Skip to main content
Log in

Accounting for Consciousness: Epistemic and Operational Issues

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Within the philosophy of mind, consciousness is currently understood as the expression of one or other cognitive modality, either intentionality (representation per se), transparency (immediacy of cognitive content consequent upon the unawareness of underlying representational processes), subjectivity (first-person perspective) or reflexivity (autonoetic awareness). However, neither intentionality, subjectivity nor transparency adequately distinguishes conscious from nonconscious cognition. Consequently, the only genuine index or defining characteristic of consciousness is reflexivity, the capacity for autonoetic or self-referring, self-monitoring awareness. But the identification of reflexivity as the principal index of consciousness raises a major challenge in relation to the cognitive mechanism responsible for operationalizing such a reflexive state. Current reliance by higher-order and intrinsic self-representational theories on self-representing data structures to achieve reflexive self-awareness is highly problematic, suggesting a solution in terms of a self-referential processing regime.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Reflexivity is used here to connote cognitively operating upon or referring to itself in the same sense that a sentence is reflexive if it has the same subject and object, as in “The man washed himself”. Here the subject operates upon himself. Just so, cognitive reflexivity involves a cognitive process operating most immediately upon itself, thereby knowing itself or recognizing itself most immediately.

  2. Curiously, transparency has been deemed both the engine of consciousness, as Metzinger proposes, as well as the basis of the claim that consciousness itself is invisible or diaphanous, such that we see through our conscious awareness to the objects or representational content we are aware of (on which see Hume 1739–1740; Moore 1903; Tye 1995; Dretske 2003; Crane 2003).

  3. Smithies and Stoljar (2012: 20–21 N12) read Rosenthal’s higher-order thought theory of consciousness as claiming that “a mental state is phenomenally conscious if and only if one knows by introspection that one is in that mental state.” But this is incorrect. Rosenthal actually distinguishes consciousness from introspection, where the latter, he insists “involves more than a mental state’s being a conscious state. Introspecting a mental state is deliberately and attentively focusing on that state. Nonintrospective consciousness, by contrast, requires no special act of attention. Every introspected state is therefor a conscious state, but not conversely” (1997: 745). For Rosenthal, the two are not equivalent (cf Van Gulick 2001). Nonetheless, inasmuch as higher order theories in general invoke some additional cognitive act (thought about, belief about …) in relation to the primary cognition, they are closer to the understanding of consciousness reflexivity as consequent upon an act of introspection than to the understanding of consciousness as intrinsically relfexive without need of any such additional cognitive act.

  4. Janzen (2008: 106) also references similar positions outlined by Gurwitsch (1950: 6) and Smith (1989, Ch 2, Sect 3.2). Similarly, Zahavi notes (1999: 17) that refutation of the introspective model (the “reflection model”) of consciousness can be found in the Heidelberg School of German philosophers, including Heinrich, Frank, Pathast and Cramer. Kriegel (2009a, b: 179) cites argument for cosc as prereflective in continental Phenomenologists Husserl, Saarte, Merleau-Ponty and Gurwitsch.

  5. Where first order accounts of consciousness discount or ignore reflexivity altogether, or reduce it to either subjectivity or transparency (as discussed above), higher-order representational theories are explicitly focused on explaining consciousness as reflexivity, casting the consciousness-yielding representational process in terms of a higher-order data structure directed towards first-order content. Several cognitive data structures have been proposed to cognitively activate or operationalize the crucial awareness-of capacity, including higher-order perception (Armstrong 1981; Lycan 1996), higher-order belief (Dennett 2003), and higher-order-thought (Rosenthal 1997; Weisberg 1999).

  6. Where higher-order theories rely on a two-state representational structure to achieve reflexive self-awareness (consciousness),”intrinsic” theories posit a single self-representational state. Aristotle has been read as advocating this understanding (Caston 2002), while Brentano is usually credited with initiating this approach in the modern era (Thomasson 2000; Kriegel 2003, 2005; Zahavi 1999), and has been followed most recently by Natsoulas (1996), Kriegel (2003), Van Gulick (2004), Smith (2004) and Janzen (2008).

