Skip to main content
Log in

Human Enhancement and Communication: On Meaning and Shared Understanding

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“The way we communicate with others and with ourselves ultimately determines the quality of our lives”. Anthony Robbins

Abstract

Our technologies have enabled us to change both the world and our perceptions of the world, as well as to change ourselves and to find new ways to fulfil the human desire for improvement and for having new capacities. The debate around using technology for human enhancement has already raised many ethical concerns, however little research has been done in how human enhancement can affect human communication. The purpose of this paper is to explore whether some human enhancements could change our shared lifeworld so radically that human communication as we know it would not be possible any longer. After exploring the kinds of communication problems we are concerned with as well as mentioning some possible enhancement interventions that could bring about such problems, we will address some of the ethical implications that follow from these potential communication problems. We argue that because of the role that communication plays in human society, this issue deserves attention.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here and in what follows we will be referring to the tools, methods, or substances used for the purposes of human enhancement as enhancement technologies (Coenen et al. 2009; Elliott 2003).

  2. According to Nagel (1974) points of view are shaped by values, beliefs, education, and other social and psychological factors (Nagel 1974).

  3. The term has been used widely by Habermas (1987) as the set of skills, competencies, knowledge and perceptions used by humans in order to negotiate their way through everyday life, that is to say by interacting with other people, understanding and manipulating their environments (physical and social) and themselves, differentiating distinct entities and events in the world, and ultimately creating and maintaining meaningful social relationships (Habermas 1987).

  4. We can imagine what would be like for me to behave as a bat, but not what it is like for a bat to be a bat (Nagel 1974). In that sense we are restricted to our biological and historical resources, and as such it is beyond our ability to conceive what it is like to be a bat.

  5. There would be of course still be private experiences that are accessible to only a particular individual, but we are concerned with the type of facts that we qua humans can have access to in general terms, and which are as such not limited to one’s own individual private experiences of the world.

  6. We might have partial understanding of certain facts, but not the kind of understanding that would be needed for meaningful human communication. However, up to certain level of meaning we could try to develop concepts that could be used to explain the objective facts of the world we live in.

  7. Wittgeinstein also uses the case of feeling pain as an experience in which in principle we can imagine someone else’s pain on the model of our own experience of pain. Although he also pointed out that this is already not an easy thing to do since “I have to imagine pain which I do not feel on the model of the pain which I do feel” (1953: 101). So even though one can empathize with someone else’s pain one still would not be able to experience that person’s pain (we can think for instance that they might be more sensitive to pain than I am or a difference like that).

  8. In this paper Jackson uses the case of Mary who knows everything about the science of colour but has never actually ‘experienced’ seeing colours because she is forced to investigate the world from a black and white room via a black and white television monitor.

  9. For instance these people could lead nocturnal lifestyles without having to depend on special infrastructure.

  10. If a few humans were enhanced with a new sense perhaps the situation would be more like this than like the blind in our society.

  11. Humans have also external devices that enable them to processes sound information in an analogous form to bat’s echolocation (e.g. sonar technology).

  12. Interestingly, Thaler and colleagues note that in early blind echolocation experts, the visual cortex is activated in response to auditory stimuli.

  13. In addition, partial understanding might be necessary but not sufficient for the type of meaningful communication that is needed in certain spheres of human communication.

  14. Some researchers have argued that epilectic individuals with seizures in certain areas of the brain can have intense, spiritual experiences and bursts of creativity (Ramachandran and Blakeslee 1999).

  15. Sacks’s has already put them to the test about their understanding of simple calculations such as multiplication or division of which they seem to have none. However, they had divided spontaneously “a compound number into three equal parts”.

  16. For instance, generally we believe that human beings see with their eyes; however, it does not matter which sense someone is using to gather data, rather it is how the brain interprets it what counts (“you don’t see with your eyes, you see with your brain” (Bach-y-Rita and Kercel 2003).

  17. Neurostimulation have already been used beyond just improving mood and mental function in patients with neuropsychiatric disorders, into enhancing certain features in normal people (Snyder et al. 2003).

  18. The computer game industry, for example funds many brain-computer interfaces designed to enable users to directly control their avatars in “virtual worlds” (Waters 2008). Other relevant non-medical arenas for the use of BCI are the automotive, telecommunication and robotics industries (F. Berger et al. 2008).

