Skip to main content
Log in

On the Norms of Visual Argument: A Case for Normative Non-revisionism

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Visual arguments can seem to require unique, autonomous evaluative norms, since their content seems irreducible to, and incommensurable with, that of verbal arguments. Yet, assertions of the ineffability of the visual, or of visual-verbal incommensurability, seem to preclude counting putatively irreducible visual content as functioning argumentatively. By distinguishing two notions of content, informational and argumentative, I contend that arguments differing in informational content can have equivalent argumentative content, allowing the same argumentative norms to be rightly applied in their evaluation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Following Dove (2011: 4) I will take a visual argument to be “any argument in which at least one of the elements is conveyed visually” (cf. Blair 2015: 218). As such, included in the category of visual arguments, as they are discussed in the paper, are arguments of mixed-modality, or multimodal arguments, where at least one of the elements of the argument is conveyed visually.

  2. Here I employ, with a neutral connotation, the language of the “innovation lifecycle”—a sociological model intended to map the adoption of some change (frequently technological) within some group. The model, known as the diffusion process (Bohlen and Beal 1957; Beal et al. 1957; Rogers 1962), postulates that the acceptance of some change, or the adoption of some innovation, within a population typically occurs according to a normal distribution that can be divided into the following rough groups in order of adoption: enthusiasts (innovators), visionaries (early adopters), pragmatists (early majority), conservatives (late majority), and skeptics (laggards). Here I adapt the use of these terms to group argumentation theorists according to their relative acceptance of visual arguments.

  3. See “Appendix 1” for a proof that there are visual arguments.

    • On this last point, consider, for example, the following silent exchange between two parties, Pro and Resp.

    • Pro: points to Resp and then to the door

    • Resp: shakes his head and raises his hands, palms-up, in an upward, shrugging motion

    • Pro: points to her watch

    • Resp: raises an eyebrow and shrugs again

    • Pro: holds up a pair of tickets from the mantle

    • Resp: smacks forehead with palm, grabs the tickets from Pro and rushes to the door.

  4. Birdsell and Groarke (1996: 9) identified a series of tasks that must be met by any theory of visual argument:

    any account of visual argument must identify how we can (a) identify the internal elements of a visual image (b) understand the contexts in which images are interpreted (c) establish the consistency of an interpretation of the visual, and (d) chart changes in visual perspectives over time.

    Importantly, all of these are interpretative tasks relating to the identification and analysis of images, rather than anything related to their evaluation as arguments. Nor were any such items added in their revised agenda (Birdsell and Groarke 2007). It would seem, then, that Birdsell and Groarke found the evaluative apparatus to be already in place.

  5. Additionally, Blair (2015) agrees (at least in part) with my reading of Groarke as a normative non-revisionist. He (2015: 219) writes:

    Groarke, in (1996: 114), argued that visual arguments can be held to the same standards as verbal arguments. At the time, … his point was that there is no need for special dispensation for visual arguments—that no different standards are needed to admit visual arguments into the fold. … In today’s light, Groarke’s point can be seen as asserting that the probative standards (or criteria) that apply to verbal arguments may be applied equally to visual arguments, but not as denying that there might also be other probative standards that are unique to visual arguments.

    In the last phrase, Blair leaves open the possibility of a normative revisionism in Groarke’s position, saying that Groarke’s position does not commit Groarke to denying the possibility of probative standards unique to visual arguments.

  6. The source (Johnson 2010) is an unpublished conference paper that the author has graciously made available to me and permitted me to quote from.

  7. Gilbert’s (1994, 1997) work on multi-modal argumentation does not take a position on whether the visual counts as a mode of argument. Recent correspondence confirms that, while multi-modal argumentation is intended to be open to such a possibility, Gilbert has not taken a position on this question.

  8. See “Appendix 2” for a brief discussion of the nature of argument modality.

  9. In identifying these as modes, Gilbert applies the concept of modality differently from the way it is applied in media, communication, and visual studies, where “mode” denotes a form of expression, and where, e.g., emotional and intuitive would not be considered modes.

  10. The question of whether the same argument can be presented in different modes, say visual and verbal, is discussed later in Sects. 5 and 8.

