Skip to main content
Log in

Interpretative Disputes, Explicatures, and Argumentative Reasoning

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The problem of establishing the best interpretation of a speech act is of fundamental importance in argumentation and communication in general. A party in a dialogue can interpret another’s or his own speech acts in the most convenient ways to achieve his dialogical goals. In defamation law this phenomenon becomes particularly important, as the dialogical effects of a communicative move may result in legal consequences. The purpose of this paper is to combine the instruments provided by argumentation theory with the advances in pragmatics in order to propose an argumentative approach to meaning reconstruction. This theoretical proposal will be applied to and tested against defamation cases at common law. Interpretation is represented as based on a hierarchy of interpretative presumptions. On this view, the development of the logical form of an utterance is regarded as the result of an abductive pattern of reasoning in which various types of presumptions are confronted and the weakest ones are excluded. Conflicts of interpretations and equivocation become essentially interwoven with the dialectical problem of fulfilling the burden of defeating a presumption. The interpreter has a burden of explaining why a given presumption is subject to default, assuming that the speaker is reasonable and acting based on a set of shared expectations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the letter of recommendation used by Grice, the writer is implicating that the candidate is not suitable for the job in question. The letter does not provide the relevant pieces of information concerning the candidate’s lecturing, research, supervising, and administrative abilities. This information is absent in the letter, which dwells on a quality that is not indispensable. Capone (2006) believes that the absence of the relevant elements that are conventionally associated with the frame of writing recommendation letters creates an implicature that is not cancellable. Clearly, the non-cancellability depends on the context. In a different context (for example, in case the letter is for a job as a secretary), the aforementioned letter could actually work as an act of recommendation (Seymour 2013). In this sense, we cannot evaluate cancellability independently from the context (Capone 2006, 2013). Whereas the pragmatic meaning might be different in different contexts, in a particular context an inference (such as the one triggered by the recommendation letter) cannot be withdrawn or cancelled.

  2. A recent Italian judgment has decreed that even non-explicit (or non-fully explicit) defamatory utterances published through Facebook are actionable (see Tribunale di Livorno, Judgment no. 38912 of 31 December 2012).

  3. http://www.cspinet.org/new/200508112.html (retrieved on May 16th, 2014).

References

  • Agerri, Rodrigo, and Kepa Korta. 2004. Pragmatically determined aspects of meaning; explicature, impliciture or implicature. Ms. ILCLI & UPV-EHU Donostia.

  • Aquinas, Thomas. 2003. On evil. Richard Regan, trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1995).Topics. Translated by Willam Pickard-Cambridge. In The works of Aristotle, vol. I, ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Aston, William. 2000. Illocutionary acts and sentence meaning. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay, and Stephen Levinson. 1981. It-clefts, informativeness and logical form: Radical pragmatics (revised standard version). In Radical pragmatics, ed. Peter Cole, 1–62. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout, Anne. 1997. Pragmatics, semantic underdetermination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind 106(423): 375–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair Edlow, Robert. 1977. Galen on language and ambiguity. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1998a. Action, norms, and practical reasoning. Noûs 32: 127–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1998b. Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton-Roberts, Noel. 2006. Cancellation and intention. Newcastle Working Papers in Linguistics 12–13: 1–12.

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2006. On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics 38: 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2009. Are explicatures cancellable? Toward a theory of the speaker’s intentionality. Intercultural Pragmatics 6(1): 55–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2010. On the social practice of indirect reports (further advances in the theory of pragmemes). Journal of Pragmatics 42: 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2011. The attributive/referential distinction, pragmatics, modularity of mind and modularization. Australian Journal of Linguistics 31(2): 153–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2013. Explicatures are NOT Cancellable. In Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics, perspectives in pragmatics philosophy and psychology, vol. 2, ed. Alessandro Capone, Franco Lo Piparo, and Marco Carapezza, 131–151. Amsterdam: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. Forthcoming.The role of pragmatics in (re)constructing the rational law-maker. Pragmatics and Cognition (Accepted).

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2013. Legal texts and canons of construction. A view from current pragmatic theory. In Law and language: Current legal issues, ed. Michael Freeman, and Fiona Smith, 8–34. Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Herbert. 1996. Using language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohn, David. 1993. The problem of indirect defamation: Omission of material facts, implication, and innuendo. The University of Chicago Legal Forum 233–254.