References

  • Alston W (1999) Back to the theory of appearing. In: Tomberlin J (ed) Philosophical perspectives 13 (epistemology). Blackwell, Malden, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong D (1981/1997) What is consciousness? In: The nature of mind. Cornell University Press, Ithaca NY, pp 55–67. Reprinted in Block N, Flanagan O, Guzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 721–729

  • Baars BJ (1988) A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars BJ (1997a) In the theatre of consciousness: global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 4:292–309

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars BJ (1997b) In the theatre of consciousness: the workspace of the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore SJ, Brelstaff G, Nelson K, Troscianko T (1995) Is the richness of our visual world an illusion? Transsaccadic memory for complex scenes. Perception 24:1075–1081

    Google Scholar 

  • Block Ned (1994) Consciousness. In: Guttenplan SD (ed) A companion to the philosophy of mind. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 210–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 18:227-87

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzi G (2011) False awakenings in light of the dream protoconsciousness theory: a study in lucid dreamers. Int J Dream Res 4:110–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (1997) Some like it HOT: consciousness and higher-order thoughts. Philos Stud 86:103–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (2001) Intentionalism defended. Philos Rev 110:199–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2005) Consciousness: essays from a higher-order perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2011) Higher-order theories of consciousness. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/consciousness-higher/

  • Castaneda H-N (1988) Self-consciousness, demonstrative reference, and self-ascription. In: Tomberlin JE (ed) Philosophical perspectives. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 405–454

    Google Scholar 

  • Caston V (2002) Aristotle on consciousness. Mind 111:751–815

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1995) Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 2:200–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (2004) The representational character of experience. In: Leiter B (ed) The future for philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 153–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne JA (2004) Borderlands of consciousness: between dream world and wake world. Paper presented at Toward a science of consciousness 2004 Tucson, Arizona, April 10, 2004

  • Churchland PS (2002a) Brain-wise: studies in neurophilosophy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PS (2002b) Self-representation in nervous systems. Science 296:308–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicogna PC, Bosinelli M (2001) Consciousness during dreams. Conscious Cogn 10:26–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2002) Is seeing all it seems? Action, reason and the grand illusion. J Conscious Stud 9:181–202

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2001) Elements of mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2003) The intentional structure of consciousness. In: Smith Q, Jokic A (eds) Consciousness: new philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 33–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick FC, Koch CA (2003) Framework for consciousness. Nat Neurosci 6:119–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (2000) Disorders of complex visual processing. In: Mesulam MM (ed) Principles of behavioral and cognitive neurology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 332–372

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene S, Naccache G, Le Clec H, Koechlin E (1998) Imaging unconscious semantic priming. Nature 395:597–600

    Google Scholar 

  • Delage Y (1919) La Rêve. Les Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1991) Consciousness explained. Little Brown, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1992) The self as a center of narrative gravity. In: Kessel F, Cole P, Johnson D (eds) Self and consciousness: multiple perspectives. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp 103–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2003) Who’s on first? Hetero-phenomenology explained. J Conscious Stud 10:19–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1641/1884–1891) Meditations on first philosophy. In: The philosophical writings of descartes, vol 2 (trans: Cottingham J, Stoothoff R, Murdoch D). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Dretske F (1995) Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1997) What good is consciousness? Can J Philos 27:1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (2003) How do you know you are not a zombie? In: Gertler B (ed) Privileged access and first person authority. Ashgate Publishing Limited, Aldershot, pp 1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman G (1989) The remembered present: a biological theory of consciousness. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Farthing WG (1992) The psychology of consciousness. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1984) The science of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1992) Consciousness reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Flohr H (1995) Sensations and brain processes. Behav Brain Res 71:157–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro RJ (2004) Higher-order theories of consciousness: an anthology. John Benjamins, Philadephia, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro RJ (2005) HOT theory between a rock and a hard place. J Conscious Stud 12:3–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro RJ (2006) Between pure self-referentialism and the (extrinsic) HOT theory of consciousness. In: Kriegel U, Williford K (eds) Consciousness and self-reference. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 221–248

