Skip to main content
Log in

Meat made us moral: a hypothesis on the nature and evolution of moral judgment

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the first part of the article, an account of moral judgment in terms of emotional dispositions is given. This account provides an expressivist explanation of three important features of moral demands: inescapability, authority independence and meriting. In the second part of the article, some ideas initially put forward by Christopher Boehm are developed and modified in order to provide a hypothesis about the evolution of the ability to token moral judgments. This hypothesis makes evolutionary sense of inescapability, authority independence and meriting. It does so by referring to the selection pressures generated in the Late Pleistocene by large-game hunting. If the hypothesis is correct, we can say that, in a sense, meat made us moral.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Morally required” and “morally forbidden” are interdefinable: something is morally forbidden if and only if not doing it is morally required. “Morally required” and “morally permissible” are also inter-definable: something is morally permissible if and only if it is not morally required not to do it.

  2. Various influential objections to expressivism are discussed in the meta-ethical literature. As said, this literature will not be addressed here. For some useful suggestions about how to deal with these objections, see in particular Blackburn (1998) and Gibbard (2003).

  3. Cf. Blackburn (1998) and Prinz (2007) for similar accounts of meriting, though neither of them thinks meriting is essential to moral judgment. One might object that accounts of meriting of this kind capture only in part the phenomenon that cognitivists like McDowell are trying to capture. It is certainly true that the account presented here is, in a sense, ‘deflationary’, the main idea being that, to the extent that those that in the literature talk about meriting are referring to a real phenomenon, this phenomenon, while important, amounts to nothing more than meta-anger, meta-guilt and their effects.

  4. Is not it possible to have moral judgments without dispositional meta-emotions and vice versa? Consider someone who is disposed to feel meta-anger at etiquette violations. Would this person thereby judge etiquette violations to be morally wrong? According to H, if the other three dispositions are also present, then yes, this person moralizes etiquette, she regards etiquette violations as morally wrong, contrary to what most people do (at least in contemporary Western societies). Conversely, suppose you cannot help feeling anger at the wrongdoings of psychopaths but, because you are aware that some psychological mechanisms in the minds of psychopaths malfunction (see below), you have no longer a disposition to blame those who do not feel anger at the wrongdoings of psychopaths. That is, your knowledge of psychopathic minds affects your dispositions to feel second-order anger but not your dispositions to feel first-order anger. In this case, according to H, you would not any more judge the wrongdoings of psychopaths to be morally wrong (as opposed to undesirable, regrettable, etc).

  5. Joyce (2002) argues that moral norms are different from rules of etiquette because they have (putative) authority independence in addition to inescapability. We agree with Joyce but we are not committed to his cognitivist characterization of authority independence in terms of reasons for action. We characterize authority independence in a more neutral way.

  6. Turiel’s distinction between moral and conventional norms has been questioned by Kelly et al. (2007). See Sousa (2009), Fraser (2012) for replies. Some of Kelly’s results will be re-interpreted below.

  7. Again, one might object the account of inescapable authority presented here captures only in part the phenomenon that cognitivist authors like Joyce and Mackie are trying to capture. It is certainly true that the account is, in a sense, ‘deflationary’. The main idea is that, to the extent that these authors are referring to a real phenomenon, this phenomenon, while important, amounts to nothing more than the robustness described above.

  8. We can consider a scenario like this: you have some strong desire that can only be satisfied by violating a practical demand that you take to be a moral demand. You know that violating the moral demand will make you feel guilt unless you find ways to avoid the guilt feeling. You start considering stratagems for avoiding the guilt-feeling, such as getting drunk or distracted. The thought of such plans will in general trigger meta-guilt, which will motivate you not to pursue them.

  9. Psychopaths understand inescapability: they understand that some norms (rules of etiquettes, laws of the state, etc.) apply to them irrespective of their interests.

  10. So, why does this happen at 3½? Perhaps it is because children at that age become able to imagine situations where the authorities tell them that some violations are okay, or they become able to emotionally respond to such imaginings. This needs further investigation. Nichols (2004) offers an account of which violations are likely to trigger in children emotional responses that are robust with respect to imagined changes in the preferences of authorities. Much of what he says on this issue is consistent with the account given here.

  11. There is also some evidence that people are disposed to punish in-group violators of norms more severely than out-group violators (Shinada et al. 2004).

