Skip to main content
Log in

Limit representations of intergenerational equity

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Equal treatment of all generations is a fundamental ethical principle in intertemporal welfare economics. This principle is expressed in anonymity axioms of orderings on the set of infinite utility streams. We first show that an ordering satisfies finite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity if and only if it is represented by an increasing, continuous function that is a natural extension of the limit function. We then show that whenever such an ordering is infinitely anonymous, it depends only on the liminf and limsup of any utility stream. Our results imply that in ethically ranking utility streams, reflecting only infinitely long-run movements is possible, with liminf and limsup particularly essential, but it is impossible to respect finite generations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, Fleurbaey and Michel (2003) for other versions.

  2. An exception is Lemma 4 in Lauwers (1997a). He essentially shows that if an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies a weak Pareto axiom, infinite anonymity, sup continuity, and a limit approximation axiom that links finite generations with infinite generations, then it depends only on the infimum and supremum of any utility stream. Note that our results are only related to limit properties, instead of infimum or supremum. Mathematically, the class of orederings characterized by our Theorem 2 and the class by Lauwers’ Lemma 4 have no intersection.

  3. Transitivity: for every \(x,y,z\in \ell ^{\infty }\), \(x\succsim y\) and \(y\succsim z\) imply \(x\succsim z\); Completeness: for every \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), either \(x\succsim y\) or \(y\succsim x\).

  4. This axiom is weaker than a non-substitution axiom by Lauwers (1997b) that does not allow indifference. Non-substitution axioms can be also found in Lauwers (1998), Asheim et al. (2007), and Alcantud and Garcìa-Sanz (2010a, (2010b), but ours is weakest.

  5. See, for example, Atsumi (1965), Weizsäcker (1965), Asheim (1991), Fleurbaey and Michel (2003), Sakai (2003a, (2010a), Asheim and Tungodden (2004), Asheim et al. (2010), Kamaga and Kojima (2010).

  6. His analysis focuses on linear functions and does not study orderings that can be represented by linear functions. Linear functions on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) that are extensions of the limit function are often called Banach limits (see, for example, Royden and Fitzpatrick 2010), and their existence depends on the axiom of choice.

  7. Chichilnisky (1996) and Sakai (2003b) define sensitivity axioms for finite generations, such as “non-dictatorship of the future” or “sensitivity to the present”. Any ordering represented by a generalized limit function violates these axioms.

  8. See, for example, Sakai (2010a, (2010b) and references therein.

  9. Mitra and Ozbek (2013) obtain more general representability conditions. Our Lemma 3 can be derived from their Proposition 2 (see, their Example 3).

References

  • Alcantud JCR, Garcìa-Sanz MD (2010a) Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion. Econ Lett 16:209–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alcantud JCR, Garcìa-Sanz MD (2010b) Evaluations of Infinite utility streams: Pareto-efficient and Egalitarian axiomatics, mimeo. Universidad de Salamanca, Salamanca

    Google Scholar 

  • Alcantud JCR (2012) Inequality averse criteria for evaluating infinite utility streams: the impossibility of weak Pareto. J Econ Theor 147:353–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB (1991) Unjust intergenerational allocations. J Econ Theor 54:350–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, d’Aspremont C, Banerjee K (2010) Generalized time-invariant overtaking. J Math Econ 46:519–533

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Mitra T, Tungodden B (2007) A new equity condition for infinite utility streams and the possibility of being paretian. In: Roemer J, Suzumura K (eds) Intergenerational equity and sustainability. Palgrave, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim GB, Tungodden B (2004) Resolving distributional conflicts between generations. Econ Theor 24:221–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atsumi H (1965) Neoclassical growth and the efficient program of capital accumulation. Rev Econ Stud 32:127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basu K, Mitra T (2003) Aggregating infinite utility streams with inter-generational equity: the impossibility of being paretian. Econometrica 71:1557–1563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosmans K, Ooghe E (2013) A characterization of maximin. Econ Theory Bull 1:151–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Sprumont Y, Suzumura K (2007) Ordering infinite utility streams. J Econ Theor 135:579–589

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers CP (2009) Intergenerational equity: sup, inf, lim sup, and lim inf. Soc Choice Welf 32:243–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky G (1996) An axiomatic approach to sustainable development. Soc Choice Welf 14:231–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu G (1954) Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In: Thrall RM, Coombs CH, Davis RL (eds) Decision proc. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond P (1965) The evaluation of infinite utility streams. Econometrica 33:170–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Michel P (2003) Intertemporal equity and the extension of the ramsey criterion. J Math Econ 39:777–802