  • Deppermann, Arnulf. 2000. Semantic shifts in argumentative processes: A step beyond the ‘fallacy of equivocation’. Argumentation 14(1): 17–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, Laurence. 1966. The Spurious Rule of Libel Per Quod. Harvard Law Review 79: 733–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, Morris. 1980. Analyzing informal fallacies. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, Marc, and Daniel Bussel. 1984. The Plaintiff’s burden in defamation: Awareness and falsity. William and Mary Law Review 25(5): 825–889.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and Conversation. In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, ed. Peter Cole, and Jerry Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, Charles. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horton, Tammy. 1986. Defamation: Mouthpiece libel claim fails to speak for itself. Loyola Entertainment Law Review 6: 161–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ifantidou, Elly. 2001. Evidentials and relevance. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, Katarzyna. 1999. Discourse, beliefs and intentions. Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F. (1995). On the difference between assumptions and presumptions. In Argumentation and values: Proceedings of the Ninth SCA/AFA Conference on Argumentation, ed. Jackson Sally, 509–514. Annandale, VA: Speech Communication Association.

  • Kauffeld, Fred. 2003. The ordinary practice of presuming and presumption with special attention to veracity and the burden of proof. In Anyone who has a view: Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation, ed. Frans van Eemeren, Anthony Blair, Charles Willard, and Francisca Snoek Henkemans, 136–146. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, Erik. 2003. Metadialogues. In Anyone who has a view: Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation, ed. Frans van Eemeren, Anthony Blair, Charles Willard, and Francisca Snoek Henkemans, 83–90. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lascarides, Alex, Ann Copestake, and Ted Briscoe. 1996. Ambiguity and coherence. Journal of Semantics 13: 41–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen. 2000. Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, Fabrizio. 2011. The presumptions of meaning. Hamblin and equivocation. Informal Logic 31(4): 367–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, Fabrizio. 2012. Presumptive reasoning in interpretation. Implicatures and conflicts of presumptions. Argumentation 26(2): 233–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, Fabrizio, and Douglas Walton. 2013. Implicatures as forms of argument. In Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy, ed. Alessandro Capone, Franco Lo Piparo, and Marco Carapezza, 203–225. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, Fabrizio, and Douglas Walton. 2014. Emotive language in argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, Fabrizio, and Benedetta Zavatta. 2014. Reconstructing metaphorical meaning. Argumentation 28(4): 453–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Jim. 1988. Distinguo: The response to equivocation. Argumentation 2: 465–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, Dennis. 2004. Interpretation in law. Diritto e questioni pubbliche 4: 241–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platts, Mark. 1997. Ways of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 2001. Rationality in action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, Michel. 2013. Speech act pluralism, minimal content and pragmemes. In Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy, ed. Alessandro Capone, Franco Lo Piparo, and Marco Carapezza, 245–277. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shuy, Roger W. 2005. Creating Language Crimes. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Shuy, Roger W. 2010. The Language of Defamation Cases. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson. 1986. Relevance theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 2002. Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stati, Sorin. 2002. Principi di analisi argomentativa. Patron editore: Bologna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stati, Sorin. 2013. Implicit propositions in an argumentative approach. In Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics, ed. Alessandro Capone, Franco LoPiparo, and Marco Carapezza, 433–443. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans, and Rob Grootendorst. 1984. Speech acts in argumentative discussions: A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans, and Rob Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication and fallacies. Hillsdale NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans, and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Laar, Jan Albert. 2001. Ambiguity in a dialectical perspective. Informal Logic 21(3): 245–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Laar, Jan Albert. 2003. The dialectic of ambiguity. Ph.D. Dissertation, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen.

  • Vanderveken, Daniel. 1990. Meaning and speech acts. Principles of language use, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas. 1996. Fallacies arising from ambiguity. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas, and Erik Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas, Chris Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabrizio Macagno.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Macagno, F., Capone, A. Interpretative Disputes, Explicatures, and Argumentative Reasoning. Argumentation 30, 399–422 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-015-9347-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-015-9347-5

Keywords

Navigation