  12. An individual has high cultural fitness if, e.g. due to his perceived success, his traits are more likely to be copied by other individuals in the group.

  13. Despite being unsatisfactory, Boehm’s account constitutes important progress relative to most other accounts of the evolution of morality in the literature, which routinely conflate the evolution of morality with the evolution of altruistic tendencies and ‘social instincts’ (cf. also Darwin 1871). Prosocial attitudes and the ability to token moral judgments are doubly dissociable.

  14. Bunn (2006) claims that ‘meat made us human’: he does not talk about morality, but his view is that large-game hunting (and power scavenging before it) selected, directly or indirectly, for many important and distinctive features of human beings.

References

  • Alexander RD (1987) The biology of moral systems. Aldine, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Barr A (2001) Social dilemmas and shame-based sanctions: experimental results from rural Zimbabwe. The Centre for the Study of African Economies Working Paper Series 149: http://www.bepress.com/csae/paper149

  • Barrett KC, Zahn-Waxler C, Cole PM (1993) Avoiders versus amenders: implications for the investigation of guilt and shame during toddlerhood? Cogn Emot 7:481–505

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson M, Nettle D, Roberts G (2006) Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biol Lett 2:412–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedford OA (2004) The individual experience of guilt and shame in Chinese culture. Culture Psychol 10:29–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benedict R (1947) The chrysanthemum and the sword. Secker & Warburg, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn S (1998) Ruling passions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJ (1995) A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJ (1997) Moral reasoning and the child with psychopathic tendencies. Pers Individ Dif 26:731–739

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bochet O, Page T, Putterman L (2006) Communication and punishment in voluntary contribution experiments. J Econ Behav Organ 60(1):11–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boehm C (2005) Interactions of culture and natural selection in the middle and late Stone Age. In: Jaisson P, Levinson S (eds) Evolution and culture (79–103). MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm C (2007) Conscience origins, sanctioning selection, and the evolution of altruism in Homo Sapiens. Department of Anthropology, University of Southern California

  • Boehm C (2008) Purposive social selection and the evolution of human altruism. Cross-Cultural Res 42:319–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boehm C (2012) Moral origins. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles S, Gintis H (2011) A cooperative species human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Boyd R, Richerson P (1992) Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethol Sociobiol 13:171–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson P (2005) The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunn HT (2006) Meat made us human. In: Ungar P (ed) Evolution of the human diet. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 191–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlsmith JM, Gross AE (1969) Some effects of guilt on compliance. J Pers Soc Psychol 11(3):232–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlsmith KM, Darley JM, Robinson PH (2002) Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. J Pers Soc Psychol 83:284–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casimir MJ, Schnegg M (2002) Shame across cultures: the evolution, ontogeny and function of a “Moral Emotion”. In: Keller H, Poortina YH, Scholmerich A (eds) Between biology and culture (270–300). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chekroun P, Brauer M (2002) The bystander effect and social control behavior: the effect of the presence of others on people’s reactions to norm violations. Eur J Soc Psychol 32:853–867

    Google Scholar 

  • Creighton M (1988) Revisiting shame and guilt cultures: a forty-year pilgrimage. Ethos 18:279–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms J, Jacobson D (2000) Sentiment and value. Ethics 110:722–748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio A (1994) Descartes’ Error. Putnam Publishing, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Darley JM, Pittman TS (2003) The psychology of compensatory and retributive justice. Pers Soc Psychol Rev 7:324–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall S, Gibbard A, Railton P (1992) Toward fin de siècle ethics: some trends. Philoso Rev 101:115–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1871) The descent of man. Murray, Lodon

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • DeHooge IE, Breugelmans SM, Zeelenberg M (2007) Moral sentiments and cooperation: differential influences of shame and guilt. Cogn Emot 21:1025–1042

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeWaal FBM (1982) Chimpanzee politics. Cape, London

    Google Scholar 

  • DeWaal FBM (1996) Good natured. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dominguez-Rodrigo M, Pickering TR, Diez-Martín F, Mabulla A, Musiba C, Trancho G, Baquedano E, Bunn HT, Barboni D, Santonja M, Uribelarrea D, Ashley GM, Martinez-Avila M, Barba R, Gidna A, Yravedra J, Arriaza C (2012) Earliest porotic hyperostosis on a 1.5-million-year-old Hominin, Olduvai Gorge, Tanzania. PLoS ONE 7(10):e46414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg N (2000) Emotion, regulation, and moral development. Annu Rev Psychol 51:665–697