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond PJ (1976) EquityArrow’s conditions, and Rawls’ difference principle. Econometrica 44:793–804

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamaga K, Kojima K (2010) On the leximin and utilitarian overtaking criteria with extended anonymity. Soc Choice Welf 35:377–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers L (1995) Time-neutrality and Linearity. J Math Econ 24:347–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers L (1997a) Rawlsian equity and generalised utilitarianism with an infinite population. Econ Theor 9:143–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers L (1997b) Continuity and equity with infinite horizons. Soc Choice Welf 14:345–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers L (1998) Intertemporal objective functions -strong pareto versus anonymity. Math Soc Sci 35:37–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers L (2010) Ordering infinite utility streams comes at the cost of a non-Ramsey set. J Math Econ 20:32–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matsuyama K (2005) Poverty traps. In: Blume L, Durlauf S (eds) The new palgrave dictionary of economics, 2nd edn. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitra T, Ozbek MK (2013) On representation of monotone preference orders in a sequence space. Soc Choice Welf 41:473–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royden HL, Fitzpatrick PM (2010) Real Anal, 4th edn. Pearson Education, Upper Saddle River

    Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2003a) An axiomatic approach to intergenerational equity. Soc Choice Welf 20:167–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2003b) Intergenerational preferences and sensitivity to the present. Econ Bull 4:1–5

    Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2006) Equitable intergenerational preferences on restricted domains. Soc Choice Welf 27:41–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2010a) Intergenerational equity and an explicit construction of welfare criteria. Soc Choice Welf 35:393–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakai T (2010b) A characterization and an impossibility of finite length anonymity for infinite generations. J Math Econ 46:877–883

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svensson L-G (1980) Equity among generations. Econometrica 48:1951–1956

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Weizsäcker CC (1965) Existence of optimal programmes of accumulation for an infinite time horizon. Rev Econ Stud 32:85–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zame WR (2007) Can utilitarianism be operationalized? Theor Econ 2:187–202

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to two anonymous referees, Marc Fleurbaey, Kohei Kamaga, Michihiro Kandori, Kaname Miyagishima, Akira Okada, Hiroo Sasaki, Koichi Tadenuma, and William Thomson for their insightful comments. Various earlier versions of this paper were presented at Keio University, Okayama University, Tokyo Institute of Technology, University of Tokyo, Waseda University, SWET 2010, the 16th Decentralization Conference at Kwansei Gakuin University, and the Hitotsubashi GCOE Lectures and Workshop on Choice, Games, and Welfare. I thank participants of these seminars for their helpful comments. This research is financially supported by KAKENHI (24220003). Parts of this paper were formerly circulated as “A welfare economics foundation for steady state analysis” and “An impartial representation in infinite time horizon”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toyotaka Sakai.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Theorem 1

Our proof proceeds in several lemmas, which may have independent interest. We only show that if an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto, finite anonymity, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then it is represented by a generalized limit function, since the converse statement obviously holds.

It is easy to see that uniform Pareto and sup continuity imply the following mild Pareto axiom:

  • Monotonicity. For each \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\),    if \(x_t \ge y_t\) for all \(t\in {\mathbb {N}}\),    then \(x\succsim y\).

We next introduce a new Pareto axiom that does not care utility levels of finite generations:

  • Tail Pareto. For each \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\),    if there exist \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) and \(\varepsilon >0\) for which \(x_t > y_t +\varepsilon \) for all \(t\ge s\),    then \(x{\mathrel {\succ }}y\).

Tail Pareto implies uniform Pareto and weak non-substitution, and tail Pareto and sup continuity together imply monotonicity. The normative desirability of tail Pareto might be controversial, but our first lemma shows that it is implied by uniform Pareto, finite anonymity, and weak non-substitution.

Lemma 1

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto, finite anonymity, and weak non-substitution, then \(\succsim \) satisfies tail Pareto.

Proof

Let \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\) be such that there exist \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) and \(\varepsilon >0\) for which \(x_t > y_t +\varepsilon \) for all \(t\ge s\). Our purpose is to prove \(x{\mathrel {\succ }}y\). Let \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) be such that \(a+\varepsilon <\min \{x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_s, y_1,y_2,\ldots ,y_s \}\).

