Skip to main content
Log in

Diversification preferences in the theory of choice

  • Published:
Decisions in Economics and Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Diversification represents the idea of choosing variety over uniformity. Within the theory of choice, desirability of diversification is axiomatized as preference for a convex combination of choices that are equivalently ranked. This corresponds to the notion of risk aversion when one assumes the von Neumann–Morgenstern expected utility model, but the equivalence fails to hold in other models. This paper analyzes axiomatizations of the concept of diversification and their relationship to the related notions of risk aversion and convex preferences within different choice theoretic models. Implications of these notions on portfolio choice are discussed. We cover model-independent diversification preferences, preferences within models of choice under risk, including expected utility theory and the more general rank-dependent expected utility theory, as well as models of choice under uncertainty axiomatized via Choquet expected utility theory. Remarks on interpretations of diversification preferences within models of behavioral choice are given in the conclusion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To see this, suppose u is a concave utility function representing a convex preference relation \(\succsim \). Then, if a function \(f:\mathbb {R}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is strictly increasing, the composite function \(f\circ u\) is another utility representation of \(\succsim \). However, for a given concave utility function u, one can relatively easily construct a strictly increasing function f such that \(f\circ u\) is not concave.

  2. “Diversification is both observed and sensible; a rule of behavior which does not imply the superiority of diversification must be rejected.”

  3. Drapeau and Kupper (2013) refer to the convexity property as quasiconvexity, which we believe is a mathematically more appropriate nomenclature. However, we stick to the more widely used convexity terminology for consistency.

  4. This definition of tail mean holds only under the assumption of continuous distributions, that is for integrable x.

  5. A risk measure \(\rho :\mathcal {X}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is convex if for all \(x,y\in \mathcal {X}\) and \(\lambda \in [0,1], \rho (\lambda x +(1-\lambda )y) \le \lambda \rho (x) +(1-\lambda )\rho (y)\).

  6. A risk measure \(\rho :\mathcal {X}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is subadditive if for all \(x,y\in \mathcal {X}, \rho (x+y) \le \rho (x)+\rho (y)\).

  7. A risk measure \(\rho :\mathcal {X}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is translation invariant (or cash-additive) if for all \(x\in \mathcal {X}\) and \(m\in \mathbb {R}, \rho (x+m) = \rho (x)-m\).

  8. A preference relation \(\succsim \) is compact continuous if \(x\succsim y\) whenever a bounded sequence \((x_n)_{n\in \mathbb {N}}\) converges in distribution to x and \(x_n\succsim y\) for each n. As noted by Chew and Mao (1995), many widely used examples of expected utility preferences are in fact compact continuous and not continuous when the corresponding utility function is discontinuous or unbounded.

  9. The theoretical setup of Dekel (1989) used to derive the results reviewed in this section is a very particular one, and we encourage the reader to read his article for the details.

  10. This is despite the evidence supporting alternative descriptive models, showing that people’s actual behavior deviates significantly from this normative model. See Stanovich (2009) and Hastie and Dawes (2009) for a discussion.

  11. For a more complete review of the notions of risk aversion within the theory of choice under risk, we refer the reader to Cohen (1995).

  12. A number of papers have studied portfolio theory, risk sharing, and insurance contracting in the RDEU framework; see Bernard et al. (2013) for a detailed review.

  13. Objective risk is typically available in games of chance, such as a series of coin flips where the probabilities are objectively known. In practice, the notion of risk also encompasses situations, in which reliable statistical information is available, and from which objective probabilities are inferred. Uncertainty, on the other hand, can arise in practice from situations of complete ignorance or when insufficient statistical data are available, for example.

  14. Ellsberg (1961) proposed experiments where choices violate the postulates of subjective expected utility, more specifically the Sure–Thing Principle. The basic idea is that a decision maker will always choose a known probability of winning over an unknown probability of winning even if the known probability is low and the unknown probability could be a guarantee of winning. His paradox holds independent of the utility function and risk aversion characteristics of the decision maker and implies a notion of uncertainty aversion, which is an attitude of preference for known risks over unknown risks.

  15. Recall that two acts \(f,g\in \mathbb {L}\) are said to be comonotonic if for no \(s,t\in S, f(s) > f(t)\) and \(g(s) < g(t)\).

  16. See Example 1 in Chateauneuf and Tallon (2002).

  17. Uncertainty averse preferences are a general class of preferences. Special cases that can be obtained by suitably specifying the uncertainty aversion index G defined below include, among others, variational preferences and smooth ambiguity preferences. See Cerreia-Vioglio et al. (2011b) for more details.