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2004) Third-party punishment and social norms. Evol Hum Behav 25:63–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Gächter S (2002) Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415:137–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schneider F (2010) Eyes are on us, but nobody cares: are eye cues relevant for strong reciprocity? Proc R Soc B 277(1686):1315–1323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot P (1972) Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philos Rev 81(3):305–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser B (2012) The nature of moral judgements and the extent of the moral domain. Philos Explor 15(1):1-16

    Google Scholar 

  • Gächter S, Fehr E (1999) Collective action as social exchange. J Econ Behav Organ 39(4):341–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1990) Wise feelings, apt choices. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (2003) Thinking how to live. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Graeber D (2011) Debt. Melville House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruter M, Masters RD (eds) (1987) Ostracism: a social and biological phenomenon. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108(4):814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2012) The righteous mind. Pantheon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare RD (1993) Without conscience. Simon & Schuster, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare RM (1952) The language of morals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J, Boyd R (2001) Why people punish defectors: weak conformist transmission can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in cooperative dilemmas. J Theor Biol 208:79–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill KR, Walker RS, Bozicevic M, Eder J, Headland T, Hewlett B, Hurtado AM, Marlowe F, Wiessner P, Wood B (2011) Co-Residence patterns in hunter-gatherer societies show unique human social structure. Science 331(6022):1286–1289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman ML (1997) Varieties of empathy-based guilt. In: Bybee J (ed) Guilt in children (91–112). Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone IL (1992) Direction of fit. Mind 101(401):59–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2002) The myth of morality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2006) The evolution of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones W, Kugler K, Adams P (1995) You always hurt the one you love: Guilt and transgressions against relational partners. In: Fisher K, Tangney J (eds) Self-conscious emotions: the psychology of shame, guilt, embarrassment and pride (301–321). Guilford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly D, Stich S, Haley K, Eng S, Fessler D (2007) Harm, affect and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind & Language 22(2):117–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ketelaar T, Au WT (2003) The effects of feelings of guilt on the behavior of uncooperative individuals in repeated social bargaining games: an affect-as-information interpretation of the role of emotion in social interaction. Cogn Emot 17:429–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiehl KA (2006) A cognitive neuroscience perspective on psychopathy: evidence for paralimbic system dysfunction. Psychiatry Res 142:107–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiehl KA (2008) Without morals: the cognitive neuroscience of psychopathy. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology, volume 3: the neuroscience of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochanska G, Gross JN, Lin MH, Nichols KE (2002) Guilt in young children: development, determinants, and relations with a broader system of standards. Child Dev 73:461–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy N (2007) The responsibility of the psychopath revisited. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 14(2):129–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis M (1998) Emotional competence and development. In: Pushkar D, Bukowski MW, Schwartzman AA, Stack DM, White DR (eds) Improving competence across the lifespan, 27–36. Plenum Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutwak N, Razzino BE, Ferrari JR (1998) Self-perception and moral affect: an exploratory analysis of subcultural diversity in guilt and shame emotions. J Soc Behav Pers 13(2):333–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon BE, Montgomerie R (2012) Sexual selection is a form of social selection. Philos Trans R Soc B 367:2266–2273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1985) Values and secondary qualities. In: Honderich T (ed) Morality and objectivity. Routledge & Kegan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • McMillen DL, Austin JB (1971) Effect of positive feedback on compliance following transgression. Psychon Sci 24:59–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie J (1977) Ethics. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli M (2004) The role of emotions in ecological and practical rationality. In: Evans D, Cruse P (eds) Emotion, evolution, and rationality (158–178). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli M (2013) Emotions, motivation and moral beliefs. In: Sterelny K, Joyce R, Calcott B, Fraser B (eds) Cooperation and its evolution (525–548). MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Masclet D, Noussair C, Tucker S, Villeval M (2003) Monetary and nonmonetary punishment in the voluntary contributions mechanism. Am Econ Rev 93(1):366–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele A (1996) Internalist moral cognitivism and listlessness. Ethics 106:727–753