  11. Generally, the kinds of things to be held constant include everything but the specific presentational mode, e.g., the argumentative content and facts of the argumentative situation. Recognizing that there are practical limitations on the extent to which such factors can actually be held constant, it is not unreasonable to suppose that controlling for them is practically feasible at least to the extent that one could effectively experimentally test to see whether the modality of an argument made a difference to its rhetorical or probative effect on some audience. And, the limits of the “ceteris paribus” constraint cut both ways in the debate between normative equivalentists and normative non-equivalentists. The success of either case depends on our being able to hold other factors effectively constant.

  12. Without knowing whether there actually are any self-avowed normative revisionists, this section will be speculative, seeking to articulate a set of folk assumptions and intuitions that might incline one towards a revisionist view, rather than to descriptively characterize anyone’s position. More generally, it is not relevant to the argument of the paper whether anyone actually subscribes to normative revisionism, the autonomy thesis, or the normative independence of the visual. Rather, what is important is that they are positions, with some apparent plausibility, within the spectrum of views one might take on the question of the relation between visual and non-visual (e.g., verbal) argumentation.

  13. I prefer the view that arguments are linguistic, rather than cognitive, artifacts (Godden 2015b). Such a view needn’t commit one to the textuality of language, but it does provide what seems to me to be adequate resources for explaining the meaning, including the argumentative meaning, of images and words alike (see Groarke 2014).

  14. This last point is important, since there is no reason to assume that we are especially reliable introspective reporters on the kinds of cognitive processes (broadly understood) that occur when we process visual information. For example, although we are typically particularly able to recognize and distinguish human faces, as well as facial expressions, our ability to do so is not a good reason for thinking that we have any good insight into, or explanation for, how we do so. I may be able to reliably make such distinctions without being able to report (whether reliably or at all) on, for example, which visual features I am processing and tracking in making these distinctions reliably. Yet, it does not follow from my inability to report on this that I am not processing, tracking, and distinguishing particular features which are articulable even if not by me.

  15. Importantly, neither the syntactic nor semantic conditions exclude non-linguistic information. Floridi (2010: 20–21) writes:

    ‘[W]ell formed’ means that the data are rightly put together, according to the rules (syntax) that govern the chosen system, code, or language being used. Syntax here must be understood broadly, not just linguistically, as what determines the form, construction, composition, or structuring of something. … ‘Meaningful’ means that the data must comply with the meanings (semantics) of the chosen system, code, or language in question. Once again, semantic information is not necessarily linguistic.

    Floridi offers an example of illustrations in the instruction manual for a car having a “pictorial syntax” and semantics (Floridi 2010: 21).

  16. Note: The contention of the paper is that information properly explains the nature and content of visual artifacts (e.g., images), understood as objects of visual experience—not the nature or content of the experiences of visual objects. The paper does not contend that information (or being informed) properly characterizes the rhetorical effect or phenomenological, lived quality of experience of the object-as-experienced.

  17. This is not to conflate the difference between saying (which collections of words do when uttered or written) and showing, or depicting, (which images do when presented or displayed). Rather, than resting on an identification of two presentational modalities, saying and showing, it relies on an identification of what is said with what is shown—i.e., of content.

References

  • Adriaans, P. 2012. Information. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 edn), ed. E. Zalta, 1–56. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/information.

  • Barceló-Aspeitia, A. 2012. Words and images in argumentation. Argumentation 26: 355–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and J. Etchemendy. 1996. Visual information and valid reasoning. In Logical reasoning with diagrams, ed. G. Allwein, and J. Barwise, 3–25. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and E. Hammer. 1996. Diagrams and the concept of logical system. In Logical reasoning with diagrams, ed. G. Allwein, and J. Barwise, 49–78. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. 1973. Steps to an ecology of mind. Frogmore, At. Albans: Paladin.

  • Beal, G., E. Rogers, and J. Bohlen. 1957. Validity of the concept of stages in the adoption process. Rural Sociology 22: 166–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birdsell, D., and L. Groarke. 1996. Toward a theory of visual argument. Argumentation and Advocacy 33: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birdsell, D., and L. Groarke. 2007. Outlines of a theory of visual argument. Argumentation and Advocacy 43: 103–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J.A. 1996. The possibility and actuality of visual arguments. Argumentation and Advocacy 33: 23–39. Reprinted in J.A. Blair, Groundwork in the theory of argumentation, 205–223. Amsterdam: Springer (2012).

