Skip to main content
Log in

Science and Fiction: Analysing the Concept of Fiction in Science and its Limits

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A recent and growing discussion in philosophy addresses the construction of models and their use in scientific reasoning by comparison with fiction. This comparison helps to explore the problem of mediated observation and, hence, the lack of an unambiguous reference of representations. Examining the usefulness of the concept of fiction for a comparison with non-denoting elements in science, the aim of this paper is to present reasonable grounds for drawing a distinction between these two kinds of representation. In particular, my account will suggest a demarcation between fictional and non-fictional discourse as involving two different ways of interpreting representations. This demarcation, leading me to distinguish between fictional and non-fictional forms of enquiry, will provide a useful tool to explore to what extent the descriptions given by a model can be justified as making claims about the world and to what degree they are a consequence of the model’s particular construction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This concerns propositions such as “Sherlock Holmes is a detective” versus “Sherlock Holmes is the fifth member of the Sign of Four”.

  2. Existence here means the physical existence of entities, that is their concrete being in space and time, and does not involve any possible metaphysical existence of fictional entities (Frigg 2010, 247).

  3. A question arising here is whether fiction might be said to be accidentally true. Consider, for instance, the possibility that we find a real person that matches every description of a fictional character’s biography without the author’s knowledge. Is the fictional character now a true description of the real person? A discussion of such an example can be found in (Ryle 1933): “Now suppose by sheer chance, without any knowledge of Dickens, one person had existed, such that the Pickwick Papers were in fact faithful biography. […] it seems obvious that we could not say of the real Mr. Pickwick> Oh, he is not identical with the hero of the story <.” An alternative answer is given in (Danneberg 2006a) Cited is the extended online version: (Danneberg 2006b, 14). I agree with Danneberg that the reason why we intuitively suggest the fictional character is a faithful depiction of a real person only rests on intuition based on a structural similarity by coincidence. There is, however, no causal connection that would allow for the justification of this inference. Therefore, fiction might seem accidentally true, but still lacks argumentative justification for the truthfulness of its claims.

  4. Note Eco's own quotation marks.

  5. The hermeneutic rules that regulate the reference to general knowledge are the so-called reality principle and the more restrictive mutual belief principle. The principle of reality states that the interpretation of a representation is guided by the assumption of its closest resemblance to the external world. This means that unless there are descriptions suggesting otherwise, for instance, by leading to a contradiction or formulating explicit differences, a representation depends on the same language conventions and truths as the real world. A contextually and historically restrictive version of the reality principle is the mutual belief principle; closest resemblance here is characterised by the norms and conventions that had been held true at the time of the creation of the representation. (Walton 1990, 144–161; Margolin 1991, 109–110).

  6. By virtue of their similarity to fiction yet their different epistemic function, examples such as thought experiments, counterfactuals and ceteris paribus clauses have been characterised as ‘Neighbouring Notions’ elsewhere (Albrecht and Danneberg 2011). An analysis of idealisations and theoretical models in comparison with thought experiments, counterfactuals or ceteris paribus clauses might thereby be insightful. Sudgen (2000), for instance, nicely explores theoretical models in economy in this context), yet these do not necessarily describe cases of ‘fiction’ and an analysis of them would, unfortunately, go beyond the scope of this paper.

References

  • Albrecht, A., & Danneberg, L. (2011). First steps toward an explication of counterfactual imagination. In D. Birke, M. Butter, & T. Köppe (Eds.), Counterfactual thinking/counterfactual writing (pp. 12–29). New York: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berczeller, P. (2003). Death in the snow. http://www.guardian.co.uk/culture/2003/jun/06/artsfeatures1. Accessed 31 Feb 2013.

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casanova, G. (2007 [1725–1798]). The complete memoirs of Jacques Casanova (A. Machen, Trans.): Clue.

  • Coen, J., & Coen, E. (1996). Fargo. PolyGram Filmed and Metro-Goldwyn Mayer.

  • Crasto, C. J. (2009). Computational biology of olfactory receptors. Current Bioinformatics, 4(1), 8–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danneberg, L. (2006a). Weder Tränen noch Logik. Über die Zugänglichkeit fiktionaler Welten. In U. Klein, K. Mellmann, & S. Metzger (Eds.), Heuristiken der Literaturwissenschaft. Einladung zu disziplinexternen Perspektiven auf Literatur (pp. 35–83). Paderborn: Mentis Verlag.

