Skip to main content
Log in

Decision sciences and the new case for paternalism: three welfare-related justificatory challenges

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Several authors have recently advocated a so-called new case for paternalism, according to which empirical findings from distinct decision sciences provide compelling reasons in favour of paternalistic interference. In their view, the available behavioural and neuro-psychological findings enable paternalists to address traditional anti-paternalistic objections and reliably enhance the well-being of their target agents. In this paper, I combine insights from decision-making research, moral philosophy and evidence-based policy evaluation to assess the merits of this case. In particular, I articulate and defend three complementary arguments that, I claim, challenge even the best available calls for such case. In doing so, I identify the main justificatory challenges faced by the new paternalists and explicate the implications of these challenges for the ongoing philosophical debate about the justifiability of paternalistic interference.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some authors put forward different characterizations of paternalism (e.g. Shiffrin 2000, holds that not all paternalistic interferences aim to enhance the well-being of the targeted agents, and Sunstein and Thaler 2003, do not regard violations of agents’ autonomy as a necessary condition for counting interventions as paternalistic). Still, I take the tripartite characterization in the text to be sufficiently precise for the purpose of my evaluation and sufficiently general to cover many entrenched characterizations of paternalism (see e.g. Dworkin 2010; New 1999; Wilson 2011).

  2. I am not concerned with assessing how the notion of autonomy is most aptly conceptualized. For my evaluation, it suffices to note that many paternalists and anti-paternalists alike hold that individuals have an interest in deliberating and acting in light of considered judgments about their own well-being, and that this interest is plausibly understood as an interest in autonomy (see e.g. Dworkin 1988, ch.1, and Hausman and Welch 2010). Some works relate paternalism to interventions that violate the freedom of choice (rather than the autonomy) of their target agents (see e.g. Carter 1999, ch.8, and Carter 2014). I mention only autonomy in the text for expositional convenience. I take my critique of the NCP to hold mutatis mutandis for characterizations of paternalism that relate it to interventions that violate agents’ freedom of choice (rather than autonomy).

  3. Several questions arise concerning the notion of consent (e.g. what circumstances license inferring that an agent consents to a particular interference? Under what conditions does consent count as fully informed or ideally rational?). I do not expand on these issues since the cogency of my evaluation does not rest on what position one holds about them (for a recent discussion, see e.g. Groll 2012; Husak 2010).

  4. The new paternalists typically allege that the interventions they advocate are superior to traditional paternalistic interventions in each of these three respects, individually considered, but rarely examine how such interventions fare in all those respects, collectively considered. I explore this issue’s implications for the NCP in Sect. 5.

  5. Anti-paternalists may draw on both deontological and consequentialist considerations to support these autonomy-related concerns. By way of illustration, suppose facing some agents engaged in self-regarding conduct that has no direct and significant effects on the well-being of others. A consequentialist may argue that since many agents value the opportunity to make autonomous decisions, and since giving agents opportunities they value often enhances their well-being, paternalistic interventions that frustrate this opportunity rarely turn out to be welfare-enhancing (see e.g. Sugden 2004).

  6. Not all conceptions of autonomy are equally hospitable to these considerations. For instance, some Kantians would presumably object that autonomous agency cannot be subjected to the instrumental considerations seemingly involved in the aforementioned intertemporal trade-offs. I expand in Sect. 5 on the justificatory challenges that violations of autonomy pose to the NCP.

  7. This obviously does not preclude one from opposing such interventions on other grounds. For instance, one may act on preferences that are not stable under reflection, be aware that her preferences are unstable, and yet attribute a high importance to the opportunity to satisfy her unstable preferences (see e.g. Sugden 2006, 2007). Furthermore, many individuals have strong preferences against having their preference-formation mechanisms influenced by third parties’ interference, and the new paternalists’ interventions often frustrate such preferences (see e.g. Sugden 2013).

  8. Similar concerns arise in relation to the possibility that paternalistic interference may lead to agents’ infantilization. The idea is that paternalistic interventions neither help nor incentivize their target agents to develop effective decision-making skills and make welfare-enhancing decisions for themselves (see e.g. Bovens 2009).

