Skip to main content
Log in

Non-bossiness

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An allocation rule is “non-bossy” if whenever a change in an agent’s preferences does not bring about a change in his assignment, then it does not bring about a change in anybody’s assignment. We discuss the multiple interpretations that have been proposed for this property. We question their validity, arguing that in most cases, non-bossiness either says too little or that it says too much. We also make a case against the property. We propose as its main justification the technical help that it often provides in structuring classes of rules, making characterizations more manageable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Serizawa (1999) writes: “It has also been an important research question whether or not we can substitute for nonbossiness a simple, weak, and economically meaningful condition”.

  2. In the language of Thomson (2016), non-bossiness is a “post-application invariance property” of a rule: it states the invariance of certain components of the choice the rule makes with respect to certain changes in the arguments that are subject to conditions whose verification requires that it be applied first.

  3. The index i is generally understood to refer to a specific agent but if (i) is adopted, it may more generally refer to a “position” in an economy. The position may be filled by agents with one of several preferences.

  4. Under the name of “weak non-bossiness (in terms of welfare)”.

  5. These authors use the name of “non-bossiness” and so do Berga and Moreno (2009). Mizukami and Wakayama (2007) and Nishizaki (2012) refer to it as “strong non-bossiness”.

  6. Ritz refer to it as “non-corruptibility”, as he has in mind a strategic interpretation of the property. We prefer avoiding this term because of the other, non-strategic, interpretations that can be given to the property. Berga and Moreno (2009) use the expression “weak non-bossiness”.

  7. Non-bossiness in welfare on both sides is discussed by Mutuswami (1997, 2005) under the name of “strong utility nonbossiness”, and Bade (2015) under the name of “utility non-bossiness”. Both authors provide examples of rules revealing, in the context of two different types of allocation problems, the absence of a direct logical relation between non-bossiness and non-bossiness in welfare on both sides.

  8. These authors refer to it as “weak non-bossiness”, Mizukami and Wakayama (2007), as “quasi-strong non-bossiness”, and Berga and Moreno (2009) as “quasi-non-bossiness”.

  9. These authors propose the group-restricted version under the name of “H-respectfulness”, H designating the pre-specified group. It is for an easier comparison with the other properties that we present two versions of it. Raghavan (2014a) discusses a property that is closely related to the unlimited version. Raghavan (2014b) discusses another conditional invariance property that is logically independent of non-bossiness.

  10. Nath and Sen (2014) refer to it as “allocation non-bossiness”.

  11. Saijo et al. (2007) refer to the first property as “the outcome rectangular property” and to the second one as “the rectangular property”. Mizukami and Wakayama (2005) formulate the requirement, under the name of “the weak rectangular property”, that under the same hypotheses as the rectangle property, both agents find the new outcome at most as desirable as the initial outcome according to their initial preferences.

  12. Of course, if it is manipulable, it may well be manipulable by more than one agent, and to really understand the consequences of the behavior, we should engage in its full-fledged game-theoretic analysis. For each preference profile, we should identify the equilibria of the manipulation game associated with it, and compare the resulting allocation(s) to the allocation that would have been selected in the absence of manipulation (Hurwicz 1972).

  13. Olson (1991) and Miyagawa (1997) have proposed that the two properties be merged. The first author refers to a rule satisfying their conjunction as “non-strategic” and the second as “strongly strategy-proof”.

  14. To the best of our knowledge, this is the first paper in which an implication of this type has been established.

  15. This interpretation is proposed by Ritz (1983).

  16. The property is usually called “Maskin monotonicity”.

  17. The property is introduced by Moulin (1987) in the context of binary social choice under the name of “agreement”. It has been studied in a wide variety of models. For another application, see Thomson (1993), For a survey, see Thomson (1999).

  18. For a dictatorial rule, there is an agent, chosen ahead of time and once and for all, whose welfare the rule always maximizes. The same alternatives may all be most preferred for several of his possible preferences, and among them, the rule may select in a manner that leaves his assignment unchanged but makes the other agents’ assignments depend on what his preferences are. Given an order on the agent set, the sequential priority rule associated with that order selects the alternative that is most preferred by the agent who is first if there is a unique such alternative; if not, among the alternatives that are most preferred by this agent, it selects the one that is most preferred by the agent who is second, if there is a unique such alternative, and so on. Non-bossiness holds because the order is specified before preferences are known.

  19. We say “typically” because a “conditional” type of sequential priority rule can be defined for which at each step, the identity of the agent who is next is made to depend on the preferences of the agents who have chosen so far. Such a rule is obviously bossy.