Take some \(\delta \in (0,\varepsilon )\). Define \(z^1 \in \ell ^{\infty }\) by

$$\begin{aligned} z^1_1\equiv & {} a,\\ z^1_t\equiv & {} y_t +\frac{1}{s}\delta \quad \text {for all } t\ge 2. \end{aligned}$$

By weak non-substitution, \(z^1\succsim y\). Also, define \(\tilde{z}^1 \in \ell ^{\infty }\) by replacing \(z^1_1\) and \(z^1_2\) in \(z^1\), that is,

$$\begin{aligned} {\tilde{z}}^1_1\equiv & {} y_2+\frac{1}{s}\delta ,\\ {\tilde{z}}^1_2\equiv & {} a,\\ {\tilde{z}}^1_t\equiv & {} y_t +\frac{1}{s}\delta \quad \text {for all } t\ge 3. \end{aligned}$$

By finite anonymity, \({\tilde{z}}^1 {\mathrel {\sim }}z^1\).

For each integer q with \(2\le q \le s\), define \(z^q \in \ell ^{\infty }\) by

$$\begin{aligned} z^q_1\equiv & {} a,\\ z^q_2\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-1}{s}\delta ,\\ z^q_3\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-2}{s}\delta ,\\ z^q_4\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-3}{s}\delta ,\\&\ldots&\\ z^q_q\equiv & {} a+\frac{1}{s}\delta ,\\ z^q_t\equiv & {} y_t +\frac{q}{s}\delta \quad \forall t\ge q+1. \end{aligned}$$

Next, for each integer q with \(2\le q \le s-1\), define \({\tilde{z}}^q \in \ell ^{\infty }\) by replacing \(z^q_1\) with \(z^q_{q+1}\) in \(z^q\), that is,

$$\begin{aligned} {\tilde{z}}^q_1\equiv & {} y_{q+1}+\frac{q}{s}\delta ,\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_2\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-1}{s}\delta ,\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_3\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-2}{s}\delta ,\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_4\equiv & {} a+\frac{q-3}{s}\delta ,\\&\ldots&\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_q\equiv & {} a+\frac{1}{s}\delta ,\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_{q+1}\equiv & {} a,\\ {\tilde{z}}^q_t\equiv & {} y_t +\frac{q}{s}\delta \quad \forall t\ge q+2. \end{aligned}$$

For each integer q with \(1\le q \le s-1\), finite anonymity implies \({\tilde{z}}^q {\mathrel {\sim }} z^q\), and weak non-substitution implies \(z^{q+1} \succsim {\tilde{z}}^q\). Therefore, \(z^s \succsim z^1\). Furthermore, uniform Pareto implies \(x {\mathrel {\succ }} z^s\) because

$$\begin{aligned} x_t>&z^s_t \quad \forall t\le s,\\ x_t>&z^s_t +(\varepsilon -\delta ) \quad \forall t>s. \end{aligned}$$

Overall, \(x{\mathrel {\succ }} z^s \succsim z^1 \succsim y\), as desired. \(\square \)

Lemma 2

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies tail Pareto and sup continuity, then for each \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\) such that there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) for which \(x_t = y_t\) for all \(t\ge s\), we have \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}y\).

Proof

Consider any ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying tail Pareto and sup continuity. Note that \(\succsim \) also satisfies monotonicity. Let \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\) be such that there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) for which \(x_t = y_t\) for all \(t\ge s\). Define

$$\begin{aligned} a'\equiv \max \{x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_s, y_1,y_2,\ldots ,y_s\} \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} a'' \equiv \min \{x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_s, y_1,y_2,\ldots ,y_s\}. \end{aligned}$$

Define also

$$\begin{aligned} x'\equiv & {} (\underbrace{a',a', \ldots ,a'}_{s \text { terms}}, x_{s+1},x_{s+2},x_{s+3},\ldots ) \text { and }\\ x''\equiv & {} (\underbrace{a'',a'',, \ldots , a''}_{s \text { terms}}, x_{s+1},x_{s+2},x_{s+3},\ldots ). \end{aligned}$$

By monotonicity, \(x' \succsim x\succsim x''\) and \(x' \succsim y\succsim x''\). Since our purpose is to obtain \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}y\), it suffices to show \(x' {\mathrel {\sim }} x''\). Suppose, by contradiction, that \(x' {\mathrel {\succ }} x''\). Then by sup continuity, there exists a small \(\varepsilon >0\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} x' {\mathrel {\succ }}z\equiv (\underbrace{a'',a'', \ldots , a''}_{s \text { terms}}, x_{s+1}+\varepsilon ,x_{s+2}+\varepsilon ,x_{s+3}+\varepsilon ,\ldots ). \end{aligned}$$

On the other hand, tail Pareto implies \(z{\mathrel {\succ }}x'\), a contradiction. Thus we obtain \(x' {\mathrel {\sim }} x''\), and hence \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}y\). \(\square \)

When there is no danger of confusion, we denote by \(\varvec{a}\equiv (a,a,\ldots )\in \ell ^{\infty }\) the constant utility stream consisting of \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\). Note that \(\varvec{a}=(a)_{rep}\). The following lemma is essentially due to Debreu (1954) and Diamond (1965, p. 172), but we write its proof for completeness.Footnote 9

Lemma 3

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto and sup continuity, then for each \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\), there exists a unique \(b\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{b}\).