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro R (2012) The consciousness paradox: consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Globus GG (1987) Dream life, wake life: the human condition through dreams. SUNY Press, Albany, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AJ (1970) A theory of human action. Prentice-Hall, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AJ (1993) Consciousness, folk psychology and cognitive science. Conscious Cogn 2:364–382

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AJ (1997) Consciousness, folk psychology and cognitive science. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Guzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 111–126. Reprinted from Conscious Cogn 2:364–382

  • Green C (1968) Lucid dreams. Hamish Hamilton, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Green C (1990) Waking dreams and other metachoric states. Psychiatr J Univ Ott 15:123–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Green C, McCreary C (1994) Lucid dreaming: the paradox of consciousness during sleep. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossberg S (1999) The link between brain learning, attention and consciousness. Conscious Cogn 8:1–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2004) The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery and perception. Behav Brain Sci 27:377–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch A (1950) Marginal consciousness. Ohio University Press, Athens, OH

  • Güzeldere G (1995) Problems of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 2:112–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1990) The intrinsic quality of experience. Philos Perspect 4:31–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Harth Eric (1993) The creative loop: how the brain makes a mind. Addisson-Wesley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson JA (1988) The dreaming brain. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739–1740) A treatise on human nature. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Husserl E (1931/1960) Cartesian meditations: an introduction to phenomenology (trans: Cairns D). Kluwer, Dortrecht

  • Jackendoff R (1987) Consciousness and the computational mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Janzen G (2006) The representational theory of phenomenal character: a phenomenological critique. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 5:321–339

    Google Scholar 

  • Janzen G (2008) The reflexive nature of consciousness. John Benjamins, Philadelphia, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird PN (1988) A computational analysis of consciousness. In: Marcel AJ, Bisiach E (eds) Consciousness in contemporary science. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 357–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan TL, LaBerge S (1994) Lucid dreaming as metacognition: implications for cognitive science. Conscious Cogn 3:246–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom JF (1993) The continuum of consciousness. Conscious Cogn 2:334–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind A (2001) Qualia realism. Philos Stud 104:143–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind A (2008) How to believe in qualia. In: Wright E (ed) The case for qualia. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 285–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne M (1997) What qualifies a representation for a role in consciousness? In: Cohen JD, Schooler JW (eds) Scientific approaches to consciousness. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp 335–355

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluwe RH (1987) Executive decisions and regulation of problem solving. In: Weinert F, Kluwe R (eds) Metacognition, motivation, and understanding. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp 31–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat A (2000) The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Conscious Cogn 9:149–171

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat A, Goldsmith M (1996) Monitoring and control process s in the strategic regulation of memory accuracy. Psychol Rev 103:490–517

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2002a) PANIC theory and the prospects for a representationalist theory of phenomenal consciousness. Philos Psychol 15:55–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2002b) Consciousness, permanent self-awareness, and higher-order monitoring. Dialogue 41:517–540

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2003) Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: two views and an argument. Can J Philos 33:103–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2004) Consciousness and self-consciousness. Monist 87:182–205

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2005) Naturalizing subjective character. Philos Phenomenol Res 71:23–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2007) A cross-order integration hypothesis for the neural correlate of consciousness. Conscious Cogn 16:897–912

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2009a) Self-representationalism and phenomenology. Philos Stud 142:357–381

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel U (2009b) Subjective consciousness: a self-representational theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunst-Wilson WR, Zajonc RB (1980) Affective discrimination of stimuli that cannot be recognized. Science 207:557–558

    Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge S (1985) Lucid dreaming. J.P. Tarcher, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge S (1988) The psychophysiology of lucid dreaming. In: Gackenbach J, LaBerge S (eds) Conscious mind sleeping brain. Plenum Press, New York, pp 135–153

    Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge S, DeGracia DJ (2000) Varieties of lucid dreaming experience. In: Kunzendorf RG, Wallace B (eds) Individual differences in conscious experience. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 269–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamme VA (2006) Towards a true neural stance on consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci 10:494–501