  20. Adachi and Kongo (2013) propose a version of non-bossiness in welfare on both sides, under the name of “strong non-bossiness in welfare”, which has an even closer connection to welfare-dominance under preference-replacement. On the hypothesis side, indifference is required for only one of the relations that are contemplated for the agent whose preferences change, and the requirement is that all other agents find their assignments when he makes that particular announcement at least as desirable as when he makes the second announcement. The two preference relations that are contemplated for agent i do not play the same role, so the requirement is not that the welfare of all of the other agents be unchanged. The hypotheses are weaker than those of welfare-dominance.

  21. The consistency “principle” has been the object of a large literature, reviewed in Thomson (2015a). The axiom of consistency can also be written for solution correspondences, but since here we focus on its connection to non-bossiness, a property of rules, we have stated it for rules.

  22. In fact, consistency implies the strong form of a “separability” property, which itself implies a group version of non-bossiness (Sect. 7.1).

  23. This is the case whenever the reduction operation is “transitive”. This means that reducing an economy with agent set N with respect to some subgroup \(N'\) of N and some outcome x, and then reducing the resulting economy with respect to some subgroup \(N''\) of \(N'\) and \(x_{N'}\), is the same thing as directly reducing the initial economy with respect to \(N''\) and x. Transitivity holds for the models discussed in these pages.

  24. Balinski and Young (1982) restate consistency as the requirement that “Every part of a fair allocation should be fair”.

  25. Of course, non-bossiness does not imply consistency. To see this, it suffices to consider, in our variable-population framework, a sequential priority rule in which the orders in which assignments are calculated are chosen independently population by population. For consistency, the orders with which the components of a sequential priority rule are associated should be induced from a single reference order on the entire population of potential agents.

  26. In the context of object allocation problems, random priority rules have the same feature of achieving some sort of fairness across economies (in the expected sense) but not in each economy separately (in the ex post sense). However, because each agent still has to be assigned an object, the extent to which some agents are favored by a sequential priority rule is significantly less than what is the case for the dictatorial rules that we have discussed.

  27. There are plenty of similar situations. In bargaining theory, continuity of a rule is very compelling, and not imposing continuity is not the same thing as endorsing any kind of discontinuous behavior. We cannot go into details here, but the tradeoffs between continuity, Pareto-optimality, and monotonicity are well-known.

  28. This discussion is based on Thomson (2015b).

  29. There are domains on which the Walrasian correspondence is single-valued and non-bossy. An example is the domain of Cobb-Douglas economies. The Walrasian definition can also be applied to object-reallocation problems when each agent owns one object and consumes at most one (Shapley and Scarf 1974). It is equivalent on this domain to Gale’s “top-trading-cycle rule”, which is non-bossy.

  30. Under the names of “coalitional nonbossiness”, “strong nonbossiness”, and “group non-bossiness”.

  31. Afacan (2012) provides an example in the context of object allocation problems to make the point.

  32. Under the name of “total non-bossiness”.

  33. One definition is proposed by Bogomolnaia et al. (2005).

  34. An example of such a characterization is based on the individual-endowments lower bound, anonymity in welfare, and strategy-proofness (Ashlagi and Serizawa 2012). Related results are due to Saitoh and Serizawa (2007), Sakai (2008, (2013), and Chew and Serizawa (2007).

  35. This is an object-allocation problem in which each object comes with a priority relation over its possible recipients.

  36. This rule is commonly known as the “deferred acceptance mechanism”.

  37. This rule is commonly known as the “Boston mechanism”.

  38. In the context of several-to-one two-sided matching, no selection from the stable correspondence is non-bossy (Kojima 2010). In fact, non-bossiness is incompatible with weaker requirements than stability (Kongo 2013). Thus, we can deduce from these results the non-existence of selections from the stable correspondence, or rules satisfying these weaker requirements, as well as each of the properties that we have enumerated imply non-bossiness.

  39. The argument applies even if preferences are not required to be strictly convex. If linear preferences were in the domain, it would suffice to give agent i preferences whose level curves are hyperplanes normal to the prices p.

