Skip to main content
Log in

Does Habit Interference Explain Moral Failure?

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Social psychologists have performed many well-known experiments demonstrating that experimental subjects will perform in ways that are normatively inconsistent even across very similar situations. Situationist social psychologists and philosophers have often interpreted these findings to imply that most people lack general moral dispositions. These situationists have argued that our moral dispositions are at best narrowly local traits; they often describe our moral characters as fragmented. In this paper, I offer an alternative hypothesis for the same experimental results. I argue that these normative inconsistencies in behavior might well be produced by habit interference: experimental subjects err by over-generalizing dispositions formed in prior situations. I ground this alternative hypothesis in the long tradition of transfer of learning studies, which demonstrated that cognitive inconsistency was often the result of habit interference and, hence, overly generalized dispositions. I shall thus explore the analogy between moral and cognitive inconsistency to show why social psychology might well benefit from adopting the experimental design of the classic transfer of learning studies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although “cognitive” psychology is often contrasted with Thorndike’s “behaviorism,” in this paper I will contrast Thorndike’s “cognitive” situationism with Ross and Nisbett’s “social” situationism.

  2. Doris (2002: 179n 38) does acknowledge the seminal influence of Thorndike in a footnote: “The theoretical perspective Hartshorne and May espoused was suggested more than two decades earlier by Thorndike (1906: 248), but Hartshorne and May’s work is generally taken to be the first significant empirical study suggesting such a view.” Actually, as we shall see, Thorndike and others conducted many empirical studies claiming to show the specificity of cognitive dispositions; Hartshorne and May claimed to show the specificity of moral dispositions. Daniel Russell (2009: 252) traces situationism only back to Mischel: “It seems safe to say that the school of thought in empirical psychology we now call situationism first rallied as an identifiable movement with the appearance of Michel’s landmark 1968 book, Personality and Assessment.”

  3. By contrast, the moral situationism of Hartshorne and May and their successors was subjected to scrutiny by philosophers, such as William Alston (1975). Since the publication of Walter Mischel’s (1968) critical review of the technical literature in personality psychology and Ross and Nisbett’s (1991) review of social psychology in relation to moral and political conduct, philosophers John Doris (1998, 2002, 2005, 2010), Gilbert Harman (1999, 2000, 2003, 2009), Peter Vranas (2005, 2009) and others have deployed the findings of social psychology, largely as interpreted by Mischel, Ross, and Nisbett, to make the case against the traditional psychology of general dispositions thought to underlie the moral virtues. Meanwhile, philosophers Joel Kupperrman (2001), Gopal Sreenivasan (2002), Robert Solomon (2003), Nafsika Athanassoulis (2000), Christian Miller (2003, 2009), Julia Annas (2003), Rachana Kamtekar (2004), and Daniel Russell (2009), among others, have all, to varying degrees, defended traditional virtue theory.

  4. In the vast array of experiments inspired by Darley, Milgram, Zimbardo, etc. only a tiny handful ever treated their subjects as potential learners. For examples of experiments attempting to measure whether subjects could learn to disobey authorities, see Blass (2000) and Tarnow (2000).

  5. Milgram himself (1974: 133–145) interpreted his experiments to reveal a strong, general disposition to obey authorities.

  6. To translate Aristotle into modern psychology “every instance of learning is a function of the already existent learned organization of the subject; that is, all learning is influenced by transfer” (McGeoch 1952: 346).

  7. The converse is not widely accepted among psychologists. As Doris explains: “Not every consistent behavior pattern is telling evidence for trait attribution: If someone consistently behaves gregariously across a run of situations where most everyone would, their behavior is not decisive evidence for extraversion. Rather, it is individuating behavior—behavior that is outside the population norm for a situation—that counts as evidence for trait attribution” (Doris 2002: 19).

  8. Peter Vranas says that “most people are fragmented [his emphasis]” (Vranas 2005: 1). Gilbert Harman says that social psychology implies “fragmentation” (Harman 2003: 88).

  9. Each philosopher no doubt means something different by “fragmented.” Vranas alone attempts to clarify what he means by “fragmented”: “My definition of fragmentation makes no presuppositions about why the agent behaves sometimes deplorably and other times admirably; in particular, the definition does not presuppose that the agent has a ‘modular mind’ (Fodor 1983) or a ‘fragmented psyche’ consisting of good and evil parts interlocked in a Manichean struggle” (Vranas 2005: 4).

