Skip to main content
Log in

Intrinsic value and the supervenience principle

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An important constraint on the nature of intrinsic value---the “Supervenience Principle” (SP)---holds that some object, event, or state of affairs ϕ is intrinsically valuable only if the value of ϕ supervenes entirely on ϕ's intrinsic properties. In this paper, I argue that SP should be rejected. SP is inordinately restrictive. In particular, I argue that no SP-respecting conception of intrinsic value can accept the importance of psychological resonance, or the positive endorsement of persons, in explaining value.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. Bradley (2002, p. 23). See also Moore (1951, p. 206).

  2. Korsgaard (1996, p. 253).

  3. Zimmerman (2001, p. 62).

  4. Not all people who identify “intrinsic value” with “final value” accept SP. See, for instance, Kagan (1998).

  5. See, for instance, Temkin (1993, p. 260).

  6. Lemos (1994, pp. 3–4).

  7. Ibid., p. 4.

  8. The obvious inspiration for this view is Mill (1861, Chap. II).

  9. Bradley (2002, p. 26). See also Zimmerman (2001, Chap. 3).

  10. Korsgaard (1996, p. 264).

  11. Ibid., p. 261.

  12. See, for instance, Heathwood (2008, p. 51).

  13. According to Ben Bradley, SP is a “non-negotiable” constraint on acceptable theories of well-being or relational intrinsic value. See Bradley (2009, pp. 19, 27).

  14. Griffin (1989, pp. 10–11) and Murphy (1999).

  15. See Griffin (1989, Chap. 2); for criticism, see Sobel (1994).

  16. Most importantly, see Railton (2002).

  17. See Lewis (2000).

  18. Railton (2002, p. 54). My emphasis.

  19. Hobbes (1651), I 6.

  20. Sidgwick (1981[1907], pp. 111–112). My emphasis.

  21. This feature is shared by a number of other desiderative views. See, for instance, Mulgan’s account of the desire-satisfaction view. See Mulgan (2007, p. 73).

  22. Many have held that existence internalism is a crucial plank in the argument for desiderative views of practical reason and the personal good. See, for instance, Williams (1981), Brink (2008) and Railton (2002, p. 47).

  23. Rosati (1996).

  24. Of course, the view that only desires motivate is certainly controversial. For defense, see Smith (1987) and Sinhababu (2009). Critics include Darwall (1983) and Scanlon (1999).

  25. Railton (2002, p. 47).

  26. Railton writes: “One might join the Kantians in challenging the premise of instrumentalism, and attempt to argue that some substantive ends or actions are indeed mandated by rationality. Such challenges have a noble history, and even a noble representation in the present, but I find the ignoble instrumentalist view the clearest idea we have of what it is, at a minimum, to have a reason for acting” (Railton 2002, p. 47).

  27. Larry Temkin notes this feature of a desiderative view: “on this view, the agent is the ultimate arbiter of her own good. What she desires is good for her, and, importantly, it is her desiring it which makes it so” (Temkin (1993, p. 264).

  28. Sumner (1996, p. 42).

  29. Brink (2008, pp. 40–45).

  30. Ibid., pp. 39–40.

  31. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this response.

  32. See footnote 26.

  33. This could be for many different reasons, and I remain neutral concerning which of the relata, “value” or “reason to promote”, is explanatorily prior.

  34. Bradley (2006). The “other things being equal” qualifier is meant to rule out bad instrumental effects of intrinsic goods.

  35. Bradley (2009, p. 19).

  36. Ibid., p. 5.

  37. See Feldman (2004, pp. 173–174).

  38. Bradley (2009, p. 19).

  39. Cf. Feldman (2004, p. 174).

References

  • Bradley, B. (2002). Is intrinsic value conditional? Philosophical Studies, 107, 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2006). Two concepts of intrinsic value. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9, 119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2009). Well-being and death. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (2008). The significance of desire. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (1983). Impartial reason. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (2004). Pleasure and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. (1989). Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2008). Fitting attitudes and welfare. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651). Leviathan.

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Rethinking intrinsic value. Journal of Ethics, 4, 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). Two distinctions in goodness. In Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lemos, N. (1994). Intrinsic value: Concept and warrant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Dispositional theories of value. In Papers in ethics and social philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Mill, J. S. (1861). Utilitarianism.

  • Moore, G. E. (1951). The conception of intrinsic value. In Philosophical Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mulgan, T. (2007). Understanding utilitarianism. Stocksfield: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. C. (1999). The simple desire-fulfillment theory. Noûs, 33, 247–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (2002). Facts and values. In Facts, values, and norms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Rosati, C. (1996). Internalism and the good for a person. Ethics, 106, 297–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1999). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1981[1907]). The methods of ethics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Sinhababu, N. (2009). The Humean theory of motivation reformulated and defended. Philosophical Review, 118, 465–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1987). The Humean theory of motivation. Mind, 96, 36–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, D. (1994). Full information theories of the good. Ethics, 104, 784–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L. (1993). Inequality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Internal and external reasons. In Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (2001). The nature of intrinsic value. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Ben Bradley, Chris Heathwood, Doug Portmore, and participants in a discussion of the issue of this paper at PEASoup: http://peasoup.typepad.com, for their extremely helpful comments. I would also like to thank an anonymous reviewer.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dale Dorsey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dorsey, D. Intrinsic value and the supervenience principle. Philos Stud 157, 267–285 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9636-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9636-7

Keywords

Navigation