References

  • Abdulkadiroğlu A, Sönmez T (2003) School choice: a mechanism design approach. Am Econ Rev 93:729–747

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adachi T, Kongo T (2013) First-price auctions on general preference domains: axiomatic characterizations. Econ Theory Bull 1:93–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Afacan M (2012) On the “group non-bossiness” property. Econ Bull 32:1571–1575

    Google Scholar 

  • Alcalde J (1996) Implementation of stable solutions to marriage problems. J Econ Theory 69:240–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alcalde-Unzu J, Molis E (2011) Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the top trading absorbing sets mechanisms. Games Econ Behav 73:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashlagi I, Serizawa S (2012) Characterizing Vickrey allocation rule by anonymity. Soc Choice Welf 38:531–542

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atlamaz M, Yengin D (2008) Fair Groves mechanisms. Soc Choice Welf 31:573–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bade S (2015) Multilateral matching under dichotomous preferences. Mimeo

  • Balinski M, Young P (1982) Fair Representation. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Berga D, Moreno B (2010) Individual versus group strategy-proofness: when do they coincide? J Econ Theory 145:1648–1674

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Berga D, Moreno B (2016) Group strategy-proofness in private good economies. Am Econ Rev 106:1073–1099

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Jackson M (1995) Strategy-proof exchange. Econometrica 63:51–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Jackson M, Neme A (1997) Strategy-proof allotment rules. Games Econ Behav 18:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berga D, Moreno B (2009) Strategic requirements with indifference: single-peaked versus single-plateaued preferences. Soc Choice Welf 32:275–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogomolnaia A, Deb R, Ehlers L (2005) Incentive-compatibility on the full preference domain. J Econ Theory 123:161–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew SH, Serizawa S (2007) Characterizing the Vickey combinatorial auction by induction. Econ Theor 33:393–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chun Y (1999) Equivalence of axioms for bankruptcy problems. Int J Game Theory 28:511–520

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chun Y (2006) The separability principle in economies with single-peaked preferences. Soc Choice Welf 26:239–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doğan B (2016) Nash-implementation of the no-envy solution on symmetric domain of economies. Games Econ Behav 98:165–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doğan B, Klaus B (2016) Object allocation via immediate-acceptance: characterizations and an affirmative action application. Mimeo

  • Dur U (2015) The modified Boston mechanism. Mimeo

  • Ehlers L (2014) Top trading with fixed tie-breaking in markets with indivisible goods. J Econ Theory 151:64–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley D (1967) Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Econ Essays 7:45–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Gale D, Shapley L (1962) College admissions and the stability of marriage. Am Math Mon 69:9–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes. Econometrica 41:587–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless P (2016) Immediate acceptance with or without skips: comparing school assignment procedures. Mimeo

  • Hashimoto K, Saitoh H (2012) Strategy-proof cost sharing under increasing returns: improvement of the supremal welfare loss. Mimeo

  • Hurwicz L (1972) On informationally decentralized systems. In: McGuire CB, Radner R (eds) Chapter 14 in Decision and Organisation. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 297–336

  • Jaramillo P, Manjunath V (2012) The difference indifference makes in strategy-proof allocation of objects. J Econ Theory 147:1913–1946

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ju B-G (2013) Coalitional manipulation on networks. J Econ Theory 148:627–662

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaus B (2001a) Population-monotonicity and separability for economies with single-dipped preferences and the assignment of an indivisible object. Econ Theor 17:675–692

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaus B (2001b) Coalitional strategy-proofness in economies with single-peaked preferences and the assignment of an indivisible object. Games Econ Behav 34:64–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaus B, Bochet O (2013) The relation between monotonicity and strategy-proofness. Soc Choice Welf 40:41–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kojima F (2010) Impossibility of stable and nonbossy matching mechanisms. Econ Lett 107:69–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kongo T (2013) On non-bossy matching rules in two-sided matching problems. Int J Econ Theory 9:303–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Breton M, Zaporozhets V (2009) On the equivalence of coalitional and individual strategy-proofness properties. Soc Choice Welf 33:287–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Long Y (2016) Strategy-proof group selection under single-peaked preferences over group size. Mimeo

  • Manjunath V (2012) When too little is as good as nothing at all: rationing a disposable good among satiable people with acceptable thresholds. Games Econ Behav 74:576–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manjunath V (2014) Efficient and strategy-proof social choice when preferences are single-dipped. Int J Game Theory 43:579–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maskin E (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Rev Econ Stud 66:83–114 (first circulated in 1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mishra D, Quadir A (2014) Non-bossy single object auctions. Econ Theory Bull 2:93–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miyagawa E (1997) Strategy-proofness for the reallocation of multiple indivisible goods. University of Rochester, Mimeo