  10. Jesse Prinz makes the same rash inference: “studies show that a relatively minor situation manipulation with no obvious moral significance exerts a major influence on people’s moral behavior….This suggests that if people have traits, they may be narrower than the traits postulated by virtue theorists” (2009: 119).

  11. On similarity as the basis for habit interference, see Postman (1971: 1053–1054, 1088, 1104, 1116, 1117).

  12. Even strength training in the right hand and the right arm alone measurably increased the strength of the left hand and left arm. Training one hand to draw or throw a ball had much larger effects on the other hand.

References

  • Alston, William. 1975. Traits, consistency and conceptual alternatives for personality theory. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 5: 17–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, John R. 1993. Rules of the mind. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, John R., and Mark K. Singley. 1993. The identical elements theory of transfer. In Rules of the mind, ed. John R. Anderson, 183–204. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, Julia. 2003. Virtue ethics and social psychology. A Priori 2: 20–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2008. Experiments in ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. The complete works of Aristotle. Ed. Jonathan Barnes, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Asch, S.E. [1952] 1987. Social psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Athanassoulis, Nafsika. 2000. A response to Harman: Virtue ethics and character traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 215–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagley, W.C. 1905. Educative process. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C. Daniel. 1991. The altruism question. Hilsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergström, John A. 1894. The relation of the interference to the practice effect of an association. American Journal of Psychology 6(3): 433–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blass, Thomas. 2000. The milgram paradigm after 35 years: Some things we now know about obedience to authority. In Obedience to authority, ed. Blass Thomas, 35–59. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourke, Vernon J. 1941. Saint Thomas and the transfer of intellectual skills. Modern Schoolman 18: 69–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castiello, Jaime. 1934. Geistesformung: Beiträge zur experimentellen erforschung der formalen bildung. Berlin: Dümmlers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castiello, Jaime. 1936a. The psychology of habit in St. Thomas Aquinas. Modern Schoolman 14: 8–12.

  • Castiello, Jaime. 1936b. The psychology of classical training. Thought 10: 632–654.

  • Castiello, Jaime. 1936c. A humane psychology of education. New York: Sheed and Ward.

  • Coxe, Warren W. 1924. “The Influence of Latin on the Spelling of English Words” in Journal of Educational Research Monographs no. 7 (Bloomington IL: Public School Publishing): 1–121.

  • Darley, J.M., and C.D. Batson. 1973. From Jerusalem to Jericho: A study of situationist and dispositional variables in helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27: 100–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 1998. Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Noûs 32: 504–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 2002. Lack of character. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 2005. Replies: Evidence and sensibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Review 71(3): 656–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. 1983. Modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 1999. Moral philosophy meets social psychology. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99: 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 2000. The nonexistence of character traits. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 223–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 2003. No character or personality. Business Ethics Quarterly 13: 87–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 2009. Skepticism about character traits. The Journal of Ethics 13: 235–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, Hugh, and Mark May. 1928. Studies in the nature of character Vol. 1: Studies in deceit. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, Hugh, Mark May, and Julius Maller. 1929. Studies in the nature of character Vol. 2: Studies in service and self-control. New York: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, Hugh, Mark May, and Frank Shuttleworth. 1930. Studies in the nature of character Vol. 3: Studies in the organization of character. New York: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hewins, Nellie P. 1916. The doctrine of formal discipline in the light of experimental investigation. Baltimore: Warwick and York. (= Journal of Educational Psychology Monographs no. 16).

  • Judd, Charles H. 1908. The relation of special training to general intelligence. Educational Review (June): 28–42.

  • Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar, Rachana. 2004. Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character. Ethics 114: 458–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kline, Linus. 1914. Some experimental evidence in regard to formal discipline. Journal of Educational Psychology 5: 259–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klubertanz, George. 1965. Habits and virtues. New York: Appleton-Century.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kupperman, Joel. 1991. Character. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kupperman, Joel. 2001. The indispensability of character. Philosophy 76: 239–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Dahai, Nikolas D. Macchiarella, Elizabeth L. Blickensderfer, and Dennis A. Vincenzi et al. 2009. Transfer of training. In Human factors in simulation and training, ed. Vincenzi Dennis et al. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

  • Luchins, Abraham S. 1942. Mechanization in problem solving: The effect of Einstellung in psychological monographs 54/6.

