Skip to main content
Log in

Random reduction consistency of the Weber set, the core and the anti-core

  • Published:
Mathematical Methods of Operations Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we introduce a new consistency condition and provide characterizations for several solution concepts in TU cooperative game theory. Our new consistency condition, which we call the random reduction consistency, requires the consistency of payoff vectors assigned by a solution concept when one of the players is removed with some probability. We show that the random reduction consistency and other standard properties characterize the Weber set, the convex hull of the marginal contribution vectors. Another salient feature of random reduction consistency is that, by slightly changing its definition, we can characterize the core and the anti-core in a parallel manner. Our result enables us to compare the difference between the three solution concepts from the viewpoint of consistency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that in our definition, a solution \(\sigma \) is a subset of PI.

  2. The authors thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

  3. A well-known recursion formula for the Shapley value is actually the following (see Maschler and Owen 1989; Hart and Mas-Colell 1996);

    $$\begin{aligned} Sh_{i}(N,v) = \frac{v(N) - v( \{ i \} )}{|N|} + \frac{1}{|N|} \sum _{j \in N {\setminus } \{ i \} }Sh_{i}(N {\setminus } \{ j \}, v_{|N {\setminus } \{ j \} }) \end{aligned}$$
    (4)

    where \((N {\setminus } \{ j \}, v_{|N {\setminus } \{ j \} })\) is a subgame of (Nv). Kongo et al. (2007) showed that by using the concept of duality, (4) leads to (3).

  4. Funaki and Yamato (2001) proved that the core satisfies the two properties. We can also prove that the anti-core satisfies the two properties by following the same line of the proof.

  5. Indeed, we have \(y^{N {\setminus } \{ j \} }_{i} = y^{N {\setminus } \{ j \}}(N {\setminus } \{ j \}) - y^{N {\setminus } \{ j \}}(N {\setminus } \{ i,j \} ) \le v^{com}_{N {\setminus } \{ j \}, x}(N {\setminus } \{ j \}) - v^{com}_{N {\setminus } \{ j \}, x}(N {\setminus } \{ i,j \})\), for each i.

  6. Note that \(\sigma (N,v) \subseteq PI(N,v)\).

  7. For a given coalition N and \(T \subseteq N\), the T-unanimity game, denoted as \((N,u_{T})\) is defined as

    $$\begin{aligned} u_{T}(S) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1 &{} \hbox { if}\ T \subseteq S \\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

References

  • Funaki Y, Yamato T (2001) The core and consistency properties: a general characterisation. Int Game Theory Rev 3:175–187

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Funaki Y, Tijs S, Branzei R (2007) Leximals, the lexicore and the average lexicographic value. In: Center discussion paper series no. 2007-97, Tilburg University

  • Hart S, Mas-Colell A (1996) Bargaining and value. Econometrica 64(2):357–380

  • Hwang Y, Sudhölter P (2001) Axiomaizations of the core on the universal domain and other natural domains. Int J Game Theory 29:597–623

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ichiishi T (1981) Supermodularity: applications to convex games and the greedy algorithm for LP. J Econ Theory 25:283–286

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kongo T, Funaki Y, Branzei R, Tijs S (2010) A non-cooperative and an axiomatic characterization of the average lexicographic value. Int Game Theory Rev 12:417–435

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kongo T, Funaki Y, Tijs SH (2007) New axiomatizations and an implementation of the Shapley value. Center Discussion Paper Series No. 2007-90, Tilburg University

  • Maschler M, Owen G (1989) The consistent Shapley value for hyperplane games. Int J Game Theory 18(4):389–407

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Monderer D, Samet D, Shapley LS (1992) Weighted values and the core. Int J Game Theory 21:27–39

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B (1986) On the reduced game property and its converse. Int J Game Theory 15:187–200

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B, Sudhölter P (2007) Introduction to the theory of cooperative games, 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Radzik T, Driessen T (2016) Modeling values for TU-games using generalized versions of consistency, standardness and the null player property. Math Methods Oper Res 83(2):179–205

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for \(n\)-person games. In: Roth AE (ed) The Shapley value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 41–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1971) Cores of convex games. Int J Game Theory 1:11–26

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Weber R (1988) Probabilistic values for games. In: Roth AE (ed) The Shapley value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 101–119

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Koji Yokote.

Appendix: independence of properties

Appendix: independence of properties

In this appendix we show independence of the set of properties we used to characterize the Weber set, the core and the anti-core.

1.1 Independence of NE, M-RRC, and M-CRRC

Set \(\sigma (N,v) = \emptyset \) for all \((N,v) \in \Gamma \). We can easily see that \(\sigma \) satisfies M-RRC and M-CRRC but fails to satisfy NE.

To see the independence of M-RRC, set \(\sigma (N,v) = PI(N,v)\) for all \((N,v) \in \Gamma \). It is evident that \(\sigma = PI\) satisfies ZNP and M-CRRC. Now consider a game \((N,v) \in \Gamma \) such that \(N = \{ 1,2 \}\), \(v(N) = 1\), \(v( \{ 1 \} ) = 2\), and \(v( \{ 2 \} ) = -2\). Then we have \(PI(v^{mar}_{\{1\}}) = \{ 3 \}\) and \(PI(v^{mar}_{\{2\}}) = \{ -1 \}\). If a preimputaion \(x = (x_{1} ,x_{2})\) can be represented as the way prescribed in the Eq. (1), we have

$$\begin{aligned}&x_{1} = p_{1}v( \{ 1 \} ) + p_{2}y^{\{ 1 \}}_{1} = 2p_{1} + 3p_{2} \ge 2, \\&x_{2} = p_{1}y^{\{ 2 \}}_{2} + p_{2}v( \{ 2 \} ) = -p_{1} - 2p_{2} \le -1. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, for example \((1,0) \in PI(N,v)\) can have no such representation. This indicates that \(\sigma = PI\) violates M-RRC.

