Skip to main content
Log in

A forensics of wishing: technology assessment in the age of technoscience

  • Focus
  • Published:
Poiesis & Praxis

Abstract

If one considers the Collingridge dilemma to be a dilemma awaiting a solution, one has implicitly abandoned a genuinely historical conception of the future and adopted instead a notion of the future as an object of technical design, the realisation of technical possibility or as wish-fulfilment. The definition of technology assessment (TA) as a successful response to the Collingridge dilemma renders it a technoscience that shares with all the others the conceit of being able, supposedly, to shape the future. An alternative way of pursuing TA begins with an analysis of our age of technoscience, including its impoverished conception of the future. A critical appreciation of this conception gives rise to a forensics of wishing.

Zusammenfassung

Wer das Collingridge Dilemma für ein Dilemma hält, das lösungsbedürftig ist und vielleicht sogar gelöst werden kann, hat sich bereits von einem historisch verstandenen Zukunftsbegriff verabschiedet und sieht Zukunft stattdessen als Gegenstand technischer Gestaltung, als Realisierung eines implizit schon gegebenen grenzenlosen technischen Potenzials, als Wunscherfüllung. Wenn sie vom Collingridge Dilemma ausgeht, wird die Technikfolgenabschätzung eine Technowissenschaft wie jede andere und macht sich ihren Hochmut angeblicher Zukunftsgestaltung zu eigen. Eine Alternative besteht darin, von der Analyse unseres Zeitalters der Technowissenschaften auszugehen und aus der Kritik des verarmten Zukunftsbegriffs eine Forensik des Wünschens zu entwickeln.

Résumé

Si nous considérons que le Dilemme de Collingridge est un dilemme en attente d’une solution, nous aurons, de manière implicite, abandonné une véritable conception historique de l’avenir et, à la place, adopté une notion de l’avenir en tant qu’objet de conception technique ou de réalisation de possibilité technique ou de réalisation d’un souhait. La définition de l’évaluation de la technologie en tant que réponse réussie au Dilemme de Collingridge le rend une technoscience qui partage avec tous les autres la vanité d’être capable, soi-disant, de former l’avenir. Une manière alternative de poursuivre l’évaluation de la technologie débute avec une analyse de notre ère de la technoscience, y compris sa conception appauvrie de l’avenir. Une appréciation critique de cette conception donne lieu à un débat sur le souhait.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This claim and its associated recommendations cannot be fully substantiated in a single paper. Here, it serves mostly to stimulate discussion, and its presentation therefore retains the semi-formal format of a lecture.

  2. Some theorists of technoscience, most notably Bruno Latour, argue that there is no difference between science and technoscience because upon close analysis, all sciences turn out to be technosciences—their work of purification never succeeds (Latour 1987, 1993). In the age of science, at any rate, it is a hallmark of science to engage in this work of purification, whereas in the age of technoscience, even much of physics and biology is abandoning it.

  3. Many drivers conspired to render the ideal obsolete and they all belong to the age of technoscience. They include science policy-makers and many scientists themselves—preferring the likes of a Louis Pasteur to a Nils Bohr on the one hand and a Thomas Edison on the other (Stokes 1997). They also include Science and Technology Studies—against the vigorous resistance by many philosophers and some historians of science.

  4. For all we know at this point, the technology assessment of nanomedicine serves primarily to add weight to its promises.

  5. The worry behind this dilemma is not new. In a 1963 essay on Husserl’s philosophy of technology, Hans Blumenberg noted that in respect to the technological condition, the time when it is not yet possible to raise questions becomes fused with the time in which it is no longer possible to ask questions (Blumenberg 1963).

  6. To be sure, as Liebert and Schmidt (2010a) point out, Collingridge himself does not suggest that the dilemma can be avoided by getting hold of the future through knowledge. He envisions a kind of ongoing control that keeps the problem from arising.

  7. This claim is at the heart of a disagreement about appeals to the future in TA of nanotechnology between Dupuy and Grinbaum (2004), Grunwald (2008) and Nordmann (2008). Certainly, such disagreements deserve more attention than the somewhat curt and provocative treatment they receive here.

  8. The analysis so far agrees with Liebert and Schmidt (2010a) in its analysis of the Collingridge dilemma as a problem of control. They argue, however, that Collingridge does not sufficiently appreciate the opportunities afforded under the conditions of technoscientific knowledge production. Their own proposal for avoiding the dilemma takes these conditions into consideration (Liebert and Schmidt 2010a, b). As such, their proposal appears to confirm the present analysis. However, Liebert and Schmidt rely on a distinction between the ambition to control technological development and soft, participative, reflective, and characteristically technoscientific modes of shaping it. Again, a more sustained discussion is required to explore the viability and potential significance of this distinction.

  9. However, see Hölscher (1999) for a history of the future, including a concluding chapter that notes the abandonment of the future as a historical category in our current age.