  • Danneberg, L. (2006b). Weder Tränen noch Logik. Über die Zugänglichkeit fiktionaler Welten. http://fheh.org/images/fheh/material/danneberg-fiktion.pdf. Accessed 31 Feb 2013.

  • Eco, U. (1994). Six walks in the fictional woods. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1962). Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (pp. 28–97). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1993). Fictionalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2002). Models and representation. Why structures are not enough. http://www.romanfrigg.org/writings/Models_and_Representation.pdf. Accessed 31 Feb 2013.

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Fiction in science. In J. Woods (Ed.), Fiction and models. New essays (pp. 247–287). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1969). Languages of art. An approach to a theory of symbols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harries, K. (2002). Infinity and perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heintz, J. (1979). Reference and inference in fiction. Poetics, 8, 85–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry III, W. A., Lee, G., & Ludtke, M. (1983). http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,923630,00.html. Accessed 31 Feb 2013.

  • Johansson, I., & Lynøe, N. (2008). Medicine & philosophy: A twenty-first century introduction. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1973). Bob and carol and ted and alice. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 490–518). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kay, L. E. (2000). Who wrote the book of life? A history of the genetic code. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kepler, J. (1965 [1634]). Kepler’s Dream (L. John, Trans.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Kripke, S. A. (2011). Vacuous names and fictional entities. In S. A. Kripke (Ed.), Philosophical troubles: Collected papers (Vol. 1, pp. 52–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970[1962]). The structure of scientific revolutions (2ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolin, U. (1991). The nature and function of fiction. Some recent views. Canadian review of comparative literatureRevue Canadienne de Littérature Comparée, 19, 101–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space and time, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 3, pp. 3–27). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1904). Über Gegenstandtheorie. In A. Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandtheorie und Psychologie. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. (2002). Models, stories and the economic world. In In U. Mäki (Ed.), Fact and fiction in economics (pp. 178–201). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (1999). Models as autonomous agents. In M. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators. Perspectives on natural and social science (pp. 38–65). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parson, T. (1980). Nonexistent objects. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2003). Meinongianism and the philosophy of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 11, 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘‘meaning’’. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science Lang Mind Knowl (Vol. 7, pp. 131–193). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (Ed.). (2003). The philosophy of scientific experimentation. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2005). A reply to David Bloor: Toward a sociology of epistemic things. Perspectives on Science, 13, 408.

  • Ryle, G. (1933). Imaginary objects. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 2, 18–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1998). Nonexistence. Noûs, 32(3), 277–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, C. (2006). Science as science fiction. Johannes Kepler’s Somnium and the Poetics of Invention. In T. Bernhart & P. Mehne (Eds.), Imagination und Innovation, Paragrana, Internationale Zeitschrift für Historische Anthropologie (Beiheft 2) (pp. 259–268). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1975). The logical status of fictional discourse. New Literary History. On Narrative and Narratives, 6(2), 319–332.

  • Searle, J. R. (2010). Making the social world. The structure of human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (1999). Theories, models and representations. In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 75–83): Kluwer.

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (Ed.). (2009). Fiction in science. Philosophical essays on modelling and idealisation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Fictions, inference and realism. In J. Woods (Ed.), Fictions and models: New essays (pp. 225–245). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2010). Models as make-believe. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/3227/1/Adam_Toon_-_Models_as_make-believe.pdf. Accessed 31 Feb 2013.

  • Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe: Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vaihinger, H. (2008 [1928]). The philosophy of as if. London: Taylor and Francis.

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representations. Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughn, M. (2011). X-Men: First class. Marvel Studios 20th Century Fox.

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werle, D. (2006). Fiktion und Dokument. Überlegungen zu einer gar nicht so prekären Relation mit vier Beispielen aus der Gegenwartsliteratur. Non Fiktion, 1, 112–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2009). A function for fictions. Expanding the scope of science. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Fiction in science. Philosophical essays on modelling and idealisation (pp. 179–190). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamora-Bonilla, J., & de Donato-Rodríguez, X. (2009). Explanation and idealization in a comprehensive inferential approach. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/5263/. Accessed 1 Aug 2013.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ann-Sophie Barwich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Barwich, AS. Science and Fiction: Analysing the Concept of Fiction in Science and its Limits. J Gen Philos Sci 44, 357–373 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9228-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9228-2

Keywords

Navigation