  • Blair, J.A. 2004. The rhetoric of visual arguments. In Defining visual rhetorics, ed. C.A. Hill, and M. Helmers, 41–61. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Reprinted in J.A. Blair, Groundwork in the theory of argumentation, 261–279. Amsterdam: Springer (2012).

  • Blair, J.A. 2015. Probative norms for multimodal visual arguments. Argumentation 29: 217–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohlen, J. and G. Beal. 1957. The diffusion process. Special Report No. 18 (Agriculture Extension Service, Iowa State College) 1: 56–77. http://www.soc.iastate.edu/extension/pub/comm/SP18.pdf.

  • Brandom, R. 2000. Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. 1988. Rationality. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. 1997. Proofs and pictures. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47: 161–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. 2008. Philosophy of mathematics: A contemporary introduction to the world of proofs and pictures, 2nd ed. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dove, I. 2002. Can pictures prove? Logique et Analyse 179–180: 309–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dove, I. 2011. Visual analogies and arguments. In Argumentation: Cognition and community: Proceedings of the 9th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18–21, 2011, CD ROM, ed. F. Zenker et al., 1–16. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Dove, I. 2012. On images as evidence and arguments. In Topical themes in argumentation theory: Twenty exploratory studies, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and B. Garssen, 223–238. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dove, I. 2013. Visual arguments and meta-arguments. In Virtues of argumentation. Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013, CD ROM, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński, 1–15. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Dove, I. 2016. Visual scheming: Assessing visual arguments. Argumentation and Advocacy 52: 254–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, P. 2000. Introduction: The varieties of belief and acceptance. In Believing and accepting, ed. P. Engel, 1–30. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, D. 1996. Can pictures be arguments? Argumentation and Advocacy 33: 105–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2003. Two approaches to the philosophy of information. Minds and Machines 13: 459–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2005. Is semantic information meaningful data? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2010. Information: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2011. The philosophy of information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. 1994. Multi-modal argumentation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24: 159–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. 1997. Coalescent argumentation. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2004. Arguing at cross-purposes: Discharging the dialectical obligations of the coalescent model of argumentation. Argumentation 17: 219–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2010. The importance of belief in argumentation: Belief, commitment and the effective resolution of a difference of opinion. Synthese 172: 397–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2013. On the norms of visual argument. In Virtues of argumentation. In Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013, CD ROM, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński, 1–13. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Godden, D. 2014. Teaching rational entitlement and responsibility: A Socratic exercise. Informal Logic, Teaching Supplement 34: 124–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2015a. Argumentation, rationality, and psychology of reasoning. Informal Logic 35: 135–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2015b. Images as arguments: Progress and problems, a brief commentary. Argumentation 29: 235–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2015c. On the priority of agent-based argumentative norms. Topoi: An International Review of Philosophy. doi: 10.1007/s11245-014-9296-x.

  • Godden, D. 2016. Visual argument: Content, commensurability, and cogency. In Argumentation and reasoned action: Proceedings of the first European Conference on Argumentation, Lisbon, 9-12 June 2015, vol. II, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński.

  • Govier, T. 2005. A practical study of argument, 6th ed. Toronto: Thompson-Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. 1996. Logic, art and argument. Informal Logic 18: 105–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. 2002. Toward a pragma-dialectics of visual argument. In Advances in pragma-dialectics, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, 137–151. Amsterdam: SicSat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. 2003. Commentary on R. Johnson’s “Why ‘visual arguments’ aren’t arguments.” In Informal logic at 25: Proceedings of the windsor conference, CD-ROM, ed. J.A. Blair et al., 1–4. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Groarke, L. 2007. Beyond words: Two dogmas of informal logic. In Reason reclaimed: Essays in honor of J. Anthony Blair and Ralph Johnson, ed. H.V. Hansen, and R.C. Pinto, 135–152. Newport News, VA: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. 2009. Commentary on G. Roque’s “What is visual in visual argumentation?” In Argument cultures: Proceedings of the 8th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), CD-ROM, ed. J. Ritola, 1-3. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Groarke, L. 2013. On Dove, visual evidence and verbal repackaging. In Virtues of argumentation. In Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński, 1–8. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Groarke, L. 2014. Visual argument, Wittgenstein and Patterson: How to do things without words. In International Society for the Study of Argumentation (ISSA), 8th International Conference on Argumentation, at the University of Amsterdam, the Netherlands, July 1–4, 2014.

