Skip to main content
Log in

Costly signalling: a work in progress

William A. Searcy, Stephen Nowicki: The Evolution of Animal Communication: Reliability and Deception in Signaling Systems, Princeton University Press, New Jersey, 2005, 270 + xii pp, ISBN: 0-691-07095-4

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Evolution of Animal Communication is a detailed examination of a wide variety of animal signalling systems. The main focus of the book is explaining how such signalling systems remain reliable when there is apparent evolutionary pressure to deceive. The principle strategy is to appeal to signal costs: signals remain reliable because the potential benefits of deceit are outweighed by the costs of producing the deceptive signal. In this review I show just how difficult this idea is to test, even in the simplest cases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Deceptive signalling systems would pose an inverse problem: why do the receivers of signalling systems still respond?

  2. The puzzle of reliability isn’t the only point of interest for the study of animal signalling. The study of animal signalling systems prompts many questions. Do such signals carry information about the world, and, if so, what information is signalled? How do signalling systems evolve in the first place? Is the connection between signal form and what is signalled an completely arbitrary matter? Is signalling behaviour learned or is it innate? Can the study of animal signals be used as a window onto the minds of non-human animals? Are any animal signalling systems language-like? What are the physiological mechanisms that underlie signal production and registration?

  3. See pp. 16–17, 214–218.

  4. Zahavi (1975), Zahavi and Zahavi (1997).

  5. There is also a chapter on communication networks. I won’t be discussing this part of the book.

  6. See, however, Getty (2006) for an argument that Grafen’s model should not be used in cases concerning sexual selection.

  7. I am glossing over the complicated question of whether cases of sensory manipulation are examples of signalling.

  8. Their third example concerns the tails of blue peafowl, where the relevant tail feature is the number of spots rather than length (p. 125).

  9. See pp. 123–126.

  10. See p. 124.

  11. Over time the larynx of red deer has lowered, increasing the foment dispersion of their call. But since all the deer have done this, it is still a reliable indicator of size—this feature is now fixed in the population (Marynard Smith and Harper 2003, p. 46).

  12. This point is also made in Kotiaho (2001).

  13. Michael Jennions pointed out to me that there is a problem with Møller and de Lope’s study. The ideal experiment would compare the effects of increasing tail length on a low and a high quality male that both have the same initial tail length. That is, the ideal would be to start at the same place on the cost/benefit graph. But since the males to be compared have different tail lengths (the high quality males having longer tails), adding tail length to both and measuring the effects is starting at two different points on the cost/benefit graph.

  14. The metabolic costs of producing and maintaining long tails might be linear. However, Searcy and Nowicki write, “Unfortunately, the developmental costs of elongated feather ornaments have not, to our knowledge, been investigated directly.” p. 128.

  15. The target of Adams and Mesterton-Gibbons’ model is aggressive interactions between stomatopods. Stomatopods provide a particularly striking example of deception, as males who have recently moulted (hence are extremely vulnerable) nevertheless produce aggressive weapon displays when threatened.

References

  • Adams ES, Mesterton-Gibbons M (1995) The cost of threat displays and the stability of deceptive communication. J Theor Biol 175:405–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson M (1982) Female choice selects for extreme tail length in a widowbird. Nature 299:818–820

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David P, Bjorksten T, Fowler K, Pomiankowski A (2000) Condition-dependent signalling of genetic variation in stalk-eyed flies. Nature 406:186–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enquist M (1985) Communication during aggressive interactions with particular reference to variation in choice of behaviour. Anim Behav 33:1152–1161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Getty T (2006) Sexually selected signals are not similar to sports handicaps. Trends Ecol Evol 21:83–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1990) Biological signals as handicaps. J Theor Biol 144:517–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guilford T, Dawkins MS (1991) Receiver psychology and the evolution of animal signals. Anim Behav 42:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnstone RA (1997) The evolution of animal signals. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 155–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotiaho JS (2000) Testing the assumptions of conditional handicap theory: costs and condition dependence of a sexually selected trait. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 48:188–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotiaho JS (2001) Costs of sexual traits: a mismatch between theoretical considerations and empirical evidence. Biol Rev 76:365–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1991) Honest signalling: the Philip Sidney game. Anim Behav 42:1034–1035

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Møller AP (1990) Effects of a haematophagous mite on the barn swallow (Hirundo rustica): a test of the Hamilton and Zuk hypothesis. Evolution 44:771–784

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller AP (1994) Male ornament size as a reliable cue to enhanced offspring viability. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 91:6929–6932

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller AP, de Lope F (1994) Differential costs of a secondary sexual character: an experimental test of the handicap principle. Evolution 48:1676–1683

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe LV, Evans MR, Buchanan KL (2001) The function and evolution of the tail streamer in hirundines. Behav Ecol 12:157–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas RJ (2002) The costs of singing in nightingales. Anim Behav 63:959–966

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A (1975) Mate selection—a selection for a handicap. J Theor Biol 53:205–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A, Zahavi A (1997) The handicap principle: a missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stewart Saunders.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Saunders, S. Costly signalling: a work in progress. Biol Philos 24, 405–416 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9100-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9100-z

Keywords

Navigation