Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Happiness Inequality: How Much is Reasonable?

  • Published:
Social Indicators Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We compute the Gini indexes for income, happiness and various simulated utility levels. Due to decreasing marginal utility of income, happiness inequality should be lower than income inequality. We find that happiness inequality is about half that of income inequality. To compute the utility levels we need to assume values for a key parameter that can be interpreted as a measure of relative risk aversion. If this coefficient is above one, as many economists believe, then a large part of happiness inequality is not related to pecuniary dimensions of life.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for instance Ott (2005), Borooah (2006), Duncan (2010) and Veenhoven (2005).

  2. Layard et al. (2008) take a similar approach to estimate how fast marginal utility of income decreases as income increases. Using a similar methodology Gandelman and Hernandez-Murillo (2011) estimate risk aversion from happiness data.

  3. By conservative we mean that we are not inducing an artificially low level of utility inequality.

  4. Unlike ρ, k does not bear a direct interpretation. It is needed only to be able to compute the Gini.

  5. For a justification of this cardinality assumption see Van Praag and Ferrer-i-Carbonell (2004).

References

  • Bartunek, K., & Chowdhury, M. (1997). Implied risk aversion parameter from option prices. The Financial Review, 32(1), 107–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borooah, V. K. (2006). How much happiness is there in the world? Across-country study. Applied Economics Letters, 13, 483–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Central Intelligence Agency. (2009). The World Factbook. Washington, DC.

  • Duncan, G. (2010). Should happiness-maximization be the goal of government? Journal of Happiness Studies, 11(2), 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friend, I., & Blume, M. (1975). The demand for risky assets. American Economic Review, 65(5), 900–922.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gandelman, N., & Hernández Murillo, R. (2011). What happiness data tell us about relative risk aversion? unpublished.

  • Halek, M., & Eisenhauer, J. (2001). Demography or risk aversion. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 68(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, L., & Singleton, K. (1983). Stochastic consumption, risk aversion and the temporal behavior of asset returns. Journal of Political Economy, 91(2), 249–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Institute for Economics and Peace. (2010). The Global Peace Index. NSW 1590, Sydney, Australia.

  • Kalmijn, W., & Veenhoven, R. (2005). Measuring inequality of happiness in nations: In search for proper statistics. Journal of Happiness Studies, 6, 357–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R., Nickell, S., & Mayraz, R. (2008). The marginal utility of income. Journal of Public Economics, 92(8), 1846–1857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mankiw, N. G. (1985). Consumer durables and the real interest rate. Review of Economics and Statistics, 67(3), 353–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ott, J. (2005). Level and inequality of happiness in Nations: Does greater happiness of a greater number imply greater inequality in happiness? Journal of Happiness Studies, 6, 397–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segarra, E. (2006) What happened to the distribution of income in Puerto Rico during the last three decades of the XX Century? A statistical point of view, UPR, Río Piedras, No. 129.

  • Szpiro, G. (1986). Measuring risk aversion: An alternative approach. Review of Economics and Statistics, 68(1), 156–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • VanPraag, B., & Ferrer-i-Carbonell, A. (2004). Happiness quantified, a satisfaction calculus approach. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (2005). Return of inequality in modern society? Test by dispersion of life-satisfaction across time and nations. Journal of Happiness Studies, 6(4), 457–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, W. (1975). Interest rates, inflation, and consumer expenditures. American Economic Review, 65(5), 843–858.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Bank. (2009). World development indicators. Washington DC: World Bank.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors thank Diego Lamé for his research assistance.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Néstor Gandelman.

Appendix: Relative Risk Aversion

Appendix: Relative Risk Aversion

The first and second derivatives of the utility function are:

$$ u'(y) = y^{ - \rho } $$
(2)
$$ u''(y) = - \rho y^{ - \rho - 1} . $$
(3)

A risk neutral individual is indifferent between receiving a payment of $x and a lottery that pays either $x + $z or $x−$z with a probability of 0.5 for each outcome. A concave utility function represents risk averse individuals that strictly prefer the payment of $x over participating in the lottery. A commonly used measure of risk aversion is the Arrow–Pratt coefficient of relative risk aversion, r R .

$$ r_{R} = y\frac{u''(y)}{u'(y)}. $$
(4)

Substituting (2) and (3) in (4) we get:

$$ r_{R} = \rho . $$
(5)

By now there have been almost 30 years of applied research in risk aversion. Surprisingly, there is not yet a commonly accepted estimate of the coefficient ρ. Although many economists probably believe that the coefficient of relative risk aversion is between 1 and 2, there is a wide range of measures for this coefficient (Table 5).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Happiness inequality versus income inequality

Table 5 Gini income

The following list is not an exhaustive survey of the literature on risk aversion, instead representing only a small portion of the research efforts in this area. Friend and Blume (1975), studying the demand for risky assets, find that relative risk aversion generally exceeds 1 and probably is above 2. Weber (1975), using expenditure data, and Szpiro (1986) using data on property insurance, estimate relative risk aversion to be in the range between 1.3 and 1.8. Using consumption data, Hansen and Singleton (1983) report lower estimates, between 0.68 and 0.97. Also using data on consumption, Mankiw (1985) finds much larger estimates in the range of 2.44–5.26. Halek and Eisenhauer (2001), using data on life insurance, estimate demographic differences in risk attitudes. They find an average relative risk aversion coefficient of 3.75, but a much lower median risk aversion coefficient of 0.9. Bartunek and Chowdhury (1997) use data from index option prices and estimate low risk aversion coefficients in the range of 0.2–0.3. The authors go into great pains to explain why their results are so different from the rest of the literature. The reasons provided suggest that their results are biased downwards.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gandelman, N., Porzecanski, R. Happiness Inequality: How Much is Reasonable?. Soc Indic Res 110, 257–269 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-011-9929-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-011-9929-z

Keywords

Navigation