  9. A new paternalist might object that if some paternalistic intervention is welfare-enhancing, then such intervention is ipso facto justified. However, this objection presupposes that the welfare implications of paternalistic interference include all the factors pertaining to the justifiability of such interference, and the new paternalists have not offered convincing support to this welfarist presupposition (see e.g. Kagan 1992; Sobel 1998, for a discussion of the role autonomy considerations can be taken to play in the definition and measurement of well-being).

  10. Other authors (e.g. Glaeser 2006; Rizzo and Whitman 2009b) put forward epistemic and evidential criticisms of the NCP. My remarks agree with these informative criticisms in spirit, but are grounded in a different conceptualization of paternalism and do not imply that the information required to implement welfare-enhancing interventions is “in principle” unavailable to paternalists (Rizzo and Whitman 2009b, 159).

References

  • Anderson J (2010) Review of Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein: nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Econ Philos 26:369–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archard D (1993) Self-justifying paternalism. J Value Inquiry 27:341–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson RJ (1980) Mill versus paternalism. Ethics 90:470–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson RJ (1999) Human flourishing versus desire satisfaction. Soc Philos Policy 16(1):113–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson RJ (2005) Joel Feinberg and the justification of hard paternalism. Leg Theory 11(3):259–284

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber BM, Odean T (2001) Boys will be: gender, overconfidence, and common stock investment. Q J Econ 116:261–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Gill O, Sunstein CR (2015) Regulation as delegation. J Legal Anal 7(1):1–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister R (2002) Yielding to temptation: self-control failure, impulsive purchasing, and consumer behavior. J Consum Res 28(4):670–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister R, Bratslavsky E, Muraven M, Tice D (1998) Ego depletion: is the active self a limited resource? J Pers Soc Psychol 74(5):1252–1265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister R, Vohs KD (2004) Handbook of self-regulation: research, theory, and applications. Guilford, Marquette

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner T, Heinrichs M, Vonlanthen A, Fischbacher U, Fehr E (2008) Oxytocin shapes the neural circuitry of trust and trust adaptation in humans. Neuron 58(4):639–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD (2009) On the potential of neuroeconomics: a critical (but hopeful) appraisal. Am Econ J Microecon 1:1–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Rangel A (2007) Toward choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Am Econ Rev 97:464–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhargava S, Loewenstein G (2015) Behavioral economics and public policy 102: beyond nudging. Am Econ Rev 105:396–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogg T, Roberts BW (2004) Conscientiousness and health-related behaviors: a meta-analysis of the leading behavioral contributors to mortality. Psychol Bull 130:887–919

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonell C, McKee M, Fletcher A, Wilkinson P, Haines A (2011) One nudge forward. Two steps back. Br Med J 342:d401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens L (2009) The ethics of nudge. In: Grüne-Yanoff T, Hansson SO (eds) Preference change: approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology, vol 10. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubb R, Pildes R (2014) How behavioral economics trims its sails and why. Harv Law Rev 127:1593–1678

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullock EC (2015) A normatively neutral definition of paternalism. Philos Q 65(258):1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF (2006) Wanting, liking, and learning: neuroscience and paternalism. Univ Chicago Law Rev 73(1):87–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF, Issacharoff S, Loewenstein G, O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (2003) Regulation for conservatives: behavioral economics and the case for asymmetric paternalism. Univ Pa Law Rev 151:1211–1254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter I (1999) A measure of freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carter I (2014) Is the capability approach paternalist? Econ Philos 30:75–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carver CS, Scheier MF (1998) On the self-regulation of behavior. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen S (2013) Nudging and Informed Consent. Am J Bioethics 13(6):3–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2006) Hedonism reconsidered. philos phenomenol res 73:619–645