In order to confirm the independence of M-CRRC, set \(\sigma (N,v) = \{ Sh(N,v) \}\) for all \((N,v) \in \Gamma \), where Sh(Nv) is the Shapley value of (Nv). Clearly \(\sigma \) satisfies NE. To see that \(\sigma \) satisfies M-RRC, it is sufficient to follow the proof of Lemma 1, with setting \(t_{\pi } = 1/|N|!\) in the Eq. (2) . Now consider a game \((N,v) \in \Gamma \) such that \(N = \{ 1,2,3 \}\), \(v(N) = 2\), \(v(S) = 1\) for \(|S| = 2\), and \(v( \{ i \} ) = 0\) for \(i = 1,2,3\). Then for all \(i \in N\), \(Sh(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{i\}}) = (1,1)\). Set \((p_{1},p_{2},p_{3}) = (1,0,0) \in \Delta (N)\). Then if we set

$$\begin{aligned}&x_{1} = p_{1}v( \{ 1 \} ) + p_{2} Sh_{1}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{2\}}) + p_{3} Sh_{1}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{3\}}) = 0, \\&x_{2} = p_{1}Sh_{2}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{1\}}) + p_{2} v( \{ 2 \} ) + p_{3} Sh_{2}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{3\}}) = 1, \\&x_{3} = p_{1}Sh_{3}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{1\}}) + p_{2} Sh_{3}(v^{mar}_{N\backslash \{2\}}) + p_{3} v( \{ 3 \} ) = 1, \end{aligned}$$

we have \(x = (x_{1},x_{2},x_{3}) \in PI(N,v)\). However \(x \ne Sh(N,v) = (2/3,2/3,2/3)\), indicating that \(\sigma \) dose not satisfy M-CRRC.

1.2 Independence of ZNP, IR, COV, CP-PRRC, and CP-CPRRC

Again, the empty solution \(\sigma (N,v) = \emptyset \) satisfies all the properties except ZNP.

If we take the solution \(\sigma (N,v) = PI(N,v)\), we can see that it satisfies all the properties except IR. Indeed the violation of IR is evident. It is also clear that PI satisfies ZNP, COV and CP-CPRRC. To see that PI possesses CP-PRRC, notice that for any \(x \in PI(N, v)\), it is true that \(x_{|N {\setminus } \{ i \}} \in PI(v^{com}_{N\backslash \{i\}, x}) \cap PI(v^{prj}_{N\backslash \{i\}, x})\) for all \(i \in N\) where \(x_{|N {\setminus } \{ i \}} = (x_{k})_{ k \in N {\setminus } \{ i \}}\), that is, the projection of x on \({\mathbb {R}}^{N {\setminus } \{ i \}}\).

To see the independence of COV, consider the solution \(\sigma (N,v)\) defined as follows.

$$\begin{aligned} \sigma (N,v) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \{ 0 \} &{} \text {if }0 \in C(N,v), \\ \emptyset &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

It clearly satisfies ZNP and IR. It is also evident that this solution violates COV. Notice that if \(0 \in C(N,v)\), we have \(0 \in C(v^{com}_{N\backslash \{j\}, 0}) \cap C(v^{prj}_{N\backslash \{j\}, 0})\) for each \(j \in N\). Therefore \(\sigma (N,v) = \{ 0 \}\) implies \(\sigma (v^{com}_{N\backslash \{j\}, x}) \cap \sigma (v^{prj}_{N\backslash \{j\}, x}) = \{ 0 \}\) for each \(j \in N\). By this fact, we can see that \(\sigma \) satisfies CP-PRRC and CP-CPRRC.

Next we will show the independence of CP-PRRC. Consider \(\sigma (N,v) = IR(N,v) = \{ x \in PI(N,v) \; | \; x_{i} \ge v( \{ i \} ) , \; \forall i \in N \}\), the set of all individually rational preimputations. \(\sigma = IR\) satisfies ZNP since \( \{ 0 \} = IR(N,v)\) for any zero non-positive games. It clearly satisfies IR and COV. Notice that the proof of Lemma 4 shows that \(\sigma = IR\) satisfies CP-CPRRC [see Eqs. (5, 6)]. Now consider a game (Nv) such that \(N = \{ 1,2,3 \}\) and the coalition function is defined as follows;

$$\begin{aligned}&v(N) = 1, \; v( \{ 1,2 \} ) = 3, \; v( \{ 1,3 \} ) = v( \{ 2,3 \} ) = 0 \\&v( \{ 1 \} ) = 1, v( \{ 2 \} ) = 0, v( \{ 3 \} ) = -1. \end{aligned}$$

Then we have \(IR(N,v) \ne \emptyset \), but \(IR(v^{com}_{N\backslash \{1\}, x}) \cap IR(v^{prj}_{N\backslash \{1\}, x}) = \emptyset \) for all \(x\in IR(N,v)\). Therefore any \(x \in IR(N,v)\) cannot have the representation as the way prescribed in the Eq. (7). This shows the violation of CP-PRRC.

Finally, we will show the independence of CP-CPRRC. Consider the solution \(\sigma \) defined as follows.

$$\begin{aligned} \sigma (N,v) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} C(N,v) &{} \text {if }|N| \le 3, \\ \emptyset &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

It clearly satisfies the all the properties except CP-CPRRC. The violation of CP-CPRRC is also easily verified (consider, for example, any four-person game).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Agatsuma, Y., Funaki, Y. & Yokote, K. Random reduction consistency of the Weber set, the core and the anti-core. Math Meth Oper Res 85, 389–405 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00186-017-0575-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00186-017-0575-3

Keywords

Navigation