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S (2004) Sentimental rules. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen RMA, Dijker AJ, deVries NK (2007) How to turn a hawk into a dove and vice versa: interactions between emotions and goals in a give-some dilemma game. J Exp Soc Psychol 43:280–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen RMA, Zeelenberg M (2009) Moral emotions as determinants of third-party punishment: anger, guilt, and the functions of altruistic sanctions. Judgm Decis Mak 7(4):543–553

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen RMA, Leliveld MC, vanDijk E, Zeelenberg M (2011) Fear and guilt in proposers: using emotions to explain offers in ultimatum bargaining. Eur J Soc Psychol 41(1):78–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nucci L (1985) Children’s conceptions of morality, societal convention and religious prescription. In: Harding C (ed) Moral dilemmas (137–174). Precedent Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Nucci L, Turiel E (1993) God’s word, religious rules, and their relation to Christian and Jewish children’s concepts of morality. Child Dev 74(5):1475–1491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunner-Winkler G, Sodian B (1988) Children’s understanding of moral emotions. Child Dev 59:1323–1338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niedenthal P, Tangney J, Gavenski I (1994) “If only I weren’t” versus “If only I hadn’t”: distinguishing shame and guilt in counterfactual thinking. J Pers Soc Psychol 67(4):585–595

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland NK, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction. Princenton University Press, Princenton

    Google Scholar 

  • Piers G, Singer MB (1971) Shame and guilt. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2007) The emotional construction of morals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rege M, Telle K (2004) The impact of social approval and framing on cooperation in public good situations. J Public Econ 88(7–8):1625–1644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson P, Boyd R (2005) Not by genes alone. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozin P, Lowery L, Imada S, Haidt J (1999) The CAD triad hypothesis: a mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). J Pers Soc Psychol 76:574–586

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shinada M, Yamagishi T, Ohmura Y (2004) False friends are worse than bitter enemies: “altruistic” punishment of in-group members. Evol Hum Behav 25:379–393

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shweder RA, Much NC, Mahapatra M, Park L (1997) The “Big Three” of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the “Big Three” explanations of suffering. In: Brandt A, Rozin P (eds) Morality and health (119–69). Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Smetana J, Braeges J (1990) The development of toddlers’ moral and conventional judgments. Merrill-Palmer Q 36(3):329–346

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith EA (1981) The application of optimal foraging theory to the analysis of hunter-gatherer group size. In: Winterhalder B, Smith EA (eds) Hunter-gatherer foraging strategies: ethnographic and archaeological analysis. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1994) The moral problem. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sousa P (2009) On testing the ‘moral law’. Mind Lang 24:209–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada C, Stich S (2006) A framework of the psychology of norms. In: Carruthers P, Laurence S, Stich S (eds) The innate mind: culture and cognition (280–301). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiner M, Barkai R, Gopher A (2009) Cooperative hunting and meat sharing 400–200 kya at Qesem Cave, Israel. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106(32):13207–13212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tangney J (1998) How does guilt differ from shame? In: Bybee J (ed) Guilt and children (1–17). Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangney J, Dearing RL (2002) Shame and guilt. Guilford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers RL (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q R Biol 46:35–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel E (1998) The development of morality. In: Damon W, Eisenberg N (eds) Social, emotional, and personality development: Handbook of child psychology, vol 3. 5th edn. Wiley, New York, p 863–932

  • West-Eberhard MJ (1979) Sexual selection, social competition, and evolution. Proc Am Philos Soc 123(4):222–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1987) Needs, values, truth. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Fontana, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1993) Shame and necessity. University of California Press, California

    Google Scholar 

  • Winterhalder B (2001) Intragroup resource transfers: comparative evidence, models, and implications for human evolution. In: Stanford CB, Bunn HT (eds) Meat-eating and human evolution (279–301). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong Y, Tsai J (2007) Cultural models of shame and guilt. In: Tracy JL, Robins RW, Tangney JP (eds) The self-conscious emotions: theory and research (209–223). Guilford, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank the following people for comments and discussion: two anonymous referees, Kim Sterelny, Cecilia Heyes, James Maclaurin, David Papineau, Lisa Bortolotti, Nicholas Shea, Iván Darío González Cabrera, and the audience at ISHPSSB 2013 and at FOLSATEC/SEMM.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matteo Mameli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mameli, M. Meat made us moral: a hypothesis on the nature and evolution of moral judgment. Biol Philos 28, 903–931 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9401-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9401-3

Keywords

Navigation