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall S (2006) The value of autonomy and the autonomy of the will. Ethics 116:263–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Marneffe P (2006) Avoiding paternalism. Philos Public Affair 34(1):68–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener E, Seligman M (2004) Beyond money. Toward an economy of well-being. Psychol Sci Public Int 5:1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (1972) Paternalism. Monist 56:64–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (1983) Paternalism: some second thoughts. In: Sartorius R (ed) Paternalism. University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota, pp 19–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (1988) The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (2005) Moral paternalism. Law Philos 24:305–319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (2010) Paternalism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/paternalism/

  • Elster J (1984) Ulysses and the sirens: studies in rationality and irrationality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah MJ (2012) Neuroethics: the ethical, legal, and societal impact of neuroscience. Ann Rev Psychol 63:571–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J (1971) Legal paternalism. Can J Philos 1:106–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J (1986) Harm to self. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman F (1997) On the intrinsic value of pleasures. Ethics 107:448–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsen G, Castelo N, Reiner P (2013) Decisional enhancement and autonomy: public attitudes towards overt and covert nudges. Judgm Decis Making 8:202–213

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishbach A, Trope Y (2005) The substitutability of external control and self-control. J Exp Soc Psychol 41:256–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli R (2013) The futile search for true utility. Econ Philos 29:325–347

  • Gigerenzer G (2015) On the supposed evidence for libertarian paternalism. Rev Philos Psychol 6:361–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaeser E (2006) Paternalism and psychology. Univ Chicago Law Rev 73:133–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (1986) Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Groll D (2012) Paternalism, respect, and the will. Ethics 122(4):692–720

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala F (2005) The methodology of experimental economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guala F, Mittone L (2015) A political justification of nudging. Rev Philos Psychol 6(3):385–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2010) Hedonism and welfare economics. Econ Philos 26:321–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2011) Mistakes about preferences in the social sciences. Philos Soc Sci 41:3–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2012) Preference, value, choice, and welfare. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2016) On the econ within. J Econ Methodol 23:26–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM, McPherson MS (2009) Preference satisfaction and welfare economics. Econ Philos 25:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM, Welch B (2010) Debate: to nudge or not to nudge. J Polit Philos 18(1):123–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husak D (2010) Paternalism and consent. In: Miller F, Wertheimer A (eds) The ethics of consent. Theory and practice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 107–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Infante G, Lecouteux G, Sugden R (2016) Preference purification and the inner rational agent: a critique of the conventional wisdom of behavioural welfare economics. J Econ Methodol 23:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls C, Sunstein CR (2006) Debiasing through law. J Legal Stud 35(1):199–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan J (2012) Psychology’s ghosts. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan S (1992) The limits of well-being. Soc Philos Policy 9:169–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1797) MM. The metaphysic of morals. Prussian Academy Volume VI. Transl Gregor, M [1996] Cambridge

  • Klick J, Mitchell G (2006) Government regulation of irrationality: moral and cognitive hazards. Minn Law Rev 90:1620–1663

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld M, Heinrichs M, Zak PJ, Fischbacher U, Fehr E (2005) Oxytocin increases trust in humans. Nature 435:673–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Grand J, New B (2015) Government Paternalism: nanny state or helpful friend? Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Loewenstein G, Bryce C, Hagmann D, Rajpal S (2015) Warning: you are about to be nudged. Behav Sci Policy 1:35–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein G, Haisley E (2008) The economist as therapist: methodological ramifications of ’Light’ paternalism. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) Perspectives on the future of economics: positive and normative foundations, Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Mill JS (1859) On liberty. Bobbs-Merrill [1956]

  • Mitchell G (2005) Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwest Univ Law Rev 99(3):1245–1277

    Google Scholar 

  • New B (1999) Paternalism and public policy. Econ Philos 15:63–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC, Sen A (1993) The quality of life. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (2006) Optimal sin taxes. J Public Econ 90:1825–1849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford Paperbacks, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Qizilbash M (2012) Informed desire and the ambitions of libertarian paternalism. Soc Choice Welf 38:647–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlinski J (2003) The uncertain psychological case for paternalism. Northwest Univ Law Rev 97(3):1165–1225

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo MJ, Whitman DG (2009a) Little brother is watching you: new paternalism on the slippery slopes. Arizona Law Rev 51:685–739

