Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Gender and physics: feminist philosophy and science education

  • Preclinical Study
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Physics education reform movements should pay attention to feminist analyses of gender in the culture of physics for two reasons. One reason is that feminist analyses contribute to an understanding of a ‘chilly climate’ women encounter in many physics university departments. Another reason is that feminist analyses reveal that certain styles of doing science are predominant in the culture of physics. I introduce recent philosophical work in social epistemology to argue that the predominance of certain styles of doing science is not good for science. Scientific communities would benefit from greater diversity in styles of doing science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The notion of a ‘style of doing science’ is introduced to feminist science studies by Jane Roland Martin (1988). Martin (1988) argues that Evelyn Fox Keller’s (1983) account of Barbara McClintock’s scientific practice and June Goodfield’s (1981) account of ‘Anna Brito’s’ scientific practice are testimonies of certain styles of doing science (Anna Brito is a pseudonym for a Portuguese female scientist). Both McClintock’s and Brito’s styles of doing science are characterized by a structure of emotion, imagination, and experience which is connected to friendship and love. Thus, a style of doing science may be idiosyncratic as in the case of McClintock and Brito, or it may reflect a particular culture of science which is communicated in popular science literature, science fiction, biographies of scientists, and every-day interactions in science education and research. See Hacking (1992) for a history of the notion of ‘style’ in science studies.

  2. To be precise, Solomon (2001) claims that we should give up the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic factors. She suggests that we refer to all motivational factors with an epistemologically neutral term, ‘decision vector’ (2001, p 53). Yet, she retains a distinction between two types of decision vectors, empirical and non-empirical. According to her definitions, ‘empirical decision vectors are causes of preference for theories with empirical success, either success in general or one success in particular’ (2001, p 56), whereas ‘non-empirical decision vectors are other reasons or causes for choice’ (2001, p 56). However, it is not clear what status some of those values that have traditionally been deemed as ‘epistemic’, have in Solomon’s social empiricism. For example, Robert Klee criticizes Solomon for ignoring the epistemic role of consistency or ‘closure under logical consequences’ (Klee 2003, p 250). On the one hand, consistency seems to be a ‘non-empirical decision vector’ because it is a desideratum that we impose on our knowledge claims. On the other hand, consistency seems to have a different status from other ‘non-empirical decision vectors’ because it is derived from the value of truth. Insofar as theories in science are expected to be true, they are not allowed to include inconsistent statements. Also, Klee argues that we should inquire whether some theoretical values such as elegance and simplicity have a special status which distinguishes them from other ‘non-empirical decision vectors’ (2003, p 249).

References

  • Anderson E (1995) Knowledge, human interests, and objectivity. Philos Top 23(2):27–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Barinaga M (1994) Surprises across the cultural divide. Science 263(11 March):1467–1472

    Google Scholar 

  • Brickhouse NW (2001) Embodying science: a feminist perspective on learning. J Res Sci Teach 38(3):282–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brickhouse NW, Potter JT (2001) Young women’s scientific identity formation in an urban context. J Res Sci Teach 38(8):965–980

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bug A (2003) Has feminism changed physics? Signs 28(3):881–899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz JR (1995) Improving the climate for women in physics. A report presented at the 1995 departmental chair conference, American Physical Society. http://www.aps.org/jobs/dcc/conf95/index.cfm

  • Fuller S (1988) Social epistemology. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodfield J (1981) An imagined world: a story of scientific discovery. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (1998) Science as social—yes and no. In: Haack S (ed) Manifesto of a passionate moderate. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 104–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (2003) Knowledge and propaganda: reflections of an old feminist. In: Pinnick C, Koertge N, Almeder R (eds) Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: an examination of gender and science. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, pp 7–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1992) ‘Style’ for historians and philosophers. Stud Hist Philos Sci 23(1):1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1999) The social construction of what? Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig J (1991) The role of trust in knowledge. J Philos 88(12):693–708

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger S (2000) Gender and race: (what) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Noûs 34(1):31–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasse C (2002a) Gender diversity in play with physics: the problem of premises for participation in activities. Mind Cult Act 9(4):250–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasse C (2002b) Learning physics space: the social designation of institutional culture. Folk J Dan Ethnographic Soc 44:171–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivie R, Czujko R, Stowe K (2001) Women physicists speak: the 2001 international study of women in physics. http://www.aip.org/statistics/trends/reports/iupap.pdf

  • Keller EF (1983) A feeling for the organism: the life and work of Barbara McClintock. W.H. Freeman & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters K (eds) (2006) Scientific pluralism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

  • Kitcher P (1992) Authority, deference, and the role of individual reasoning in science. In: McMullin E (ed) The social dimensions of science. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 244–271

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Klee R (2003) Watch out for those decision vectors. Metascience 12:249–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koertge N (2003) Gender and the genealogy of scientific discoveries. In: Pinnick C, Koertge N, Almeder R (eds) Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: an examination of gender and science. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, pp 47–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1977) Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In: Kuhn TS (ed) The essential tension: selected studies in scientific tradition and change. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 320–339

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (1990) Science as social knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (1995) Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese 104(3):383–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (2002) The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin JR (1988) Science in a different style. Am Philos Q 25(2):129–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick C (2000) Veritistic epistemology and feminist epistemology: a rational epistemics? Soc Epistemol 14(4):281–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick C (2003) Feminist epistemology: implications for philosophy of science. In: Pinnick C, Koertge N, Almeder R (eds) Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: an examination of gender and science. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, pp 20–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick C (2005) The failed feminist challenge to ‘fundamental epistemology’. Sci Educ 14:103–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin K (1999) Can gender ideologies influence the practice of the physical sciences? Perspect Sci 7(4):510–533

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin K (2004) Why gender is a relevant factor in the social epistemology of scientific inquiry? Philos Sci 71(5):880–891

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser SV (1995) Reaching the majority: retaining women in the pipeline. In: Rosser SV (ed) Teaching the majority: breaking the gender barrier in science, mathematics and engineering. Teachers College Press, New York, pp 1–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayre A (1975) Rosalind Franklin and DNA. W.W. Norton & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon M (2001) Social empiricism. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson JD (1968) The double helix. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheim M (1995) Pythagoras’ trousers: God, physics, and the gender wars. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2002) The epistemic significance of collaborative research. Philos Sci 6(1):150–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2006) Scientific authorship in the age of collaborative research. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37(2006):505–514

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Cassandra Pinnick and K. Brad Wray for their comments on earlier versions of this paper. I am also grateful to two reviewers of Science and Education for their suggestions to improve the paper. Cathrine Hasse and the UPGEM project funded by the European Commission have provided me a valuable opportunity to discuss gender and physics.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristina Rolin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rolin, K. Gender and physics: feminist philosophy and science education. Sci & Educ 17, 1111–1125 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-006-9065-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-006-9065-3

Keywords

Navigation