Proof

By sup continuity, the set of constant streams \(Y\equiv \{\varvec{a}\in \ell ^{\infty }: \exists a\in {\mathbb {R}}\}\) is a closed subset of \(\ell ^{\infty }\) in the sup norm topology. By uniform Pareto, both \(\{y\in Y: y\succsim x\}\) and \(\{y\in Y: x\succsim y\}\) are non-empty, and they are closed with respect to the sup norm topology. Since no closed set can be partitioned by two disjoint closed sets in the sup norm topology, they have a non-empty intersection, that is, there exists \(b\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{b}\). Uniqueness of such b is ensured by uniform Pareto. \(\square \)

Lemma 4

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies tail Pareto and sup continuity, then for each \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) such that \(\lim x_t\) exists, whenever \(a\equiv \lim x_t\), we have \(x {\mathrel {\sim }} \varvec{a}.\)

Proof

Consider any ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying tail Pareto and sup continuity. Note that \(\succsim \) also satisfies monotonicity and uniform Pareto. Pick any \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) such that \(\lim x_t\) exists. Let \(a\equiv \lim x_t\). By Lemma 3, there exists \(b\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }} \varvec{b}\). It suffices to show that \(a=b\). We first show that \(a>b\) is impossible. If \(a>b\), then, since \(a=\lim x_t\), there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that for all \(t\ge s\), \(x_t>\dfrac{a+b}{2}\). By Lemma 2,

$$\begin{aligned} y\equiv \bigg (x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_s,\frac{a+b}{2},\frac{a+b}{2},\frac{a+b}{2},\ldots \bigg ){\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{\frac{a+b}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

But monotonicity and uniform Pareto imply

$$\begin{aligned} x\succsim y {\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{\frac{a+b}{2}} {\mathrel {\succ }}\varvec{b}, \end{aligned}$$

a contradiction. We next show that \(a<b\) is also impossible. If \(a<b\), then, since \(a=\lim x_t\), there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that for all \(t\ge s\), \(x_t<\dfrac{a+b}{2}\). By Lemma 2,

$$\begin{aligned} z\equiv \bigg (x_1,x_2,\ldots ,x_s,\frac{a+b}{2},\frac{a+b}{2},\frac{a+b}{2},\ldots \bigg ) {\mathrel {\sim }} \varvec{\frac{a+b}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

But uniform Pareto and monotonicity imply

$$\begin{aligned} \varvec{b} {\mathrel {\succ }}\varvec{\frac{a+b}{2}} {\mathrel {\sim }} z \succsim x, \end{aligned}$$

a contradiction. Overall, \(a=b\), and hence \(x {\mathrel {\sim }} \varvec{a}\). \(\square \)

The next lemma completes the proof of Theorem 1.

Lemma 5

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto, finite anonymity, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then there exists a generalized limit function \(F: \ell ^{\infty }\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) that represents \(\succsim \).

Proof

Consider any ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the four axioms. By Lemma 3, for each \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\), there exists a unique \(b\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{b}\). Thus we can define the function \(F:\ell ^{\infty }\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) so that \(F(x)=b\) with \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}\varvec{b}\). It is obvious that g represents \(\succsim \). Hence, it remains to show that g is a generalized limit function. Lemma 4 implies “limit selection,” Lemma 1 implies “tail monotonicity,” Lemma 2 implies “head insensitivity,” and sup continuity implies “continuity.” \(\square \)

1.2 Proof of Theorem 2

One can easily check that if an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) has an increasing, continuous function \(W:{\mathbb {R}}^2\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) satisfying

$$\begin{aligned} x\succsim y \Longleftrightarrow W(\underline{x},\overline{x}) \ge W(\underline{y},\overline{y}) \quad \forall x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }, \end{aligned}$$
(1)

then it satisfies infinite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity. Therefore, we shall show that if an ordering satisfies these four axioms, then it is represented as in (1). The proof consists of the following three steps:

  1. Step 1.

    Define a dense subset \({\mathcal {U}}\) of \(\ell ^{\infty }\), called the universal finite domain.

