization and abstraction: a framework. In: Jones MR, Cartwright N (eds) Idealization XII: correcting the model. idealization and abstraction in the sciences. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2003) A psychological perspective on economics. Am Econ Rev 93(2):162–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knutson B, Rick GS, Wimmer E, Prelec D, Loewenstein G (2007) Neural predictors of purchases. Neuron 53:147–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld M, Heinrichs M, Zak PJ, Fischbacher U, Fehr E (2005) Oxytocin increases trust in humans. Nature 435:673–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski J, Ylikoski P (2010) Explanatory relevance across disciplinary boundaries: the case of neuroeconomics. J Econ Methodol 17(2):219–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landreth A, Bickle J (2008) Neuroeconomics, neurophysiology and the common currency hypothesis. Econ Philos 24:419–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. In: Sober E (ed) Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology, 4th edn. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 18–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein G, Rick S, Cohen JD (2008) Neuroeconomics. Annu Rev Psychol 59:647–672

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1988) On the problem of realism in Economics. Fundamenta Scientiae 9:353–373

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1990) Friedman and realism. Res Hist Econ Thought Methodol 10:171–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1992) On the method of isolation in economics. In: Dilworth C (ed) Intelligibility in science IV. Rodophi, Amsterdam, pp 317–351

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1996) Two portraits of economics. J Econ Methodol 3(1):1–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2010) When economics meets neuroscience: hype and hope. J Econ Methodol 17(2):107–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson J, Weisberg M (2009) The structure of tradeoffs in model building. Synthese 170:169–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May RM (2001) Stability and complexity in model ecosystems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • McCabe K (2008) Neuroeconomics and the economic sciences. Econ Philos 24:345–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1985) Galilean idealization. Stud Hist Philos Sci XVI:247–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M, Morrison M (eds) (1999) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Moscati I (2006) Epistemic virtues and theory choice in economics. London School of Economics-Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science, discussion paper 79/06

  • Nobel Press Release (2002) Psychological and experimental economics. Daniel Kahneman and Vernon Smith. http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/2002/press.html

  • Nowak L (1972) Laws of science, theories, measurement. Philos Sci XXXIX:533–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2003) Complex systems, trade-offs and mathematical modeling: a response to Sober and Orzack. Philos Sci LXX:1496–1507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ortmann A (2008) Prospecting neuroeconomics. Econ Philos 24:431–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH (2005) What, if anything, is ‘The strategy of model building in population biology’? A comment on Levins (1966) and Odenbaugh (2003). Philos Sci 72:479–485

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1993) A critical assessment of Levins’s ‘The strategy of model building in population biology’ (1966). Q Rev Biol 68(4):533–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park JW, Zak PJ (2007) Neuroeconomic studies. Anal Kritik 29:47–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Price CJ, Friston KJ (2005) Functional ontologies for cognition: the systematic definition of structure and function. Cogn Neuropsychol (3&4):262–275

  • Putnam H (1975) Philosophy and our mental life. In: Beakley B, Ludlow P (eds) The philosophy of mind, Ch. 13. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 91–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabin M (1998) Psychology and economics. J Econ Lit 36(1):11–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (2008) Two styles of neuroeconomics. Econ Philos 24:473–483

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden J (1979) Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: an introduction. Macmillan Publishing Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A (2008) Comments on neuroeconomics. Econ Philos 24:485–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rustichini A (2003) Brain experts now follow the money. Interview by Sandra Blakeslee, New York Times, June 17, 2003

  • Rustichini A (2005) Neuroeconomics: present and future. Games Econ Behav 52:201–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schotter A (2008) What’s so informative about choice? In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics: a handbook, Ch. 3. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 70–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Schultz W (1998) Predictive reward signal of dopamine neurons. J Neurophysiol 80:1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Schultz W, Dayan P, Montague PR (1997) A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science 275:1593–1599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer C (2000) Developments in nonexpected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. J Econ Lit 38:332–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2000) Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. J Econ Methodol 7(1):1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vercoe M, Zak PJ (2010) Inductive modeling using causal studies in neuroeconomics: brains on drugs. J Econ Methodol 17(2):133–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vul E, Harris C, Winkielman P, Pashler H (2009) Puzzlingly high correlations in fMRI studies of emotion, personality, and social cognition. Perspect Psychol Sci 4(3):274–290

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2004) Qualitative theory and chemical explanation. Philos Sci 71:1071–1081

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007a) Three kinds of idealization. J Philos 104(12):639–659. Available at: http://www.phil.upenn.edu/%7Eweisberg/documents/threekindsfinal.pdf

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2007b) Who is a modeler? Br J Philos Sci 58:207–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (1987) False models as a means to truer theories. In: Nitecki M, Hoffmann A (eds) Neutral models in biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 23–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Zak PJ (2004) Neuroeconomics. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 359:1737–1748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zak PJ, Kurzban R, Matzner WT (2004) The neurobiology of trust. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1032:224–227

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to J. McKenzie Alexander, Richard Bradley, Francesco Guala, Ivan Moscati and Michael Weisberg for the helpful comments they provided on earlier versions of this paper. I have also benefited from the valuable observations of two anonymous referees and the participants in seminars at Bocconi University, San Raffaele University and the University of Valencia.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Fumagalli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fumagalli, R. On the neural enrichment of economic models: tractability, trade-offs and multiple levels of description. Biol Philos 26, 617–635 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9272-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9272-4

Keywords

Navigation