Skip to main content
Log in

From movement to dance

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article begins with a summary phenomenological analysis of movement in conjunction with the question of “quality” in movement. It then specifies the particular kind of memory involved in a dancer’s memorization of a dance. On the basis of the phenomenological analysis and specification of memory, it proceeds to a clarification of meaning in dance. Taking its clue from the preceding sections, the concluding section of the article sets forth reasons why present-day cognitive science is unable to provide insights into dance, notably because being largely tethered to happenings in the brain, it lacks foundational grounding in experience, specifically, the actual experience of movement, which is to say in kinesthesia.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To be noted and even underscored is that, as the subtitle (“What Actions Tell the Self”) and the foreword to Motor Cognition make unequivocally clear from the very beginning, Jeannerod’s newly defined field of motor cognition has to do with action. The point, of course, is that action is not movement, and the study of action is therefore not equivalent to the study of movement any more than the study of behavior is equivalent to the study of movement (Sheets-Johnstone 2008b).

  2. A reviewer commented: “[T]he author’s ‘phenomenological analysis of movement’ is more a (Laban inspired) qualitative analysis than a phenomenological description and analysis of movement and/or dance (e.g., of being in the world).” I knew nothing of Laban’s analysis at the time of writing The Phenomenology of Dance. Laban analysts have since told me that my phenomenological analysis of movement is distinctive, but dovetails in significant ways with their analysis.

  3. The qualities are in fact evident not only in self-movement, or more generally in what is now commonly termed “human biological movement,” but also in the movement of waves, for example, and of tree limbs in a windstorm.

  4. A reviewer noted by way of counterexample that a Paul Taylor dance involved two unmoving dancers, dancers simply sitting on stage. Yvonne Rainer and Robert Morris, a number of years earlier, did something similar to Taylor’s two sitting dancers in their dance Waterman Switch, a dance in which both Rainer and Morris, nude and locked in an embrace, walked slowly from center stage into the wings, accompanied by a Verdi aria. Novel explorations are indeed the driving force of artistry and can at times bring to awareness, precisely by their seeming contrariness, stark realities of movement.

  5. For anyone doubtful about intuitive knowledge or wishing reputable empirical references to the topic, see Sheets-Johnstone 1999a, Chapter 4, on the confluence of Husserl’s and von Helmholtz’s characterization of intuitive knowledge as an effortless and immediate form of knowing.

  6. A reviewer wrote that “near and far are words but it is unclear whether they are concepts in the same way that for example ‘gift’ is a concept.” I refer any similarly dubious readers to Sheets-Johnstone 1990 which showed in fine detail through eight paleoanthropological case studies ranging from tool-making to paleolithic cave art, language, and to the concept of death that fundamental human concepts derive from the body: the body is a semantic template. See also Sheets-Johnstone 2008b, 2010.

References

  • Baars, B. J., & Gage, N. M. (2010). Cognition, brain, and consciousness (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1991). Matter and memory (trans: N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer). New York: Zone Books.

  • Bernstein, N. (1984). In H. T. A. Whiting (Ed.), Human motor actions: Bernstein reassessed. New York: Elsevier Science Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, N. (1996). In M. L. Latash & M. T. Turvey (Eds.), Dexterity and its development (trans: Latash, M.L.). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthoz, A., & Petit, J.-L. (2008). The physiology and phenomenology of action (trans: Christopher Macann). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bull, N. (1951). The attitude theory of emotion. New York: Nervous and Mental Disease Monographs (Coolidge Foundation).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullough, E. (1959). Psychical distance’ as a factor in art and an aesthetic principle. In Morris Weitz (Ed.), Problems in aesthetics (pp. 646–656). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Croce, A. (1979). Afterimages. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, M. (1968). Changes: Notes on choreography. New York: Something Else Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C (1965 [1872]). The expression of the emotions in man and animals. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • de Rivera, J. (1977). A structural theory of the emotions. New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W., Jr. (2006). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, E. (1990). “Tribute to A.R. Luria.” In E. Goldberg (Ed.), Contemporary neuropsychology and the legacy of Luria (pp. 1–9). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowitzke, B., & Milner, M. (1988). Understanding the scientific bases of human movement. Baltimore: Wilkins & Wilkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (trans: John Macquarie and Edward Robinson). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesian meditation: An introduction to phenomenology (trans: Dorion Cairns). The Hague: Martinus Nihjoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, Book II (Ideas 2) (trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer). Boston: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, E. (1929). Progressive relaxation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, E. (1967). The biology of emotions. Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, E. (1970). Modern treatment of tense patients. Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). Principles of psychology. New York: Holt.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kass, J. H. (Ed.). (2009). Evolutionary science. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S., & Engstrøm, D. A. (2006). The complementary nature. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koteen, D., & Smith, N. S. (2008). Caught Falling. Northampton, MA: Contact Editions.