  19. For a case portraying this view see http://www.washingtonpost.com/national/on-innovation/ethics-in-the-age-of-acceleration/2012/07/13/gJQAzVDUiW_story.html.

  20. Presumably we can try to come up with ways to translate different experiences in order to communicate to others experiences that otherwise they cannot experience. But this takes us to Nagels point in which I might reach a partial understanding that is good enough to reach certain level of communication, but the more ones share lifeworld diverge from others the more likely meaningful communication would be impaired.

References

  • Bach-y-Rita, P., & Kercel, S. (2003). Sensory substitution and the human-machine interface. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(12), 541–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baylis, F. (2011). “I Am Who I Am”: On the perceived threats to personal identity from deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics, 1–14, doi:10.1007/s12152-011-9137-1.

  • Benali, A., Trippe, J., Weiler, E., Mix, A., Petrasch-Parwez, E., Girzalsky, W., et al. (2011). Theta-burst transcranial magnetic stimulation alters cortical inhibition. [Research Support, Non-U.S. Gov’t]. Journal of Neuroscience, 31(4), 1193–1203. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1379-10.2011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, T. W., Ahuja, A., Courellis, S. H., Deadwyler, S. A., Erinjippurath, G., Gerhardt, G. A., et al. (2005). Restoring lost cognitive function. IEEE Engineering in Medicine and Biology Magazine, 24(5), 30–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, F., Gevers, S., Siep, L., & Weltring, K.-M. (2008). Ethical, legal and social aspects of brain-implants using nano-scale materials and techniques. Nanoethics, 2(3), 241–249. doi:10.1007/s11569-008-0044-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blauert, J. (1997). Spatial hearing: The psychophysics of human sound localization. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1998). The annotated Alice: Alice’s adventures in wonderland and through the looking glass. New York: Wings Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coenen, C., Schuiff, M., Smits, M., Klaassen, P., Hennen, L., Rader, M., et al. (2009). Human enhancement. Study commissioned by the Science and Technology Options Assessment and carried out by the European Technology Assessment Group.

  • Council, N. R. (2009). Persistent forecasting of disruptive technologies. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennet, D. (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donoghue, J. P. (2002). Connecting cortex to machines: Recent advances in brain interfaces. Nature Neuroscience, 5, 1085–1088. doi:10.1038/Nn947.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donoghue, J. P. (2008). Bridging the brain to the world: A perspective on neural interface systems. Research Support, N.I.H., Extramural.

  • Dubiel, H. (2006). Deep in the brain: Living with Parkinson’s disease. (Trans: Philip, Schmidtz). New York: Europa Editions, 2009.

  • Edgar, A. (2009). The hermeneutic challenge of genetic engineering: Habermas and the transhumanists [Review]. Medicine Health Care and Philosophy, 12(2), 157–167. doi:10.1007/s11019-009-9188-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, C. (2003). Better than well: American medicine meets the American dream. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. J. (2010). Neuroethics : An introduction with readings (Basic bioethics). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. J., & Heberlein, A. S. (2007). Personhood and neuroscience: naturalizing or nihilating? [Research Support, N.I.H., Extramural]. The American Journal of Bioethics, 7(1), 37–48. doi:10.1080/15265160601064199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. J., & Wolpe, P. R. (2004). Monitoring and manipulating brain function: New neuroscience technologies and their ethical implications [Research Support, U.S. Gov’t, Non-P.H.S.]. Hastings Center Report, 34(3), 35–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glannon, W. (2007). Bioethics and the brain. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1993). Ethics and cognitive science. Ethics, 103(2), 337–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987). The theory of communicative action: Reason and the rationalization of society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2000). On the pragmatics of communication (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2003). The future of human nature. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Longo, M. (2010). You are what you touch: How tool use changes the brain’s representations of the body. Scientific American online.