  • Groarke, L. 2015. Going multimodal: What is a mode of arguing and why does it matter? Argumentation 29: 133–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L., and C. Tindale. 2012. Good reasoning matters!, 5th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L., C.H. Palczewski, and D. Godden. 2016. Navigating the visual turn in argument. Argumentation and Advocacy 52: 217–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guarini, M. 2011. Commentary on Ian Dove’s “Visual analogies and arguments.” In Argumentation: Cognition and community: Proceedings of the 9th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18–21, 2011, CD ROM, ed. F. Zenker et al., 1–5. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Hesse, D. 1992. Aristotle’s Poetics and Rhetoric: Narrative as rhetoric’s fourth mode. In Rebirth of rhetoric: Essays in language, culture, and education, ed. R. Andrews, 19–38. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammer, E., and N. Danner. 1996. Towards a model theory of Venn diagrams. In Logical reasoning with diagrams, ed. G. Allwein, and J. Barwise, 109–127. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R.H. 2003. Why “visual arguments” aren’t arguments. In Informal logic at 25: Proceedings of the Windsor conference, CD-ROM, ed. J.A. Blair et al., 1–13. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Johnson, R.H. 2010. On the evaluation of visual arguments: Roque and the autonomy thesis. [Unpublished conference paper, presented to] Persuasion et argumentation: Colloque international organisé par le CRAL à l’Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, 105 Bd. Raspail, 75006 Paris, Salle 7, 7–9 Septembre 2010.