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux JE (1992) Emotion and the amygdala. In: Aggleton JP (ed) The amygdala: neurobiological aspects of emotion, memory, and mental dysfunction. Wiley-Liss, New York, pp 339–351

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (2001) Purple haze. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (2006) Conscious awareness and (self-)representation. In: Kriegel U, Williford K (eds) Self-representational approaches to consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 173–197

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet B (1985) Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behav Brain Sci 8:529–566

    Google Scholar 

  • Lurz R (2003) Advancing the debate between HOT and FO theories of consciousness. J Philos Res 27:25–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan W (1990) What is the ‘subjectivity’ of the mental? In: Tomberlin J (ed) Philosophical perspectives 4. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 109–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan W (1996) Consciousness and experience. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan W (2001) A simple argument for a higher order representation theory of consciousness. Analysis 61:3–4

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons W (1986) The disappearance of introspection. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyyra P (2009) Two senses for ‘givenness of consciousness’. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 8:67–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Mamelak AN, Hobson JA (1989) Dream bizarreness as the cognitive correlate of altered neural behavior in REM sleep. J Cogn Neurosci 3:201–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin MGF (2002) The transparency of experience. Mind Lang 4:376–425

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn C (1991) The problem of consciousness. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn C (1997) Missing the mind: consciousness in the swamps, review of Fred Dretske’s Naturalizing the Mind. Noûs 31:528–537

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele AR (2006) Free will and luck. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele AR (2008) Recent work on free will and science. Am Philos Q 45:107–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (1995a) The problem of consciousness. In: Metzinger T (ed) Conscious experience. Schoningh, Paderborn, pp 3–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (1995b) Faster than thought: holism, homogeneity and temporal coding. In: Metzinger T (ed) Conscious experience. Schoningh, Paderborn, pp 425–461

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2000) Subjectivity of subjective experience. In: Neural correlates of consciousness, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 285–306

  • Metzinger T (2003a) Being no one: the self-model theory of subjectivity. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

  • Metzinger T (2003b) Phenomenal transparency and cognitive self reference. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 2:353–393

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner D, Goodale M (1995) The visual brain in action. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1903) The refutation of idealism. In: Philosophical papers. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Reprinted in Mind 12:433–453

  • Nagel T (1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philos Rev 83:435–450

    Google Scholar 

  • Natsoulas T (1993) What’s wrong with appendage theory of consciousness. Philos Psychol 6:137–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Natsoulas T (1996) The case for intrinsic theory 1. J Mind Behav 17:267–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser JU (2006) Unconscious subjectivity. Psyche 12(3):1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin N (1995) The dissociation of phenomenal states from apperception. In: Metzinger T (ed) Conscious experience, Schoningh, Paderborn, pp 3–40

  • Nisbett RE, Wilson TD (1977) Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychol Rev 84:231–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2007) The critique of pure phenomenology. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6:231–245

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien G, Opie J (1999) A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience. Behav Brain Sci 22:127–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Pace M (2007) Blurred vision and the transparency of experience. Pac Philos Q 88:328–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlis D (1997) Consciousness as self-function. J Conscious Stud 4:509–525

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry J (1979) The problem of the essential indexical. Nous 3:3–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters F (2009) Consciousness and self-regulation. J Mind Behav 30:267–290

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters F (2010) Consciousness as recursive, spatiotemporal self location. Psychol Res PRPF 74:407–422

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters F (2013) Theories of consciousness as reflexivity. Philos Forum 44:341–372

    Google Scholar 

  • Polger T, Flanagan O (2002) Consciousness, adaptation and epiphenomenalism. In: Fetzer JH (ed) Consciousness evolving. John Benjamins, Philadelphia, PA, pp 21–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Proust J (2003) Thinking of oneself as the same. Conscious Cogn 12:495–509

    Google Scholar 

  • Reason J (1984) Lapses of attention in everyday life. In: Parasuraman R, Davies D, Beatty J (eds) Varieties of attention. Academic Press, NY, pp 515–549

    Google Scholar 

  • Rensink RA, O’Regan JK, Clark JJ (1997) To see or not to see: the need for attention to perceive changes in sciences. Psychol Sci 8:368–373

