Skip to main content
Log in

Rule consequentialism and disasters

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Rule consequentialism (RC) is the view that it is right for A to do F in C if and only if A’s doing F in C is in accordance with the set of rules which, if accepted by all, would have consequences which are better than any alternative set of rules (i.e., the ideal code). I defend RC from two related objections. The first objection claims that RC requires obedience to the ideal code even if doing so has disastrous results. Though some rule consequentialists embrace a disaster-clause which permits agents to disregard some of the rules in the ideal code as a necessary means of avoiding disasters, they have not adequately explained how this clause works. I offer such an explanation and show how it fits naturally with the rest of RC. The second disaster objection asserts that even if RC can legitimately invoke a disaster-clause, it lacks principled grounds from distinguishing disasters from non-disasters. In response, I explore Hooker’s suggestion that “disaster” is vague. I contend that every plausible ethical theory must invoke something similar to a disaster clause. So if “disaster” is vague, then every plausible ethical theory faces a difficulty with it. As a result, this vagueness is not a reason to prefer other theories to RC. However, I argue, contra Hooker, that the sense of “disaster” relevant to RC is not vague, and RC does indeed have principled grounds to distinguish disasters from non-disasters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For helpful discussion of some of the varieties of consequentialism, see Brink (2006) and Sinnott-Armstrong (2006).

  2. On our ordinary conception of morality, see what Parfit (1984, pp. 95–116) calls “Common-Sense morality” or simply “M,” what Kagan (1989, pp. 1–46) calls “ordinary morality,” and what is often called “folk morality” by those working in and around experimental philosophy such as Knobe (2003).

  3. In this paper, I limit myself to discussion of agent-based restrictions and do not address the parallel issue of agent-based prerogatives.

  4. For discussions of alternative forms of indirect consequentialism, see e.g., Adams (1976), Railton (1988), Crisp (1992), Brandt (1996), and—despite her own characterization—Driver (2003).

  5. I omit all page numbers from references to this forthcoming book since I have only an MS copy of it.

  6. A highly abbreviated list of philosophers working on rule consequentialism (or something very similar) includes Harsanyi (1977), Brandt (1979), Hooker (2000), Mulgan (2006; though compare his 2001, especially Chaps. 3 and 8), Ridge (2006), Parfit (2011), as well as Kahn (Unpublished 1) and Kahn (Unpublished 2).

  7. Compare, e.g., Brandt (1979, pp. 193–199), Hooker (2000, p. 32), and Mulgan (2006, p. 184).

  8. E.g., Kagan (1989, p. 37) and Brandt (1996, pp. 145–155).

  9. Obviously, more realistic thought experiments of this sort are possible, but they require much more qualification and take up considerably more room as a result. So I avoid them here. I turn to variations of Torture-1 in Sect. 4.

  10. Also see Smart (1956), Foot (1985), Brandt (1979, pp. 278–285), Parfit (1984, pp. 30–31), Foot (1985), Brink (1989, p. 237), Kagan (1989, pp. 36–37, 1998, pp. 231–232), and de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2010).

  11. This is the model suggested in Hooker (2008). See also Kagan (1998, p. 232).

  12. See, e.g., Brandt (1979, p. 181), Kagan (1989, p. 37), and Hooker (2000, pp. 78–80).

  13. This is the model suggested in Hooker (2000, pp. 98–99).

  14. See especially Williams (1985, pp. 185–187) and Brandt (1996, pp. 70–71). I discuss this point at length in Kahn (2011) and Kahn (Forthcoming).

  15. I omit all page numbers from references to this paper since at the moment I lack access to the journal and have only an text copy of it. See also Harrison (1979), Lyons (1994), and de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2010).

  16. Lyons (1965). The literature on this subject is too large to cite in any detail here, but for an overview of more recent work see Kagan (1998, pp. 225–230), Hooker (2000, pp. 93–99), and Mulgan (2006, pp. 137–140).

  17. Also see Driver (2002), Mulgan (2006, especially, pp. 301–339), and Hooker (2009).

  18. Beginning, it seems to me, primarily with Williamson (1994).

  19. Discussed, e.g., by Smart (1956), Kagan (1989, pp. 32–37), and Darwall (1998, p. 137).

  20. See also Hare (1981, p. 150), Parfit (1984, Chapts. 1, 4, and 5), Railton (1988, pp. 168–174), Brink (1989, pp. 216–217), Brandt (1996, pp. 142–145), and Kagan (1998, pp. 68, 70, and 224).

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1976). Motive utilitarianism. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 467–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. B. (1972). Utilitarianism and the rules of war. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1, 145–162. Reprinted in Brandt, R. B. (1992). Morality, utilitarianism, and rights (336–353). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Brandt, R. B. (1979). A theory of the good and the right. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. B. (1996). Facts, values, and morality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (2006). Some forms and limits of consequentialism. In D. Copp (Ed.), Oxford handbook in ethical theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (1992). Utilitarianism and the life of virtue. Philosophical Quarterly, 42, 139–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (1997). Mill on utilitarianism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (1998). Philosophical ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Lazari-Radek, K., & Singer, P. (2010). Secrecy in consequentialism: A defense of esoteric morality. Ratio, 23, 34–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2002). Review of ideal code, real world by brad Hooker. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=1136

  • Driver, J. (2003). Uneasy virtue. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, T. (2001). Law is necessarily vague. Legal Theory, 7, 377–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1985). Utilitarianism and the virtues. Mind 94, 196–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its level, methods, and point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, J. (1979). Rule utilitarianism and cumulative utilitarianism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 5, 21–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrod, R. M. (1936). Utilitarianism revised. Mind, 45, 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. (1977). Rule utilitarianism and decision theory. Erkenntnis, 11, 25–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2000). Ideal code, real world: A rule-consequentialist theory of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2005). Reply to Arneson and McIntyre. Philosophical Issues, 15, 264–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2008). Act-consequentialism versus rule-consequentialism. Politeia, 24, 75–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2009). The demandingness objection. In T. Chappell (Ed.), The moral problem of demandingness (pp. 148–162). London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2010). Publicity in morality: Reply to de Lazari-Radek and Singer. Ratio, 23, 111–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (2000). Evaluative focal points. In B. Hooker, E. Mason, & D. Miller (Eds.), Morality, rules, and consequences: A critical reader (pp. 134–155). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, L. (2011). Conflict, regret, and modern moral philosophy. In T. Brooks (Ed.), New waves in ethics. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, L. (Forthcoming). Regret. In H. LaFolette (Ed.), International encyclopedia of ethics. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Kahn, L. How many codes are ideal? Unpublished 1.

  • Kahn, L. Ideal codes and the problem of partial compliance. Unpublished 2.

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63, 190–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, D. (1965). Forms and limits of utilitarianism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, D. (1994). Rights, welfare, and mill’s moral theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, T. (2001). The demands of consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, T. (2006). Future people. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1984). Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13, 134–171. Reprinted in Railton, P. (2003). Facts, values, and norms: Essays toward a morality of consequence (pp. 151–186). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Railton, P. (1988). How thinking about character and utilitarianism might lead to rethinking the character of utilitarianism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 13. Reprinted in Railton, P. (2003). Facts, values, and norms: Essays toward a morality of consequence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Ridge, M. (2006). Introducing variable-rate rule-utilitariansim. Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 242–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Consequentialism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/.

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1956). Extreme and restricted utilitarianism. Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 344–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I am very grateful to Dale Miller for his helpful comments on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leonard Kahn.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kahn, L. Rule consequentialism and disasters. Philos Stud 162, 219–236 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9756-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9756-8

Keywords

Navigation