  • Johnson, R., and J.A. Blair. 1994. Logical self-defense, 3rd ed. Toronto: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., and A. Varzi. 2000. Some pictures are worth 2ℵ0 sentences. Philosophy 75: 377–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, J. 2012. Pictorial argumentation in advertising: Visual tropes and figures as a way of creating visual argumentation. In Topical themes in argumentation theory: Twenty exploratory studies, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and B. Garssen, 239–255. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, J. 2013. Virtues of visual argumentation. In Virtues of argumentation. Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013, CD ROM, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński, 1–13. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Kjeldsen, J. 2015a. The rhetoric of thick representation: How pictures render the importance and strength of an argument salient. Argumentation 29: 197–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, J. 2015b. The study of visual and multimodal argumentation. Argumentation 29: 115–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, J. 2015c. Where is visual argument? In Reflections on theoretical issues in argumentation theory, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and B. Garssen, 107–117. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lake, R., and B. Pickering. 1998. Argumentation, the visual, and the possibility of refutation: An exploration. Argumentation 12: 79–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, S. 2005. More than pictures? An exploration of visually dominant magazine ads as arguments. Journal of Visual Literacy 25: 145–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumma, J. 2010. Proofs, pictures, and Euclid. Synthese 175: 255–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, D.J. 1977. Two concepts of argument. Journal of the American Forensic Association 13: 121–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, S. 2010. “A picture held us captive”: The later Wittgenstein on visual argumentation. Cogency 2: 105–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R.C. 2006. Evaluating inferences: The nature and role of warrants. Informal Logic 26: 287–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R.C. 2009. Argumentation and the force of reasons. Informal Logic 29: 268–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, E. 1962. Diffusion of innovations. Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roque, G. 2009. What is visual in visual argumentation? In Argument Cultures: Proceedings of the 8th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), CD-ROM, ed. J. Ritola, 1–9. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Roque, G. 2012. Visual argumentation: A further reappraisal. In Topical themes in argumentation theory: Twenty exploratory studies, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and B. Garssen, 273–288. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roque, G. 2015. Should visual arguments be propositional in order to be arguments? Argumentation 29: 177–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. 1988. Educating reason: Rationality, critical thinking and education. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality redeemed: Further dialogues on an educational ideal. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. 2004. Rationality and judgment. Metaphilosophy 35: 597–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shin, S.-J. 1996. Situation-theoretic account of valid reasoning with Venn diagrams. In Logical reasoning with diagrams, ed. G. Allwein, and J. Barwise, 81–108. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tseronis, A. 2013. Argumentative functions of visuals: Beyond claiming and justifying. In Virtues of argumentation. In Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013, CD ROM, ed. D. Mohammed, and M. Lewiński, 1–17. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Van den Hoven, P. 2011. The story behind the plot: About the propositionality of visually presented argumentation. In Argumentation: Cognition and community: Proceedings of the 9th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18–21, 2011, CD ROM, ed. F. Zenker et al., 1–8. Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Van den Hoven, P. 2015. Cognitive semiotics in argumentation: A theoretical exploration. Argumentation 29: 157–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., C. Reed, and F. Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Willard, C. 1989. A theory of argumentation. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Excerpts from previous versions of this paper were presented at: (1) Virtues of Argumentation, Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA) 10, on May 24, 2013, at the University of Windsor in Ontario, Canada, under the title “On the norms of visual argument,” and (2) Argumentation and Reasoned Action, 1st European Conference on Argumentation (ECA), on June 11, 2015 at the Universidade Nova de Lisboa, in Lisbon, Portugal, under the title “Visual argument: Content, commensurability, and cogency.” Each paper subsequently appeared in the conference proceedings (Godden 2013, 2016). Research and travel for each paper presentation was supported by Old Dominion University (ODU), in Norfolk, Virginia; the first paper was further supported by a Summer Research Fellowship Program grant from ODU’s Office of Research. The present paper was supported by a Faculty Summer Fellowship Program grant from the College of Arts and Letters at Michigan State University. Other than from audience feedback at these events, the paper has benefitted from exchanges with several others who deserve my recognition and thanks. First among these is J. Anthony Blair whose pioneering work in the informal logic of visual argumentation exhibits an incisiveness, acuity, and lucidity that should serve as a beacon to all working in the field. My intellectual debt to him is vast, and his influence on my thinking, I trust, readily apparent. Second is Ian Dove, whose generous and insightful comments on the OSSA presentation (Dove 2013), as well as our extensive subsequent discussions, were invaluable to me in formulating the position I offer in the paper. I am also indebted to Ian for making me aware of several pivotal sources (e.g., Kitcher and Varzi 2000), and for his ever expanding repertoire acutely incisive conceptualizations and examples, which should be of value to any theorist hoping to come to terms with the subject area. Next is Jens Kjeldsen, first for his conversations and extensive published work which have been especially informative to my own work and thinking, and secondly for the opportunity he afforded me by inviting a commentary, “Images as arguments: Progress and problems, a brief commentary,” (Godden 2015b) on the special issue of Argumentation he guest-edited (Kjeldsen 2015b), which allowed me to formulate and crystalize some of the ideas articulated in this paper. Also deserving of my special thanks are Leo Groarke and Catherine Palczewski, my co-editors of a special issue of Argumentation and Advocacy, “Twenty Years of Visual Argument,” 2016, volume 52(4), pp. 217–299 (Groarke et al. 2016). In addition to the extensive and groundbreaking contributions to the literature made by each of my co-editors, our discussions throughout the editorial project were an invaluable source of knowledge, perspective, and inspiration for me. And nor should I forget Robyn Bluhm, who put(s) up with a lot of ramblings from the author. Finally, I am indebted to the anonymous referees who reviewed the paper for their insightful and constructive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Godden.

Appendices

Appendix 1: A Proof that There are Visual Arguments

1.1 Proof

P1    Categorical syllogisms are arguments.

P2    Categorical syllogisms can be expressed by Venn diagrams.

P3    Venn diagrams are visual images.

∴C    Some visual images express arguments.

1.2 Reply to an Anticipated Objection

To those inclined to respond that images can only express, rather than be arguments, consider the analogous argument:

P1    Categorical syllogisms are arguments.

P2    Categorical syllogisms can be expressed by sets of sentences.

∴C    Some sets of sentences express arguments.

Consequently, in whatever sense sentences can be syllogistic arguments, so too can images.