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834. doi:10.1037//0033-295x.108.4.814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamani, C., McAndrews, M. P., Cohn, M., Oh, M., Zumsteg, D., Shapiro, C. M., et al. (2008). Memory enhancement induced by hypothalamic/fornix deep brain stimulation [Case Reports]. Annals of Neurology, 63(1), 119–123. doi:10.1002/ana.21295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayles, N. K. (1999). How we became posthuman: Virtual bodies in cybernetics, literature, and informatics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heinrichs, J.-H. (2012). The promises and perils of non-invasive brain stimulation. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 35(2), 121–129. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2011.12.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B. (2001). Active artificial echolocation and the nonvisual perception of aperture passability. Human Movement Science, 20(4–5), 371–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of the European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaming, L., & Haselager, P. (2010). Did my brain implant make me do it? Questions raised by DBS regarding psychological continuity, responsibility for action and mental competence. Neuroethics, 1–13. doi:10.1007/s12152-010-9093-1.

  • Luria, A. R. (1987). The mind of a mnemonist: A little book about a vast memory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magee, B., & Milligan, M. (1998). Sight unseen: Letters between Bryan Magee and Martin Milligan. Phoenix.

  • Maslow, A. H. (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review, 50, 370–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat. Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council. (2008). Emerging cognitive neuroscience and related technologies. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A. (2004). Converging technologies: Shaping the future of European societies. Report from the High Level Expert Group on “Foresighting the New Technology Wave”. Luxemburg.

  • Parens, E. (2005). Authenticity and ambivalence: Toward understanding the enhancement debate. The Hastings Center Report, 35(3), 34–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Passer, M., Smith, R., Atkinson, M., Mitchell, J., & Muir, D. (2005). Psychology: Frontiers and applications (Second Canadian ed). Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.

  • Ramachandran, V. S., & Blakeslee, S. (1999). Phantoms in the brain: Probing the mysteries of the human mind. Fourth Estate.

  • Ravitch, H. (1968). On gödel’s philosophy of mathematics. Los Angeles: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Research Support, U.S. Gov’t, Non-P.H.S. Neuron, 60(3), 511–521. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2008.10.037.

  • Roco, M. C., & Bainbridge, W. S. (2003). Converging Technologies for Improving Human Performance: Nanotechnology, Biotechnology. Information Technology and Cognitive Science.

  • Rosenblum, L., Gordon, M., & Jarquin, L. (2000). Echolocating distance by moving and stationary listeners. Ecological Psychology, 12(13), 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (1985). The man who mistook his wife for a hat and other clinical tales. New York, NY: Summit Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. (2009). The human prejudice and the moral status of enhanced beings: What do we owe the gods? In N. Bostrom & J. Savulescu (Eds.), Human enhancement (pp. 211–247). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, A. W., Mulcahy, E., Taylor, J. L., Mitchell, D. J., Sachdev, P., & Gandevia, S. C. (2003). Savant-like skills exposed in normal people by suppressing the left fronto-temporal lobe. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, 2(2), 149–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Society for Neuroscience. (2008a). Brain facts: A primer on the brain and nervous system.

  • Society for Neuroscience. (2008b). Neuroscience core concepts.

  • Stroffregen, T., & Pittenger, J. (1995). Human echolocation as a basic form of perception and action. Ecological Psychology, 7(3), 181–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, L., Arnott, S. R., & Goodale, M. A. (2011). Neural correlates of natural human echolocation in early and late blind echolocation experts. PLoS ONE, 6(5), e20162. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0020162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. C., & Sahakian, B. J. (2006). Neuroethics of cognitive enhancement. Biosocieties, 1(01), 113–123. doi:10.1017/S1745855205040044.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, D. (2008). Brain control headset for gamers. BBC News. Accessed 23 Oct 2009, from http://news.bb.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-2/hi/technology/7254078.stm.

  • Wells, H. G. (2006). The country of the blind, and other stories. Fairfield, IA: 1st World Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations: The English text of the third edition. NY: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpe, P. R., Foster, K. R., & Langleben, D. D. (2005). Emerging neurotechnologies for lie-detection: promises and perils. The American Journal of Bioethics, 5(2), 39–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper received constructive comments from Dr. Kiran Donaghe and from participants attending the seminar in the Centre of Applied Ethics in Linkoping, as well as those attending the Darmstadt 2010 S.NET conference. We also thank the two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments which helped to considerably improve the quality of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Laura Cabrera.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cabrera, L., Weckert, J. Human Enhancement and Communication: On Meaning and Shared Understanding. Sci Eng Ethics 19, 1039–1056 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-012-9395-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-012-9395-2

Keywords

Navigation