  2. Step 2.

    Clarify ranking of utility streams that belong to \({\mathcal {U}}\).

  3. Step 3.

    For every utility stream in \(\ell ^{\infty }\setminus {\mathcal {U}}\), find another utility stream in \({\mathcal {U}}\) that is indifferent to it. This completes finding the entire ranking.

We begin the proof.

1.2.1 Step 1. Introducing the universal finite domain

Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be the set of non-empty, finite subsets of \({\mathbb {R}}\), that is,

$$\begin{aligned} {\mathcal {S}}\equiv \{X\subset {\mathbb {R}} : 1\le |X|<\infty \}. \end{aligned}$$

Given any finite set of “utility parameters” \(X\in {\mathcal {S}}\), its infinite product \(X^{\infty }\) denotes the associated domain of utility streams. The universal finite domain is the union of all associated domains,

$$\begin{aligned} {\mathcal {U}}\equiv \bigcup _{X\in {\mathcal {S}}} X^{\infty }. \end{aligned}$$

Lemma 6

The set \({\mathcal {U}}\) is a dense subset of \(\ell ^{\infty }\) in the sup norm topology; that is, for every \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) and every \(\varepsilon >0\), there exists \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\) such that \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t -y_t|<\varepsilon \).

Proof

Pick any \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) and \(\varepsilon >0\). Let \(M>0\) be a large integer such that

$$\begin{aligned} -M\varepsilon<x_t<M\varepsilon \quad \forall t\in {\mathbb {N}}. \end{aligned}$$

For every \(t\in {\mathbb {N}}\), there exists a unique \(m\in \{-M+1,-M+2,\ldots ,M-1,M\}\) such that \((m-1)\varepsilon < x_t \le m\varepsilon \), and then let \(y_t\equiv (m-\frac{1}{2})\varepsilon \). Obviously, \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t-y_t|\le \frac{1}{2}\varepsilon <\varepsilon \). Since \(y=(y_1,y_2,\ldots )\) consists of at most finite number of real values, it follows that \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\).

Let \({\mathcal {N}}\) be the set of infinite subsets of \({\mathbb {N}}\), that is, \({\mathcal {N}}\equiv \{{\mathbb {N}}'\subset {\mathbb {N}}: |{\mathbb {N}}'|=\infty \}\). Pick any \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\), and let \(A(x)\equiv \{a\in {\mathbb {R}} : \exists {\mathbb {N}}'\in {\mathcal {N}}, \forall t\in {\mathbb {N}}', x_t=a\}\) be the set of real values that appear in \(x=(x_1,x_2,\ldots )\) infinitely many times. Since x is taken from the universal finite domain, A(x) consists of at most finite number of real values, that is, \(1\le |A(x)| <\infty \). The key properties described by the next lemma should be recognized throughout the subsequent discussion.

Lemma 7

For every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\), (i) \(\underline{x}=\min _{a\in A(x)}a\) and \(\overline{x}=\max _{a\in A(x)}a\), and (ii) there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that \(\underline{x} \le x_t \le \overline{x}\) for all \(t\ge s\).

Proof

Immediately follows from the definition of the universal finite domain. \(\square \)

We also remark that for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\), both \(\max _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}}x_t\) and \(\min _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}}x_t\) are well-defined.

1.2.2 Step 2. Clarify ranking on the universal finite domain

The next axiom is a stronger non-substitution condition. It obviously implies weak non-substitution.

  • Strong non-substitution. For every \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), if there exist a finite subset \({\mathbb {N}}'\subset {\mathbb {N}}\), an infinite subset \({\mathbb {N}}''\subset {\mathbb {N}}\setminus {\mathbb {N}}'\), and \(\varepsilon >0\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned}&y_t<x_t \qquad \quad \text {for all }t\in {\mathbb {N}}',\nonumber \\&x_t +\varepsilon \le y_t \quad \text {for all }t\in {\mathbb {N}}'',\nonumber \\&x_t=y_t \qquad \quad \text {for all } t\notin {\mathbb {N}}'\cup {\mathbb {N}}'', \end{aligned}$$
    (2)

    then \(y\succsim x\).

Lemma 8

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then it satisfies strong non-substitution.

