Skip to main content
Log in

Disparities in socio-economic outcomes: some positive propositions and their normative implications

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Demographic disparities between the rates of occurrence of an adverse economic outcome can be observed to be increasing even as general social improvements supposedly lead towards the elimination of the adverse outcome in question. Scanlan (Chance 19(2):47–51, 2006) noticed this tendency and developed a ‘heuristic rule’ to explain it. In this paper, we explore the issue analytically, providing a criterion from stochastic ordering theory under which one of two demographic groups can be considered disadvantaged and the other advantaged, and showing that Scanlan’s heuristic obtains as a rigorous finding in such cases. Normative implications and appropriate social policy are discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See the Scanlan’s Rule page of www.jpscanlan.com.

  2. As a particular scenario, Scanlan posits an ‘across the board change’, or social improvement, such that everyone between a previously set poverty line and 50 % of that poverty line, escapes poverty. Following that decline, the disparity in the black/white rates of experiencing poverty increases given Scanlan’s data.

  3. Other descriptors could include economic benefit, means, good, or ‘economic advantage’. In this paper we reserve the descriptor ‘advantaged’ for one of two groups relative to the other.

  4. For the reader’s convenience and ease of transcription, \(\prec \) is denoted \(\le _{lr} \) in this book, and the random variables and distributions corresponding to our \(Y_{D},\,Y_{A}\) and \(F_{D}(y), F_{A}(y) \) are denoted \(X, Y\) and \(F(t), G(t)\) respectively.

  5. The condition can equally be expressed in terms of \(F_A (y)\) and \(F_D (y)\). For \(u\in [a,b],\,{Y}_{\!\!D} \prec {Y}_{\!\!A}\) says that \(\frac{F_D (b)-F_D (u)}{F_D (b)-F_D (a)}\le \frac{F_A (b)-F_A (u)}{F_A (b)-F_A (a)}\).

  6. Notice, however, that if one allowed for the possibility of \({\varphi }'(y)\ge 0\forall y\), then inter-group disparity could be altogether eliminated by having \(\phi (y)\) be perfectly horizontal at \(\bar{{y}}\), the mean. Provided that society is not destitute, i.e. provided that the poverty line is below the mean (Cowell 1988, p.159), no poor person would pay tax in this case.

  7. In fact, from Definition 3, \({Y}_{\!\!D} \prec {Y}_{\!\!A} \) is equivalent to \(\left\{ {Y_D \left| {a\le Y_D \le b} \right. } \right\} \prec _{fsd} \left\{ {Y_A \left| {a\le Y_A \le b} \right. } \right\} \) whenever \(a\le b\), which is clearly significantly stronger than \(F_D \prec _{fsd} F_A \).

  8. If \(X\) is uniform on {1,2,3,4} and \(Y\) is defined by P(\(Y\) = 1) = 0.1, P(\(Y\) = 2) = 0.3, P(\(Y\) = 3) = 0.2, P(\(Y\) = 4) = 0.4 then, as Shaked and Shanthikumar (2007, p. 43) note, \( X\prec _{hr} Y \quad \& \quad X\prec _{rh} Y\) (and of course \(X\prec _{fsd} Y)\) but it is not the case that \(X \prec Y\).

  9. A referee suggested that HRX might be identified by means of a carefully formulated geometric condition on the discrimination curve, namely, a condition whose stringency is intermediate between that required for the likelihood ratio ordering and that required for first-degree stochastic dominance. We thank the referee for this challenging suggestion, which remains for future investigation. It is interesting to note that several empirical studies on wage discrimination document cases in which a ‘disadvantaged’ group performs better than a supposed ‘advantaged’ one, at least on some limited wage intervals. The likelihood ratio ordering would not hold in such a case: the curve of Fig. 1 could cross the \(45^{\circ }\) line. The possibility that HRX could hold in such a circumstance also remains to be investigated in future work.

  10. Its ingredients, which are the relative frequency curves \(f_D (y)\) and \(f_A (y)\), feature centrally in the class of segregation measures proposed by Duncan and Duncan (1955), and have been used since in modified form to capture occupational discrimination by gender and by race. In that literature, both the differences in the distributions of the respective groups, and the differences in mean earnings between the respective groups, are highly relevant; see (Wolff 1976, p. 152).

  11. There are noteworthy examples of such measures, for example, the reservation of quotas in education and employment for ethnic, religious, or caste minorities, and supplementary nutrition targeted to the poor, children, or lactating mothers.

References

  • Cowell FA (1988) Poverty measures, inequality and decomposability. In: Bös D, Rose M, Seidl C (eds) Welfare and efficiency in public economics. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 149–166

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan OD, Duncan B (1955) A methodological analysis of segregation indices. Am Sociol Rev 20:210–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1977) Reverse discrimination. Taking rights seriously. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 223–237

    Google Scholar 

  • Gastwirth JL (1975) Statistical measures of earning differentials. Am Stat 29:32–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Handcock MS, Morris M (1999) Relative distribution methods in the social sciences. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jewitt I (1991) Applications of likelihood ratio orderings in economics. In: Stochastic Orders and Decision Under Risk, Institute of Mathematical Statistics Lecture Notes—Monograph Series 19. Beachwood, OH pp 174–189.

  • Le Breton M, Michelangeli A, Peluso E (2012) A stochastic dominance approach to the measurement of discrimination. J Econ Theory 147:1342–1350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom PR (1981) Good news and bad news: representation theorems and applications. Bell J Econ 12:380–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1997) Equality and priority. Ratio 10:202–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt JW (1964) Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica 32:122–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (1988) Equality of opportunity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlan JP (2006) Can we actually measure health disparities? Chance 19(2):47–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1973) On economic inequality. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shaked M, Shanthikumar JG (2007) Stochastic orders. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff EN (1976) Occupational earnings behavior and the inequality of earnings by sex and race in the United States. Rev Income Wealth 22(2):151–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors thank two anonymous referees of this journal for their insightful comments on an earlier draft, which have enabled us to make considerable improvements in our paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to S. Subramanian.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lambert, P.J., Subramanian, S. Disparities in socio-economic outcomes: some positive propositions and their normative implications. Soc Choice Welf 43, 565–576 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-014-0794-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-014-0794-y

JEL Classification

Navigation