  • Mizukami H, Wakayama T (2007) Dominant strategy implementation in economic environments. Games Econ Behav 60:307–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizukami H, Wakayama T (2009) The relation between non-bossiness and monotonicity. Math Soc Sci 58:256–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morimoto S, Serizawa S (2015) Strategy-proofness and efficiency with nonquasi-linear preferences: a characterization of minimum price Walrasian rule. Theor Econ 10:445–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morimoto S, Serizawa S, Ching S (2013) A characterization of the uniform rule with several commodities and agents. Soc Choice Welf 40:871–911

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1987) The pure compensation problem: egalitarianism versus laissez-fairism. Q J Econ 101:769–783

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mukherjee C (2015) On axioms underlying the use of reserve price. Mimeo

  • Mutuswami S (1997) Strategyproof and coalitionally strategyproof mechanisms for cost sharing

  • Mutuswami S (2005) Strategyproofness, non-bossiness, and group strategy-proofness in a cost sharing model. Econ Lett 89:83–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagahisa N (1991) A local independence condition for characterization of Walrasian allocations rule. J Econ Theory 54:106–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagahisa R, Suh S-C (1995) A characterization of the Walras rule. Soc Choice Welf 12:335–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash JF (1950) The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18:155–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nath S, Sen A (2015) Affine maximizers in domains with selfish valuations. ACM Trans Econ Comput 3(26):1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill B (1982) A problem of rights arbitration from the Talmud. Math Soc Sci 2:345–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1991) Dominant and Nash strategy mechanisms for the assignment problem. Mimeo

  • Pápai S (2000a) Strategy-proof assignment by hierarchical exchange. Econometrica 68:1403–1433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pápai S (2000b) Strategyproof multiple assignment using quotas. Rev Econ Design 5:91–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pápai S (2001b) Strategyproof and nonbossy multiple assignments. J Public Econ Theory 3:257–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pápai S (2003) Strategyproof exchange of indivisible goods. J Math Econ 39:931–959

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pazner E, Schmeidler D (1978) Egalitarian equivalent allocations: a new concept of economic equity. Q J Econ 92:671–687

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raghavan M (2014a) Sufficient conditions for weak group strategy-proofness. Mimeo

  • Raghavan M (2014b) Efficient pairwise allocation with priority trading. Mimeo

  • Rhee S (2011) Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods among couples. Jpn Econ Rev 62:289–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritz Z (1983) Restricted domains, Arrow social welfare functions and noncorruptible and non-manipulable social choice correspondences: the case of private alternatives. Math Soc Sci 4:155–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saijo T, Sjöström T, Yamato T (2007) Secure implementation. Theor Econ 2:203–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Saitoh H, Serizawa S (2007) Vickrey allocation rule with income effect. Econ Theor 35:391–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2008) Second price auctions on general preference domains: two characterizations. Econ Theor 37:347–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2013) An equity characterization of second price auctions when preferences may not be quasi-linear. Rev Econ Design 17(1):17–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T, Wakayama T (2011) Uniform, equal division, and other envy-free rules between the two

  • Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorem for voting procedures and social choice functions. J Econ Theory 10:187–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite M, Sonnenschein H (1981) Strategy-proof allocation mechanisms at differentiable points. Rev Econ Stud 48:587–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer J (2000) Manipulation through bribes. J Econ Theory 91:180–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serizawa S (1999) Strategy-proof and symmetric social choice functions for public good economies. Econometrica 67:121–145

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley L, Scarf H (1974) On cores and indivisibility. J Math Econ 1:23–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shenker S (1992) Some technical results on continuity, strategy-proofness, and related strategic concepts. Mimeo

  • Sönmez T, Switzer T (2013) Matching with (branch-of-choice) contracts at United States military academy. Econometrica 81:451–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (1987) The vulnerability to manipulative behavior of economic mechanisms designed to select equitable and efficient outcomes. In: Groves T, Radner R, Reiter S (eds) Chapter 14 of Information, Incentives and Economic Mechanisms. University of Minnesota Press, USA, pp 375–396

  • Thomson W (1993) The replacement principle in public good economies with single-peaked preferences. Econ Lett 42:31–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (1999) Welfare-domination under preference-replacement: a survey and open questions. Soc Choice Welf 16:373–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2005) Divide-and-permute. Games Econ Behav 52:186–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2011) Fair allocation rules. In: Arrow K, Sen A, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. North-Holland, Amsterdam, New York, pp 393–506

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2012) On the axiomatics of resource allocation: Interpreting the consistency principle. Econ Philos 28:385–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2015a) Consistent allocation rules. Mimeo

  • Thomson W (2015b) Strategy-proof allocation rules. Lecture notes

  • Thomson W (2016) Designing allocation rules. Mimeo

  • Wakayama T (2016) Bribe-proofness for single-peaked preferences: characterizations and maximality-of-domains results. Mimeo

  • Yengin D (2012) Egalitarian-equivalent Groves mechanisms in the allocation of heterogenous objects. Soc Choice Welf 38:137–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yengin D (2013a) Identical preferences lower bound for allocation of heterogeneous tasks and NIMBY problems. J Public Econ Theory 15:580–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yengin D (2013b) Population monotonic and strategy-proof mechanisms respecting lower bounds. J Math Econ 49:389–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Thomson.