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the four axioms. By Theorem 1, there exists a generalized limit function \(F:\ell ^{\infty } \rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) that represents \(\succsim \). Consider any \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\) that satisfy the hypothesis of strong non-substitution, as in (2). Let us show \(y\succsim x\). Define \(z\in \ell ^{\infty }\) by \(z_t \equiv x_t\) for all \(t\in {\mathbb {N}}'\) and \(z_t \equiv y_t\) for all \(t\in {\mathbb {N}}\setminus {\mathbb {N}}'\). Then by definition,

$$\begin{aligned} F(y)=F(z)\ge F(x), \end{aligned}$$

so \(y\succsim x\). \(\square \)

Lemma 9

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, monotonicity, and strong non-substitution, then for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}<\overline{x}\), it holds that \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\succsim x\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the three axioms. Pick any \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}<\overline{x}\). Let \({\mathbb {N}}_{1}\equiv \{t\in {\mathbb {N}}: x_t =\underline{x}\}\). Since \(\underline{x}=\min _{a\in A(x)}a\) by Lemma 7, we have \(|{\mathbb {N}}_1 |=\infty \), and hence there exists \({\mathbb {N}}_{2}\subset {\mathbb {N}}_{1}\) such that \(|{\mathbb {N}}_2|=\infty \) and \(|{\mathbb {N}}_1 \setminus {\mathbb {N}}_2 |=\infty \).

Define y by

$$\begin{aligned} \overline{x}<x_t&\Longrightarrow&y_t \equiv \underline{x},\\ t\in {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&y_t\equiv \frac{\underline{x}+\overline{x}}{2},\\ \text { otherwise }&\Longrightarrow&y_t\equiv x_t. \end{aligned}$$

By strong non-substitution, \(y\succsim x\).

Define z by

$$\begin{aligned} t\in {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&z_t \equiv \overline{x},\\ t\notin {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&z_t \equiv x_t . \end{aligned}$$

Since z is obtained from x by a permutation, by infinite anonymity, \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}z\). By monotonicity, \(z\succsim y\). Therefore, \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}y\).

Define w by

$$\begin{aligned} \underline{x}<y_t&\Longrightarrow&w_t\equiv \overline{x},\\ y_t\le \underline{x}&\Longrightarrow&w_t\equiv \underline{x}. \end{aligned}$$

Then by monotonicity, \(w\succsim y\), and hence \(w\succsim x\). By infinite anonymity, \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}{\mathrel {\sim }}w\), and hence \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\succsim x\). \(\square \)

Lemma 10

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, monotonicity, and strong non-substitution, then for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}<\overline{x}\), it holds that \(x\succsim (\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the three axioms. Pick any \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}<\overline{x}\). Let \({\mathbb {N}}_{1}\equiv \{t\in {\mathbb {N}}: x_t =\overline{x}\}\). Let \({\mathbb {N}}_{2}\subset {\mathbb {N}}_{1}\) be such that \(|{\mathbb {N}}_2|=\infty \) and \(|{\mathbb {N}}_1 \setminus {\mathbb {N}}_2 |=\infty \). Define y by

$$\begin{aligned} t\in {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&y_t \equiv \frac{\underline{x}+\overline{x}}{2},\\ x_t<\underline{x}&\Longrightarrow&y_t\equiv \underline{x},\\ \text { otherwise }&\Longrightarrow&y_t \equiv x_t . \end{aligned}$$

By strong non-substitution, \(x\succsim y\).

Define z by

$$\begin{aligned} t\in {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&z_t\equiv \underline{x},\\ t\notin {\mathbb {N}}_{2}&\Longrightarrow&z_t\equiv x_t. \end{aligned}$$

Since z is obtained from x by a permutation, by infinite anonymity, \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}z\). By monotonicity, \(y\succsim z\). Therefore, \(y\succsim x\), so that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}y\).

Define w by

$$\begin{aligned} y_t < \overline{x}&\Longrightarrow&w_t\equiv \underline{x},\\ \overline{x} \le y_t&\Longrightarrow&w_t\equiv \overline{x}. \end{aligned}$$

Then by monotonicity, \(y\succsim w\), and hence \(x\succsim w\). By infinite anonymity, \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}{\mathrel {\sim }}w\), and hence \(x \succsim (\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\). \(\square \)

Lemma 11

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto, monotonicity, and strong non-substitution, then for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) and \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(\underline{x}> a\), it holds that \(x{\mathrel {\succ }}(a)_{rep}\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the three axioms. Pick any \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) and \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(\underline{x}> a\).