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo MJ, Whitman DG (2009b) The knowledge problem of the new paternalism. Brigham Young University Law Review, pp 103–161

  • Rubinstein A, Arad A (2015) The people’s perspective on libertarian-paternalistic policies. At: http://www.tau.ac.il/~aradayal/LP.pdf

  • Rubinstein A, Salant Y (2012) Eliciting welfare preferences from behavioral datasets. Rev Econ Stud 79:375–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salant Y, Rubinstein A (2008) (A, f): choice with frames. Rev Econ Stud 75:1287–1296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson W, Zeckhauser R (1988) Status Quo bias in decision making. J Risk Uncertain 1:7–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin SV (2000) Paternalism, unconscionability doctrine, and accommodation. Philos Public Affairs 29:205–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel D (1998) Well-being as the object of moral consideration. Econ Philos 14(2):249–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stijn D, Vanrie J, Dreesen A, Brijs T (2010) Additional road markings as an indication of speed limits: results of a field experiment and a driving simulator study. Acc Anal Prevent 42(3):953–960

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2004) The opportunity criterion: consumer sovereignty without the assumption of coherent preferences. Am Econ Rev 94:1014–1033

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2006) Taking unconsidered preferences seriously. In: Olsaretti S (ed) Preferences and well-being. Paperback, Oxford, pp 209–232

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2007) The value of opportunities over time when preferences are unstable. Soc Choice Welf 29:665–682

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2008) Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Const Polit Econ 19:226–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2013) The behavioural economist and the social planner: to whom should behavioural welfare economics be addressed? Inquiry 56:519–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sumner LW (1995) The subjectivity of welfare. Ethics 105:764–790

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (2013a) Deciding by default. Univ Pa Law Rev 162:1–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (2013b) The Storrs lectures: behavioral economics and paternalism. Yale Law J 122:1826–1899

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (2015) Nudging and choice architecture: ethical considerations. Yale J Regul. At: http://www.law.harvard.edu/programs/olin_center/papers/pdf/Sunstein_809.pdf

  • Sunstein CR, Thaler RH (2003) Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. Univ Chicago Law Rev 70(4):1159–1202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2003) Libertarian paternalism. Am Econ Rev 93(2):175–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • Trope Y, Fishbach A (2000) Counteractive self-control in overcoming temptation. J Pers Soc Psychol 79(4):493–506

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout JD (2005) Paternalism and cognitive bias. Law Philos 24:393–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout JD (2009) The empathy gap. Building bridges to the good life and the good society. Viking/Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science 185:1124–1131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman JD (1999) A right to self-termination? Ethics 109:606–628

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voorhoeve A (2013) Response to Rabin. In: Oliver A (ed) Behavioural public policy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 140–147

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstein ND, Klein WM (2002) Resistance of Personal risk perceptions to debiasing interventions. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 313–323

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • White M (2013) The manipulation of choice: ethics and libertarian paternalism. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson TM (2013) Nudging and manipulation. Polit Stud 61(2):341–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willis LE (2013) When nudges fail: slippery defaults. Univ Chicago Law Rev 80:1115–1229

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson J (2011) Why it’s time to stop worrying about paternalism in health policy. Public Health Ethics 4(3):269–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zamir E (1998) The efficiency of paternalism. Virgin Law Rev 84(2):229–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Richard Arneson, Boudewijn de Bruin, Daniel Hausman, Christian Piller, Mario Rizzo, Ariel Rubinstein, Rudolf Schussler, Bob Sugden, Attila Tanyi, J.D. Trout and Alex Voorhoeve for their comments on previous versions of this paper. I also benefited from the observations of two anonymous referees and audiences at the University of Hamburg, the Frankfurt School of Finance and Management, the University of Valencia, the University of Groningen, the University of Manchester, the University of Edinburgh, the University of York, and New York University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Fumagalli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fumagalli, R. Decision sciences and the new case for paternalism: three welfare-related justificatory challenges. Soc Choice Welf 47, 459–480 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0972-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0972-1

Keywords

Navigation