Additional information

I thank Bernardo Moreno, Vikram Manjunath, Szilvia Pápai, and particularly Andrew Mackenzie, Patrick Harless, anonymous referees and the Editor for their comments. I presented early versions of this work at a conference held in Madrid in the honor of Luis Corchon in June 2014, at the SSK International Conference on Distributive Justice held in Seoul, October 2014, at the Manchester Workshop in Social Choice and Mechanism Design in May 2015, and at the Workshop in Microeconomic Theory held in Lausanne in May 2015.

Appendices

Appendix A

This appendix contains lists of models that should help understand the role played by non-bossiness in relating strategy-proofness and group strategy-proofness.

(i)  Models for which non-bossiness (or a version of it) and strategy-proofness together imply group strategy-proofness (or its weak form) are identified by Barberà and Jackson (1995), Serizawa (1996), Pápai (2000a, (2000b), Rhee (2011), Manjunath (2014), and Long (2016).

(ii)  Models for which a related implication holds that involves some other requirements are identified by Barberà et al. (1997), Klaus (2001a, (2001b), and Mutuswami (2005).

(iii)  Models for which non-bossiness and strategy-proofness together do not imply group strategy-proofness are identified by Miyagawa (1997), Pápai (2003), Alcalde-Unzu and Molis (2011), Manjunath (2012), Jaramillo and Manjunath (2012), Hashimoto and Saitoh (2012), Ehlers (2014) and Morimoto et al. (2013).

Appendix B

In this appendix we support our claim that there is no logical relation between localness and non-bossiness. We omit the formal definition of the Walrasian rule. It is clearly local. However, there are domains on which it is bossy.

Claim 1

The Walrasian rule violates non-bossiness on the quasi-linear domain.

To prove this, we consider the following example, in the description of which \(U(R_i,x_i)\) designates the upper contour set of the relation \(R_i\) at \(x_i\). Here, by a quasi-linear relation we mean a relation such that if two bundles are indifferent, then so are the two bundles obtained from them by adding the same quantity of a particular good. Let \({\varvec{\mathcal {R}}}_{{{\varvec{ql}}}}\) denote the class of continuous, monotonic, convex, and quasi-linear preferences for which the particular good is good 1. An economy is a pair \((\omega , R)\) of a profile \(\omega \equiv (\omega _i)_{i \in N}\) of endowments and a profile \(R\equiv (R_i)_{i \in N}\in \mathcal {R}^N_{ql}\). Let W denote the Walrasian rule. To make our point, we need not vary the endowment profile and therefore we do not list it as an argument of W.

Proof

Let \(\ell =2\), \(N\equiv \{1,2,3\}\), \(\omega _1= \omega _2 =\omega _3 \equiv (5,5)\), and preferences \(R \in \mathcal {R}^N_{ql}\) be such that \(U(R_1, x_1)\) is uniquely supported by the line of slope \(-1\) at each point \(x_1\) of ordinate 5, \(U(R_2, x_2)\) is supported by any line of slope between \(-1\) and \(-\frac{1}{2}\) at each point \(x_2\) of ordinate 3, \(U(R_3, x_3)\) is supported by any line of slope between \(-1\) and \(-\frac{1}{2}\) at each point \(x_3\) of ordinate 7. Let \(y\equiv ((5,5), (7,3),(3,7))\). We have \(\{y\} =W(R)\). Now, let \(R'_1\in \mathcal {R}_{ql}\) be such that \(U(R'_1, x_1)\) is uniquely supported by the line of slope \(-\frac{1}{2}\) at each point \(x_1\) of ordinate 5. Let \(y'_1\equiv y_1\), \(y'_2\equiv (9, 3)\),  \(y'_3\equiv (1,7)\), and \(y'\equiv (y'_1, y'_2, y'_3)\). Then, \(\{y'\} =W(R'_1, R_2,R_3)\). Agent 1’s assignment has not changed, but the other agents’ assignments have. \(\square \)

Agents 2 and 3’s preferences in the example used to prove Claim 1 are not smooth: they have non-degenerate cones of lines of support at each point on the horizontal lines of ordinates 3 and 5 respectively. The relevance of smoothness in guaranteeing non-bossiness is discussed by Satterthwaite and Sonnenschein (1981).