  18. “The nature of one’s information concerning the relative likelihood of events...a quality depending on the amount, type, reliability and ‘unanimity’ of information, and giving rise to one’s degree of ‘confidence’ in an estimation of relative likelihoods.” Ellsberg (1961).

  19. They are referred to as the Two-Urn Paradox and the Three-Color Paradox—see Ellsberg (1961).

  20. “As time goes on I get more and more convinced that the right method in investment is to put fairly large sums into enterprises which one thinks one knows something about and in the management of which one thoroughly believes. It is a mistake to think that one limits one’s risk by spreading too much between enterprises about which one knows little and has no reason for special confidence. [...] One’s knowledge and experience are definitely limited and there are seldom more than two or three enterprises at any given time in which I personally feel myself entitled to put full confidence.” See Keynes (1983).

  21. See De Giorgi et al. (2016) for a review of empirical evidence suggesting underdiversification.

  22. A number of other research efforts empirically studying the effect of ambiguity aversion on portfolio choice reach the conclusion of under-diversification in some form, including the works of Uppal and Wang (2003), Maenhout (2004), Maenhout (2006), Garlappi et al. (2007), Liu (2010), Campanale (2011), and Chen et al. (2014).

References

  • Acerbi, C., Tasche, D.: Expected shortfall: a natural coherent alternative to value at risk. Econ. Notes 31(2), 379–388 (2002a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acerbi, C., Tasche, D.: On the coherence of expected shortfall. J. Bank. Finance 26(7), 1487–1503 (2002b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais, M.: The General Theory of Random Choices in Relation to the Invariant Cardinal Utility Function and the Specific Probability Function: The \((U, q)\) Model—A General Overview. CNRS, Paris (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, F., Aumann, R.: A definition of subjective probability. Ann. Math. Stat. 34, 199–205 (1963)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J.: The theory of risk aversion. In: Saatio, Y.J. (ed.) Aspects of the Theory of Risk Bearing. Markham Publ. Co., Chicago (1965)

  • Artzner, P., Delbaen, F., Eber, J.-M., Heath, D.: Coherent measures of risk. Math. Finance 9(3), 203–228 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C., He, X., Yan, J.-A., Zhou, X.Y.: Optimal insurance design under rank-dependent expected utility. Math. Finance 25(1), 154–186 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D.: Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk. Econometrica 22, 23–26 (1738)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, P., Garlappi, L., Uppal, R., Wang, T.: Keynes meets Markowitz: the trade-off between familiarity and diversification. Manag. Sci. 58(2), 253–272 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campanale, C.: Learning, ambiguity and life-cycle portfolio allocation. Rev. Econ. Dyn. 14, 339–367 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Montrucchio, L.: Risk measures: rationality and diversification. Math. Finance 21(4), 743–774 (2011a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Montrucchio, L.: Uncertainty averse preferences. J. Econ. Theory 146, 1275–1330 (2011b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, A., Cohen, M.: Risk seeking with diminishing marginal utility in a non-expected utility model. J. Risk Uncertain. 9, 77–91 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, A., Lakhnati, G.: From sure to strong diversification. Econ. Theory 32, 511–522 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, A., Tallon, J.-M.: Diversification, convex preferences and non-empty core in the choquet expected utility model. Econ. Theory 19, 509–523 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, H., Ju, N., Miao, J.: Dynamic asset allocation with ambiguous return predictability. Rev. Econ. Stud. 17(4), 799–823 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S.H., Karni, E., Safra, Z.: Risk aversion in the theory of expected utility with rank dependent probabilities. J. Econ. Theory 42, 370–381 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S.H., Mao, M.H.: A Schur concave characterization of risk aversion for non-expected utility preferences. J. Econ. Theory 67, 402–435 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choquet, G.: Theory of capacities. Ann. Inst. Fourier 5, 131–295 (1954)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M.D.: Risk-aversion concepts in expected- and non-expected-utility models. Geneva Pap. Risk Insur. Theory 20, 73–91 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Giorgi, E., Epper, T., Mahmoud, O.: A behavioral analysis of diversification. Working Paper, University of St. Gallen (2016)

  • Debreu, G.: Continuity properties of Paretian utility. Int. Econ. Rev. 5, 285–293 (1964)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E.: Asset demands without the independence axiom. Econometrica 57, 163–169 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dimmock, S. G., Kouwenberg, R., Mitchell, O.S., Peijnenburg, K.: Ambiguity aversion and household portfolio choice. NBER Working Paper No. 18743 (2014)