  10. This is leaving aside the fascinating question as to whether there are technical systems so complex that it would require a sustained, perhaps indefinite process of inquiry to determine what some machine does or does not do. Also, materials research might formulate and deliberate hypotheses about specific properties of a device. To be distinguished here are the temporal horizons for the scientific hypothesis “such and such stresses induce material fatigue (and a device of this kind will break after 15 years)” and for the technoscientific claim “the controlled growth of carbon nanotubes can be achieved with this kind of seeding on this kind of substrate”. The first of these claims requires past and future history of science to be validated, the second is validated at the moment of its realisation.

  11. This is a strong claim, to be sure, that requires a cultural history of the present. For an extremely modest beginning, see Nordmann and Schwarz (2010).

  12. Again, here is a distinction that demands closer attention—while everyone talks about acceptance or rejection of human enhancement technologies, there is no teleological or regulative discourse about the role of technology in the process of the Enlightenment, including intellectual and moral improvement (with the exception, perhaps, of Khushf 2007). Indeed, such a discourse would appear rather quaint in a technological milieu or the age of technoscience.

  13. Though the following focuses on the forensics of wishing, quite literally, this is not the only approach that avoids reference to the future. Any assessment that evaluates technological alternatives can do this.

References

  • Bensaude-Vincent B (2009) Les Vestiges de la Technoscience. Éditions la Découverte, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenberg H (1963) Lebenswelt und Technisierung unter Aspekten der Phänomenologie. In: Blumenberg H (ed) Wirklichkeiten in denen wir leben. Reclam, Stuttgart, pp 7–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Collingridge D (1980) The social control of technology. St. Martin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupre J (2008) What is a human being. In: Ganten D, Gerhardt V, Ingersoll J-CH, Nida-Rümelin J (eds) Was ist der Mensch. Berlin, De Gruyter

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy J-P, Grinbaum A (2004) Living with uncertainty: toward the ongoing normative assessment of nanotechnology. Techné 8:4–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher E, Mahajan Roop L, Mitcham C (2006) Midstream modulation of technology: governance from within. Bulletin of Science. Technology & Society 26(6):485–496

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman P (2007) The primacy of science in modernity, of technology in postmodernity, and of ideology in the history of technology. Hist Technol 23:1–152, 10.1080/07341510601092191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galison P (2006) The pyramid and the ring. Presentation at the conference of the Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie (GAP), Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Grin J, Grunwald A (eds) (2000) Vision assessment: shaping technology in 21st century society. Springer, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald A (2006) Nanotechnologie als Chiffre der Zukunft. In: Nordmann A, Schummer J, Schwarz A (eds) Nanotechnologien im Kontext: Philosophische, gesellschaftliche Perspektiven. Ethische Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, Berlin, pp 49–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1983) Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hölscher L (1999) Die Entdeckung der Zukunft. Fischer, Frankfurt/M

    Google Scholar 

  • Hottois G (1984) Le Signe et la Technique: La Philosopie à l’épreuve de la technique. Aubier, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Khushf G (2004) Systems theory and the ethics of human enhancement: a framework for NBIC convergence. Ann New York Acad Sci 1013:124–149, 10.1196/annals.1305.007

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour B (1987) Science in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour B (1993) We have never been modern. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebert W, Schmidt J (2010) Collingridge’s dilemma and technoscience: an attempt to provide a clarification from the perspective of philosophy of science. Poiesis & Praxis 7 (this issue)

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebert W, Schmidt J (2010) Towards a prospective technology assessment: challenges and requirements for TA in the age of technoscience. Poiesis & Praxis 7 (this issue)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann A (2007) If and then: a critique of speculative nanoethics. NanoEthics 1(1):31–46, 10.1007/s11569-007-0007-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann A (2008) No future for nanotechnology? Historical development vs. global expansion. In: Jotterand F (ed) Emerging conceptual, ethical and policy issues in bionanotechnology. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 43–63, 10.1007/978-1-4020-8649-6_4

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann A (Forthcoming) Science in the context of technology. In: Carrier M, Nordmann A (eds) Science in the context of application. Springer, Berlin

  • Nordmann A, Schwarz A (2010) Lure of the ‘Yes’: The seductive power of technoscience. In: Kaiser M, Kurath M, Maasen S, Rehmann-Sutter C (eds) Governing future technologies: nanotechnology and the rise of an assessment regime. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 255–277

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes D (1997) Pasteur’s quadrant–basic science and technological innovation. Brookings Institution Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1946) Science as a vocation. In: Gerth HH, Wright Mills C (eds) From max weber: essays in sociology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 129–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne B (2001) Creating public alienation: expert cultures of risk and ethics on GMOs. Sci Cul 10(4):445–481, 10.1080/09505430120093586

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfred Nordmann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nordmann, A. A forensics of wishing: technology assessment in the age of technoscience. Poiesis Prax 7, 5–15 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10202-010-0081-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10202-010-0081-7

Keywords

Navigation