Let \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\) be such that

$$\begin{aligned} x_t <\underline{x}&\Longrightarrow&y_t \equiv x_t,\\ \underline{x}\le x_t&\Longrightarrow&y_t \equiv \underline{x}. \end{aligned}$$

By monotonicity, \(x\succsim y\). By strong non-substitution, \(y\succsim \left( \dfrac{\underline{x}+a}{\ 2\ }\right) _{rep}\). By uniform Pareto, \(\left( \dfrac{\underline{x}+a}{\ 2\ }\right) _{rep} {\mathrel {\succ }}(a)_{rep}\). Therefore, \(x{\mathrel {\succ }}(a)_{rep}\). \(\square \)

Lemma 12

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies uniform Pareto, strong non-substitution, and sup continuity, then for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}=\overline{x}\), it holds that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{x})_{rep}\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the three axioms. Let \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\) with \(\underline{x}=\overline{x}\). Lemma 3 implies that there exists a unique \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(a)_{rep}\). It suffices to show that \(a=\underline{x}\). Since \(\succsim \) also satisfies monotonicity, by \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(a)_{rep}\) and Lemma 11, \(a\ge \underline{x}\). Since \(\underline{x}=\overline{x}\) and \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\), there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that \(x_t=\underline{x}\) for all \(t> s\).

Suppose, by contradiction, that \(a> \underline{x}\). Define y by

$$\begin{aligned} y_t< & {} \inf _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}}x_t \quad \text { for all }t\le s,\\\equiv & {} \frac{a+\underline{x}}{2} \quad \text { for all }t>s. \end{aligned}$$

Then by strong non-substitution, \(y\succsim x\). By uniform Pareto, \((a)_{rep}{\mathrel {\succ }}y\). Hence, \((a)_{rep}{\mathrel {\succ }}x\), a contradiction. Overall, \(a=\underline{x}\) must hold. \(\square \)

We summarize characterizations obtained in this proof step. It exhibits an essence on how utility streams in \({\mathcal {U}}\) are ranked.

Lemma 13

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then for every \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\), it holds that \(x {\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the four axioms. Note that \(\succsim \) also satisfies monotonicity. Furthermore, by Lemma 8, \(\succsim \) satisfies strong non-substitution.

Take any \(x\in {\mathcal {U}}\). If \(\underline{x}<\overline{x}\), then by Lemmas 9 and 10, \(x {\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\). If \(\underline{x}=\overline{x}\), then by Lemma 12, \(x {\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\). \(\square \)

1.2.3 Step 3. Extending the characterization to \(\ell ^{\infty }\)

Lemma 14

For every \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) and every \(\varepsilon >0\), there exists \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\) such that \(\underline{x}=\underline{y}\), \(\overline{x}=\overline{y}\), and \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t-y_t|<\varepsilon \).

Proof

Pick any \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\) and \(\varepsilon >0\). By Lemma 6, there exists \(z\in {\mathcal {U}}\) such that \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t-z_t|<\varepsilon \).

Consider the case that \(a\equiv \lim x_t\) exists. Then, there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that \(|x_t -a|<\varepsilon \) for all \(t\ge s\). Define y by

$$\begin{aligned} y_t\equiv & {} z_t \quad \text { for all }t \le s-1,\\\equiv & {} a \quad \ \text { for all }t\ge s. \end{aligned}$$

Obviously, \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\) and it satisfies the desired properties.

Consider the case that \(\lim x_t\) does not exist. Then, there exists small \(\delta <\varepsilon \) such that \(\underline{x}+\delta <\overline{x}-\delta \). Furthermore, by the definitions of the liminf and limsup, there exists \(s\in {\mathbb {N}}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \underline{x}-\delta<x_t< \overline{x}+\delta \quad \text { for all }t\ge s. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

Define y by

$$\begin{aligned} y_t\equiv & {} \underline{x}\quad \text {if }t\ge s \text { and } \underline{x}-\delta<x_t<\underline{x}+\delta ,\\\equiv & {} \overline{x} \quad \text {if }t\ge s \text { and } \overline{x}-\delta<x_t<\overline{x}+\delta ,\\\equiv & {} z_t \quad \text {otherwise}. \end{aligned}$$

Since \(z\in {\mathcal {U}}\), by construction of y, we have \(y\in {\mathcal {U}}\) and \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t-y_t|<\varepsilon \). Note that there exist infinitely many \(t\ge s\) with \(\underline{x}-\delta<x_t<\underline{x}+\delta \), and infinitely many other \(t\ge s\) with \(\overline{x}-\delta<x_t<\overline{x}+\delta \). This fact and (3) imply that \(\underline{y}=\underline{x}\) and \(\overline{y}=\overline{x}\). \(\square \)

We now extend the result obtained for \({\mathcal {U}}\) in Lemma 13 to \(\ell ^{\infty }\).