  • Langer, S. K. (1953). Feeling and form. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, S. K. (1957). Problems of art. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria, A. R. (1966). Human brain and psychological processes (trans. Basil Haigh). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria, A. R. (1973). The working brain (trans: Basil Haigh). Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria, A. R. (1980). Higher cortical functions in man (trans. Basil Haigh) (2nd ed.). New York: Basic Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mazo, J. H. (1977). Prime movers. New York: William Morrow and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (trans: Colin Smith). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pineda, J. A. (Ed.). (2009). Mirror neuron systems. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pribram, K. (1966). “Preface” to A.R. Luria’s Human brain and psychological processes (pp. xiii–xv). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pribram, K. (1980). “Preface” to A.R. Luria’s Higher cortical functions in man (2nd ed., pp. xv–xvi). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raab, M., Johnson, J. G., & H. Heekeren (Eds.). (2009). Mind and motion: The bidirectional link between thought and action (Progress in Brain Research, vol. 174). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, M. E. (2006). The brain’s dark energy. Science, 314, 1249–1250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, D. A. (2010). Human movement control (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoenbaum, G., Gottfried, J. A., Murray, E. A., Ramus, S. J., eds. (2007). Linking affect to action: Critical contributions of the orbitofrontal cortex. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, vol. 1121.

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1966 [1979; 1980]). The phenomenology of dance. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Second edition: 1979, London: Dance Books Ltd.; 1980, New York: Arno Press.

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1981). “Thinking in movement.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 39/4: 399–407. An expanded version of the article appears in Sheets-Johnstone 1999a (Chapter 12) and Sheets-Johnstone 2009 (Chapter II).

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1990). The roots of thinking. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1998). “Consciousness: A natural history.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 5/3: 260–294. The article is included in Sheets-Johnstone 1999a (Chapter 2, Part I).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999a). The primacy of movement. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999b). “Emotions and movement: A beginning empirical-phenomenological analysis of their relationship.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 6/11-12: 259–277. The article is included in Sheets-Johnstone 2009 (Chapter VIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2003). “Kinesthetic memory.” Theoria et Historia Scientiarum: An International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies VII/1 (special issue on “Embodiment and Awareness,” ed. Shaun Gallagher and Natalie Depraz): 69–92. The article is included in Sheets-Johnstone 2009 (Chapter X).

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2004). On bacteria, corporeal representation, Neandertals, and Martha Graham. In M. Alac & P. Violi (Eds.), In the beginning: Origins of semiosis (pp. 105–136). Bologna, Italy: Brepols Turnhout. The article is included in Sheets-Johnstone 2009 (Chapter XI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2006). “Sur la nature de la confiance,” (trans: Albert Ogien). In Les moments de la confiance, ed. Albert Ogien and Louis Quéré. Paris: Economica, pp. 23–41. The article is included in Sheets-Johnstone 2008a (Chapter 7).

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2008a). The roots of morality. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2008b). Getting to the heart of emotions and consciousness. In P. Calvo & A. Gomilla (Eds.), Handbook of cognitive science (pp. 453–465). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2009a). The corporeal turn: An interdisciplinary reader. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2009b). Animation: The fundamental, essential, and properly descriptive concept. Continental Philosophy Review, 42, 375–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2010). Movement: The generative source of spatial perception and cognition. In R. Mitchell & F. Dolins (Eds.), Spatial perception, spatial cognition: Mapping the self and space (pp. 323–340). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2011) (forthcoming from John Benjamins Publishing: “Consciousness and Emotions Series”). “Fundamental and Inherently Interrelated Aspects of Animation.” In Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: The Role of (E)motion for Intersubjectivity, Consciousness, and Language, ed. Ad Foolen, Ulrike M. Lüdtke, Timothy P. Racine, Jordan Zlatev.

  • Sherrington, S. C. (1906). The integrative action of the nervous system. New York: Scribner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2010). Cognition, evolution, and behavior (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D. (1985). The interpersonal world of the infant. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teuber, H. L. (1966). “Discussion” of “Cerebral organizaiton and the conscious control of action” by D. M. MacKay. In J. C. Eccles (Ed.), Brain and conscious experience (pp. 442–445). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind and life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., & Depraz, N. (2005). At the source of time: Valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. In G. Colombetti & E. Thompson (Eds.), Journal of Consciousness Studies 12/8-10 (special issue on “Emotion Experience”) (pp. 61–81).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maxine Sheets-Johnstone.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sheets-Johnstone, M. From movement to dance. Phenom Cogn Sci 11, 39–57 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9200-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9200-8

Keywords

Navigation