Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

Man's language ability is due to a more general, deep-seated cognitive ability characteristic of the species. It is argued that man's ability for mathematical thinking is a product of the same species-specific form of cerebration as language. The basis for mathematical constructs seems to be contained in the basis for language constructs; apparently, for every mathematical notion there is a homologous one in the sphere of language, the former always being more restricted and well defined than the latter. Mathematical ability may therefore be regarded as a special case of the more general ability that also generates language, and this point is further emphasized by certain similarities in the formal structure of mathematics (arithmetic in particular) and language. Taking advantage of the commonalities between language and arithmetic, it is possible to use the latter to illustrate important general characteristics of the former. The insights gained are relevant to biology at large, and to comparative zoology and neurology in particular. The zoologist who wishes to compare animal communication with language must know what the nature of language is-how (or whether) one might analyze it into components. He must know what might constitute a primitive or simple language. It is shown that the irreducible elements of the two systems under study (language and arithmetic) are processes (i.e., processes of “relating,” or simply “relations”) and that these processes combine into interrated systems. The systems have ontogenetic histories that might, perhaps, furnish a criterion for the notion of simplicity. We do not yet know what might be a homologous phylogenetic “cousin” of the basic human ability under consideration; howerver, we should expect it to be “homeomorphic” to the human system if it is derived from a common ancestral ability. Homeomorphic mapping is therefore the most reliable criterion so far for phylogenetic relatedness. By characterizing language and arithmetic simultaneously (in order to get at their common biological foundations) it is also possible to sharpen up the questions that the student of language should put to the neurophysiologist. The quest for innovation or differences in brain processes and functions now appears to be the primary one, whereas a description of structural changes in the human brain would be of interest only insofar as this would elucidate how brain functions might have become modified by them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Bellugi, U. (in press).How Children Say No. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

  • Benacerraf, P., and Putnam, H. (eds.) (1963).Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, R. A., and Gardner, B. T. (1969). Teaching sign language to a chimpanzee.Science 165: 664–672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guttman, N. (1968). Review ofBiological Foundations of Language, by E. H. Lenneberg,J. Acoust. Soc. Amr. 43: 178–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hockett, C. F. (1960). Logical considerations in the study of animal communication. In Lanyon, W. E., and Tavolga, W. N. (eds.),Animal Communication. American Institute of Biological Sciences. Washington, D.C., pp. 392–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenneberg, E. H. (1967).Biological Foundations of Language. Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenneberg, E. H. (1969). On explaining languageScience 164: 635–643.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenneberg, E. H. (1970). Brain Correlates of language. In Schmitt, F. O. (ed.),The Neurosciences: Second Study Program. Rockefeller University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfungst, O. (1911).Clever Hans, The Horse of Mr. von Osten. Holt, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D. (1969).A Functional Analysis of Language Invited address., Div. I, Amer. Psychol. Assoc., Washington, D.C.; mimeographed prepublication copy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitaker, H. A. (1969).On the Representation of Language in the Brain. UCLA Working Papers in Phonetics #12.

  • Zeeman, E. C., and Buneman, O. P. (1968). Tolerance spaces and the brain. In Waddington, C. H., (ed.),Towards a Theoretical Biology; an I.U.B.S. Symposium. Aldine, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

This paper has resulted from research carried out under Grant No. 2279 from the Wenner-Gren Foundation.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lenneberg, E.H. Of language knowledge, apes, and brains. J Psycholinguist Res 1, 1–29 (1971). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01066934

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01066934

Keywords

Navigation