  • McGeoch, John A. 1952. The psychology of human learning. New York: Longmans, Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, Stanley. 1974. Obedience to authority. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Christian. 2003. Social psychology and virtue ethics. The Journal of Ethics 7: 365–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Christian. 2009. Empathy, social psychology, and global helping traits. Philosophical Studies 142: 247–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mischel, Walter. 1968. Personality and assessment. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mischel, Walter, and Philip Peake. 1982. Beyond Déjà Vu in the search for cross-situationist consistency. Psychological Review 89(6): 730–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orata, Pedro. 1928. The theory of identical elements. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postman, Leo. 1971. Transfer, interference, and forgetting. In Experimental psychology, ed. J.W. Kling and Riggs Lorrin, 1019–1132. New York: Holt, Reinhart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, Jesse. 2009. The normativity challenge: Cultural psychology provides the real threat to virtue ethics. The Journal of Ethics 13: 117–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reason, James. 1990. Human error. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reason, James, and Klara Mycielska. 1982. Absent-minded? Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, Brent, and Eva Pomerantz. 2004. On traits, situations, and their integration: A developmental perspective. Personality and Social Psychology 8(4): 402–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Lee, and Richard E. Nisbett. 1991. The person and the situation. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruediger, William C. 1908. The indirect improvement of mental function thru ideals. Educational Review (November): 364–371.

  • Rugg, Harold Ordway. 1916. The experimental determination of mental discipline in school studies. Baltimore: Warwick and York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Daniel. 2009. Practical intelligence and the virtues. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siipola, Elsa M., and Harold E. Israel. 1933. Habit-interference as dependent upon stage of training. The American Journal of Psychology 45: 205–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singley, Mark K., and John R. Anderson. 1989. The transfer of cognitive skill. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert C. 2003. Victims of circumstances? A defense of virtue ethics in business. Business Ethics Quarterly 13: 42–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert C. 2005. What’s character got to do with it? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71/3 (November).

  • Sreenivasan, Gopal. 2002. Errors about errors: Virtue theory and trait attribution. Mind 111(441): 47–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, Gopal. 2008. Character and consistency: Still more errors. Mind 117(467): 603–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarnow, Eugen. 2000. Self-destructive obedience in the airplane cockpit and the concept of obedience optimization. In Obedience to authority, ed. Blass Thomas, 111–123. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1906. Principles of teaching. New York: A. G. Seiler.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1909. A note on the specialization of mental functions with varying content. Journal of Philosophy 6: 239–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1910. Relation between memory for words and memory for number. American Journal of Psychology 2: 487–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1913. Educational psychology, vol. 2. New York: Teachers College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1914. Educational psychology: Briefer course. New York: Teachers College, Columbia University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E.L. 1922. The effect of changed data upon reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology 5: 33–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E. L. 1924. Mental discipline in high school studies in The Journal of Educational Psychology 15: 1–22 and 83–98.

  • Thorndike, E.L., and R. S. Woodworth. 1901. The influence of improvement of one mental function upon the efficiency of other functions. The Psychological Review 8: 247–261, 384–395, 553–564.

  • Vranas, Peter. 2005. The indeterminacy paradox: Character evaluations and human psychology. Noûs 39(1): 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas, Peter. 2009. Against moral character evaluations: The undetectability of virtue and vice. The Journal of Ethics 13: 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, Louie Winfield. 1917. Transfer of training and retroaction. Psychological Monographs 24: 1–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodworth, Robert S., and Harold Schlosberg. 1954. Experimental psychology. New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimbardo, Philip, Christina Maslach, and Craig Haney. 2000. Reflections on the Stanford prison experiment. In Obedience to authority, ed. Blass Thomas, 193–237. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Bernard Murphy.

Additional information

I am indebted to discussions about this paper with my colleague, Benjamin Valentino, and to the editorial assistance of Grace Park and Yevgenia Rem.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Murphy, J.B. Does Habit Interference Explain Moral Failure?. Rev.Phil.Psych. 6, 255–273 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0220-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0220-5

Keywords

Navigation