Non-bossiness does not imply localness. The proof if by means of an example. It concerns the fair division problem when preferences belong to the domain \({\varvec{\mathcal {R}}}_{{{\varvec{cl}}}}\) of continuous, monotonic, and strictly convex preferences.

Example 1

Let r be a point in the simplex of commodity space, and let \({{\varvec{E}}}^{{\varvec{r}}}\) be the rule that selects, for each economy, the efficient allocation x—under our assumptions, it is unique—such that, for some \(\lambda \in \mathbb {R}_+\), each agent \(i \in N\) is indifferent between \(x_i\) and \(\lambda r\).

The egalitarian-equivalence correspondence (Pazner and Schmeidler 1978) selects for each economy each allocation x such that there is a reference bundle \(x_0\) that each agent finds indifferent to his assignment. The rules \(\{E\}_{r \in \Delta ^{\ell -1}}\) are canonical selections from the Pareto–and–egalitarian-equivalence correspondence.

Claim 2

For each \(r \in \Delta ^{\ell -1}\), the rule \(E^r\) is non local and non-bossy.

Proof

It is obvious that each \(E^r\) violates localness. Now, let \(R \in \mathcal {R}^N_{cl}\) and \(x\equiv E^r(R)\) with associated parameter \(\lambda \). Let \(i \in N\). Let \(R'_i \in \mathcal {R}_{cl}\) and \(x'\equiv E^r(R'_i, R_{-i})\). Suppose that \(x'_i = x_i\). Let \(\lambda '\) be the parameter associated with \((R'_i, R_{-i})\). We claim that \(\lambda '=\lambda \). Indeed, if \(\lambda '>\lambda \), each agent \(j \in N{\setminus } \{i\}\) is better off than he was initially. This means that in R, \(x'\) Pareto dominates x. If \(\lambda '<\lambda \), in \((R'_i, R_{-i})\), x Pareto dominates \(x'\). In each case, we obtain a contradiction to the fact that \(E^r\) is a selection from the Pareto correspondence. If \(\lambda '=\lambda \), for each \(j \in N{\setminus } \{i\}\), \(x'_j = x_j\). Altogether, \(x' = x\). \(\square \)

Because of its importance to public economics, let us also discuss the Lindahl correspondence, again omitting the formal definitions. (The only difference with the Walrasian correspondence is that agents face individualized prices.) It is clearly local. Also, there are interesting preference domains on which it is single-valued and non-bossy. One such domain is when (i) preferences are strictly convex and the public good is “strictly normal”, in the sense that an increase in the individualized price an agent faces leads to an increase in the public good component of the bundle at which he maximizes his preferences in his budget set, and (ii) the technology is linear. Then, there is a unique Lindahl allocation. Now, if agent i’s preferences change but his assignment does not, the public good level does not change. For an agent’s maximizing bundle on his new budget set to have the same public good component, his budget set should be the same. He faces the same individualized prices. So then, the allocation remains a Lindahl allocation.

Appendix C

The individual-endowments-lower-bound correspondence selects all the allocations that each agent finds at least as desirable as his endowment.

Claim 3

Any subsolution of the Pareto–and–individual-endowments-lower-bound correspondence that is local is a subsolution of the Walrasian correspondence.

Proof

Let \(\varphi \) be a subsolution of the Pareto correspondence. Let \(R \in \mathcal {R}^N\), \(x \in \varphi (R)\), and suppose that \(x \notin W(R)\). Then, at the supporting prices p—they exist because \(\varphi \) is a subsolution of the Pareto correspondence—there is \(i \in N\) such that \(px_i <p\omega _i\). Then, let \(R'_i \in \mathcal {R}\) be such that \(U(R'_i,x_i)\) still admits p as supporting prices, but \(\omega _i \mathrel {P'_i} x_i\).Footnote 39 By localness, \(x\in \varphi (R'_i,R_{-i})\). However, in \((R'_i,R_{-i})\), the individual-endowments lower bound is violated for agent i at x. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thomson, W. Non-bossiness. Soc Choice Welf 47, 665–696 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0987-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0987-7

JEL Classification

Navigation