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo A (2006) Inner presence, consciousness as a biological phenomenon. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal D (1986) Two concepts of consciousness. Philos Stud 49:329–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal D (1993) Thinking that one thinks. In: Davies Martin, Humphries GlynW (eds) Consciousness: psychological and philosophical essays. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 197–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal D (1997) A theory of consciousness. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 729–754

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal D (2000) Consciousness and metacognition. In: Sperber D (ed) Metarepresentation: proceedings of the tenth Vancouver cognitive science conference. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal D (2005) Consciousness and mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlicht T (2011) Non-conceptual content and the subjectivity of consciousness. Int J Philos Stud 19:491–520

    Google Scholar 

  • Schooler JW (2002) Re-representing consciousness: dissociations between experience and meta-consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci 6:339–344

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel E (2007) No unchallengeable epistemic authority, of any sort, regarding our own conscious experience—Contra Dennett. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6:107–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel E (2008) The unreliability of naive introspection. Philos Rev 117:245–273

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1992) The rediscovery of the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1993) The problem of consciousness. Conscious Cogn 2:310–319

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2002) Consciousness and language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1968) Self-reference and self-awareness. J Philos 65:555–567

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1994) Self-knowledge and ‘‘inner sense’. Philos Phenomenol Res 54:249–314

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1996) The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith DW (1988) Rey cogitans: the unquestionability of consciousness. In: Otto H, Tueidio J (eds) Perspectives on mind. Kluwer Academic, Norwell, pp 25–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith DW (1989) The circle of acquaintance. Kluwer, Dortecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith DW (2004) Return to consciousness. In: Smith DW (ed) Mind world: essays in phenomenology and ontology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 76–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies D, Stoljar E (2012) Introspection and consciousness: an overview. In: Smithies D, Stoljar E (eds) Introspection and consciousness. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 3–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubenberg L (1998) Consciousness and qualia. John Benjamins, Philadelphia, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson A (2000) After Brentano: a one-level theory of consciousness. Eur J Philos 8:194–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2007) Look again: phenomenology and mental imagery. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6:137–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi G (1998) Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto. Biol Bull 215:216-242

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi G, Edelman GM (1998) Consciousness and complexity. Science 282:1846–1851

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi G, Koch C (2008) The neural correlates of consciousness: an update. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1124:239–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (1995) Ten problems of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Underwood G (1990) Conscious and unconscious representation of aspectual shape in cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 13:628–629

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick R (2001) Inward and upward: reflection, introspection, and self-awareness. Philos Top 28:275–305

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick R (2004) Higher-order global states (HOGS): an alternative higher-order model of consciousness. In: Gennaro RJ (ed) Higher order theories of consciousness: an anthology. John Benjamins, Philadelphia, PA, pp 67–92

  • Velmans M (1991) Is human information processing conscious? Behav Brain Sci 14:651–726

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick R (2006) Mirror, mirror—is that all? In: Kriegel U, Williford K (eds) Self-representational approaches to consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 11–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner D (2002) The illusion of conscious will. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg J (1999) Active, thin and hot! An actualist response to Carruthers’ dispositionalist HOT view. Psyche 5(6):1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg J (2005) Consciousness constrained. Psyche 11(5):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg J (2008) Same old, same old: the same-order representation theory of consciousness and the division of phenomenal labor. Synthese 160:161–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D, Parnas J (1998) Phenomenal consciousness and self-awareness: a phenomenological critique of representational theory. J Conscious Stud 5:687–705

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (1999) Self-awareness and alterity: a phenomenological investigation. Northwestern Univeristy Press, Evanston, IL

  • Zahavi D (2004) Back to Brentano? J Conscious Stud 11:66–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2005a) Subjectivity and selfhood. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

  • Zahavi D (2005b) Being someone. Psyche 11(5):1–20

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frederic Peters.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Peters, F. Accounting for Consciousness: Epistemic and Operational Issues. Axiomathes 24, 441–461 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-014-9232-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-014-9232-0

Keywords

Navigation