Lemma 15

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then for every \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\), it holds that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the four axioms. Pick any \(x\in \ell ^{\infty }\). By Lemma 14, for every positive integer k, there exists \(x^{k}\in {\mathcal {U}}\) such that \(\underline{x}=\underline{x}^k\), \(\overline{x}=\overline{x}^k\), and \(\sup _{t\in {\mathbb {N}}} |x_t-x^k_t|<\frac{1}{k}\). By Lemma 13, \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}{\mathrel {\sim }}x^k\) for all k. Thus by sup continuity, \((\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}{\mathrel {\sim }}x\). \(\square \)

The next lemma completes the proof of Theorem 2.

Lemma 16

If an ordering \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfies infinite anonymity, uniform Pareto, weak non-substitution, and sup continuity, then there exists an increasing, continuous function \(W:{\mathbb {R}}^2\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) such that for every \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), \(x\succsim y \Longleftrightarrow W(\underline{x},\overline{x}) \ge W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\).

Proof

Let \(\succsim \) be an ordering on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the four axioms.

Take any \(z\in \ell ^{\infty }\). By Lemma 3, there exists a unique \(a(z)\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(z{\mathrel {\sim }}(a(z))_{rep}\). By Lemma 15, \(z{\mathrel {\sim }}(\underline{z},\overline{z})_{rep}\). Therefore \(a(z)=a((\underline{z},\overline{z})_{rep})\), and define

$$\begin{aligned} W\big (\underline{z},\overline{z}\big )\equiv a\big (\big (\underline{z},\overline{z}\big )_{rep}\big ). \end{aligned}$$

Note that \(W:{\mathbb {R}}^2 \rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\).

For each \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), by properties of \(a(\ \cdot \ )\) and uniform Pareto,

and

so that

$$\begin{aligned} x\succsim y \iff W\big (\underline{x},\overline{x}\big ) \ge W\big (\underline{y},\overline{y}\big ). \end{aligned}$$

Furthermore, uniform Pareto implies that W is increasing, and sup continuity implies that W is continuous, as desired. \(\square \)

1.3 Proof of Corollary 2

We only prove the “only if” part. Consider any \(\succsim \) on \(\ell ^{\infty }\) satisfying the listed five axioms. Let W be a function associated with \(\succsim \), which is established by Theorem 2. The proceeding proof depends on a standard Hammond-type proof technique (e.g., Bosmans and Ooghe 2013). It suffices to show that for all \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), (\(\star \)) \(\underline{x}> \underline{y}\) implies \(W(\underline{x},\overline{x}) > W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\), and (\(\star \star \)) \(\underline{x}= \underline{y}\) implies \(W(\underline{x},\overline{x}) = W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\).

(\(\star \)) Suppose, by contradiction, that for some \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), \(\underline{x}> \underline{y} \text { and } W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\ge W(\underline{x},\overline{x})\). Let \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) be \(\underline{x}>a>\underline{y}\). By pairwise Hammond, \((a)_{rep} \succsim (\underline{y},\overline{y})_{rep}\), and hence \(W(a,a) \ge W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\). But then \(W(a,a) \ge W(\underline{x},\overline{x})\), so \((a)_{rep}{\mathrel {\succ }}(\underline{x},\overline{x})_{rep}\). This contradicts uniform Pareto.

(\(\star \star \)) Suppose, by contradiction, that for some \(x,y\in \ell ^{\infty }\), \(\underline{x}= \underline{y} \text { and }W(\underline{x},\overline{x}) > W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\). By Lemma 3, there exists \(a\in {\mathbb {R}}\) such that \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(a)_{rep}\). Since \(W(a,a)=W(\underline{x},\overline{x})\), one has \(W(a,a)>W(\underline{y},\overline{y})\), and then increasingness of W implies \(a>\underline{y}\), which in turn implies \(a>\underline{x}\). Then there exists \(b\in {\mathbb {R}}\) with \(a>b>\underline{x}\), and by uniform Pareto and pairwise Hammond, \(W(a,a)>W(b,b)\ge W(\underline{x},\overline{x})\). This contradicts \(x{\mathrel {\sim }}(a)_{rep}\). \(\Box \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sakai, T. Limit representations of intergenerational equity. Soc Choice Welf 47, 481–500 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0973-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0973-0

Keywords

Navigation