1.3 Discussion

There is considerable debate about whether mathematical diagrams constitute proofs (i.e., arguments of a kind) or whether they are merely ancillary to proofs which, properly conceived, are ordered sequences of sentences or formulae where the initial items on the list are given as axioms or premises, the remainder of which are theorems derived by rules of inference from items higher up on the list, and where the last item in the sequence is the conclusion (Barwise and Etchemendy 1996; Brown 1997, 2008; Dove 2002). The work of Shin (1996) and Hammer and Danner (1996) demonstrates that Venn diagrams can be operationalized as a logical system, understood as “a mathematical model [either semantic or proof theoretic] of some pretheoretic notion of consequence and an existing (or possible) inferential practice that honors it” (Barwise and Hammer 1996: 51). That is, the basic diagrammatic elements of Venn diagrams can be provided with a syntax, semantics, and system of derivation rules such that Venn diagrams can be rigorously and unambiguously interpreted as expressively equivalent to sequences of lines in a syllogistic proof. If successful, this conclusively demonstrates that Venn diagrams are arguments if syllogisms are. Mumma (2010) provides a similarly rigorous interpretation of the diagrams in Euclid’s Elements, in an effort to establish that they too function demonstratively, rather than merely instrumentally as heuristic or illustrative devices. See also Dove (2013: 8–9) for a visual, diagrammatic refutation of the transitivity of the quantifier “most,” and (9–14) for a diagrammatic map that provides a Heawood counter-model to Kempe’s four-color theorem about the minimum number of different colors required to shade any planar map such that no bordering regions will have the same color.

The point here, I take it, is not that such a rigorous interpretive system is a requirement for something’s being an argument. Rather, the point is that whatever standards of meaningfulness we require in order that something rightly be interpreted as an argument, those conditions can be met by images when they are supplied with an appropriate context of use. More generally then, as Groarke (2014) argues, meaning is a function of use, and images, when used in the right sorts of ways, can take on meaning such that they can function argumentatively (cf. Lake and Pickering 1998; Barceló-Aspeitia 2012; Tseronis 2013). And most importantly, the meaningfulness and argumentative function of images is to be explained in exactly the same way as the meaningfulness and argumentative function of words. When embedded in an appropriate system and practice of use, images become linguistic elements just as phonemes and graphemes do.

Appendix 2: On the Nature of Argument Modality

Section 3.2.2 characterizes the modality of an argument as its presentational manner, such that modes are distinguished not on the basis of content but according to the manner in which some content is presented. Blair (2015: 218; emphasis added) adopts a similar idea whereby the modal categorization of an argument designates “the manner in which the argument is expressed or communicated.” By contrast, Groarke (2015: 140, 143; emphasis added) proposes an account that “define[s] modes in terms of the ingredients (the ‘material’, the ‘stuff’) an arguer uses and arranges when they engage in an act of arguing,” such that “[t]o see if an act of arguing is an instance of a particular mode it is enough to check whether it is built from ingredients that define the mode.”

Given its centrality in theories of multi-modal argumentation, there is a pressing need to articulate a workable and agreeable concept of an argumentative mode. Of the two views just considered, despite their difference in focus on adverbial qualities of argumentative acts (presentational manners) versus noun-categories of argument components (material ingredients), the views are similar in that each directs us to consider by what means the arguer is arguing when determining the mode of argument. I recommend an account that permits the distinction of function, content, and mode. Functionally speaking, arguments are all built from the same stuff. Arguments are composed not of images, nor even of words, but of claims and reasons (Godden 2015b: 237). As Blair (2015: 232) writes: “Arguments are not themselves verbal or visual.” Whatever reasons are built out of, it is a condition of their being a reason that they be able to function as such. Thus, the modality of a reason cannot interfere with its functionality as a reason; similarly with claims. Further, in order to retain the possibility that the same argumentative content (whether claim or reason) might occur in a variety of different modes, I suggest that there is an advantage in identifying reasons and claims by their content. Rather than a noun-category, the modality of a claim or reason could then be either an adjectival property of the artifact (i.e., its manner of presentation), or an adverbial property of the presentational act. This would allow claims and reasons to be identified by their content and categorized by their mode in a way consistent with Groarke’s (2015: 135ff.) key component tables.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Godden, D. On the Norms of Visual Argument: A Case for Normative Non-revisionism. Argumentation 31, 395–431 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9411-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9411-9

Keywords

Navigation