  • Dow, J., da Costa Werlang, S.R.: Uncertainty aversion, risk aversion, and the optimal choice of portfolio. Econometrica 60(1), 197–204 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drapeau, S., Kupper, M.: Risk preferences and their robust representation. Math. Oper. Res. 38(1), 28–62 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D.: Risk, ambiguity and savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 75, 643–679 (1961)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G.: A definition of uncertainty aversion. Rev. Econ. Stud. 66(3), 579–608 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Föllmer, H., Schied, A.: Coherent and convex risk measures. In: Cont, R. (ed.) Encyclopedia of Quantitative Finance, pp. 355–363. Wiley, New York (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Föllmer, H., Schied, A.: Stochastic Finance: An Introduction in Discrete Time. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin (2011)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garlappi, L., Uppal, R., Wang, T.: Portfolio selection with parameter and model uncertainty: a multi-prior approach. Rev. Financ. Stud. 20, 41–81 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Marinacci, M.: Ambiguity made precise: a comparative foundation. J. Econ. Theory 102, 251–289 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I.: Expected utility with purely subjective non-additive probabilities. J. Math. Econ. 16, 65–88 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hadar, J., Russell, W.R.: Rules for ordering uncertain prospects. Am. Econ. Rev. 59, 25–34 (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hastie, R., Dawes, R.M.: Rational Choice in an Uncertain World: The Psychology of Judgement and Decision Making. SAGE Publishing Inc., Beverly Hills (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Tversky, A.: Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47, 263–291 (1979)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Tversky, A.: Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty. J. Risk Uncertain. 5, 297–323 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan & Co, London (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.: Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Houghton Miffin, Boston (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Landsberger, M., Meilijson, I.: Mean-preserving portfolio dominance. Rev. Econ. Stud. 60, 479–485 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lintner, J.: The valuation of risky assets and the selection of risky investments in stock portfolios and capital budgets. Rev. Econ. Stat. 47(1), 13–37 (1965)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, H.: Robust consumption and portfolio choice for time varying investment opportunities. Ann. Finance 6, 435–454 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M.J.: A stronger characterization of declining risk aversion. Econometrica 50, 1069–1079 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M.J.: The Economic Theory of Individual Behavior Toward Risk. Cambridge University Press, First published in 1983 as Paper No. 433, Center for Research on Organizational Efficiency, Stanford University (2008)

  • Machina, M.J., Siniscalchi, M.: Ambiguity and ambiguity aversion. In: Machina, M.J., Viscusi, K. (eds.) Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty, Chap. 13, vol. 1, pp. 729–807. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Maenhout, P.: Robust portfolio rules and asset pricing. Rev. Financ. Stud. 17, 951–983 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M.J., Siniscalchi, M.: Robust portfolio rules and detection-error probabilities for a mean-reverting risk premium. J. Econ. Theory 128, 136–163 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markowitz, H.M.: Portfolio selection. J. Finance 7, 77–91 (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossin, J.: Equilibrium in a capital asset market. Econometrica 34(4), 768–783 (1966)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, J.W.: Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica 32, 122–136 (1964)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J.: A theory of anticipated utility. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 3, 323–343 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J.: Comparative statics for rank-dependent expected utility theory. J. Risk Uncertain. 4, 339–350 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J.: Increasing risk: another definition. In: Chikan, A. (ed.) Progress in Decision, Utility and Risk Theory. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J.: Generalized expected utility theory: the rank-dependent model. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1993)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F.J.: Truth and probability. In: Braithwaite, R.B. (ed.) The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays. Kegan Paul, London (1926)

  • Röell, A.: Risk aversion in Quiggin and Yaari’s rank-order model of choice under uncertainty. Econ. J. 97, 143–159 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S.A.: Some stronger measures of risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica 49(3), 621–638 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothchild, M., Stiglitz, J.E.: Increasing risk: I. A definition. J. Econ. Theory 2, 225–243 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.J.: The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York (1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D.: Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica 5, 571–587 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, U.: Anticipated utility: a measure representation approach. Ann. Oper. Res. 19, 359–374 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe, W.F.: Capital asset prices: a theory of market equilibrium under conditions of risk. J. Finance 19(3), 425–442 (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K.E.: Decision Making and Rationality in the Modern World. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Uppal, R., Wang, T.: Model misspecification and underdiversification. J. Finance 58, 2465–2486 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., Morgenstern, O.: Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1944)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.: Characterizing optimism and pessimism directly through comonotonicity. J. Econ. Theory 52, 453–463 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, M.E.: The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica 55, 95–115 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J.: Subjective ambiguity, expected utility and choquet expected utility. Econ. Theory 20(1), 159–181 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Enrico G. De Giorgi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

De Giorgi, E.G., Mahmoud, O. Diversification preferences in the theory of choice. Decisions Econ Finan 39, 143–174 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10203-016-0182-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10203-016-0182-4

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation