Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The neurological dynamics of the imagination

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article examines the imagination by way of various studies in cognitive science. It opens by examining the neural correlates of bodily metaphors. It assumes a basic knowledge of metaphor studies, or the primary finding that has emerged from this field: that large swathes of human conceptualization are structured by bodily relations. I examine the neural correlates of metaphor, concentrating on the relation between the sensory motor cortices and linguistic conceptualization. This discussion, however, leaves many questions unanswered. If it is the case that the sensory motor cortices are appropriated in language acquisition, how does this process occur at the neural level? What neural preconditions exist such that this appropriation is possible? It is with these questions in mind that I will turn my attention to studies of neural plasticity, degeneracy and the mirror neuron activation. Whereas some scholarship in philosophy and cognitive neuroscience has aimed to identify the neurological correlates of consciousness, examining plasticity, degeneracy and activation shifts the discussion away from a study of correlates toward an exploration of the neurological dynamics of thought. This shift seems appropriate if we are to examine the processes of the “imagination.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Daniel Dennett has been accused of this type of eliminative materialism which states that a discussion of mental dispositions such as qualia or the imagination ought to be cut short in favor of a detailed materialist account of mind. See Dennett (1988). Varela carefully states the dangers of materialism and physicalism. He also outlines the dangers of dismissing cognitive science whole cloth. See Varela (1992, p. 13).

  2. Edelman goes on to describe the particular mechanisms that grant the possibility of the development of secondary functional repertoires in his concept of “reentry” which stands apart from neural “feedback.” This distinction and the imaginative character of reentry will be addressed in the discussion of the organic/molecular basis of the imagination. See Edelman and Tononi (2000b, p. 64).

  3. CP 4.39.

  4. Ibid., 19.

  5. Ibid.

  6. Ibid., 48.

  7. Ibid., 50.

  8. Ibid., 22.

  9. Ibid.

  10. Ibid., 331.

  11. Ibid.

  12. Ibid.

  13. The concept of reentry has been addressed by many researchers for nearly two decades. See Sporns et al. (1991). Also Edelman (1997).

  14. CP 6.104.

  15. Ibid., 49.

  16. Ibid.

  17. Ibid., 114.

  18. Ibid., 86–87, 97–98. See also Tononi et al. (1995).

  19. Ibid., 98.

References

  • Allard, T., et al. (1991). Reorganization of somatosensory area 3b representations in adult owl monkeys after digital syndctyly. Journal of Neurophysiology, 66, 1048–1058.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1988). Quining Qualia. In A. J. Marcel, & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1986/1934). Art as experience. In J. A. Boydson (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works, 1925–1953 (vol. 12 (p. 271). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1987a). Neural Darwinism: The theory of neuronal group selection. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1987b). Neural Darwinism. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1989). The remembered present: A biological theory of consciousness p. 50. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1997). Neural dynamics in a model of the thalamocortical system, 2: The role of neural synchrony tested through the perturbations of spike Timing. Cerebral Cortex, 7, 228–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1999). Building a picture of the brain. Annals of the New York Academy of Science, 882(1), 70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G., & Gally, J. (2001). Degeneracy and complexity in biological systems. Proceeding of the National Academy of Sciences, 13767, (Nov. 6).

  • Edelman, G., & Tononi, G. (2000a). A universe of consciousness: How matter becomes imagination. Cambridge: Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G., & Tononi, G. (2000b). A universe of consciousness: How matter becomes imagination. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engberg, P. (1995). The concept of domain in cognitive theory of metaphor. Nordic Journal of Linguistics, 18, 111–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engberg, P. (1999). Space and time: A metaphoric relation.Cognitive semantics: Meaning and cognition. Amsterdam: Benjamin.

  • Feldman, J. (2006). From molecule to metaphor. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, J. (1984). The brain’s dynamic way of keeping in touch. Science, 225(4664), 820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Metzinger, T. (2003). The emergence of a shared action ontology: Building blocks for a theory. Consciousness and Cognition, 12, 549–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 558–565.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauk, O. (2004). Somatotopic representations of action words in human motor and premotor cortex. Neuron, 41, 301–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J. (1995). Hidden order: How adaptation builds complexity. Cambridge: Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1950). The principles of psychology p. 262. New York: Dover Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. Dewey’s Zen: The ‘oh’ of wonder. Discussion paper at the Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy.

  • Johnson, M., & Lakoff, G. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (2000). Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, E. (2002). Hearing sounds, understanding actions: Action representation in mirror neurons. Science, 297, 846.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, E., Gallese, V., et al. (2002). Hearing sounds, understanding actions: Action representations in mirror neurons. Science, 297, 846–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. (1980). Autopoeisis: The organization of the living. In Autopoeisis and cognition. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Rohrer, T. (2006). Image schemata and the brain. In B. Hampe, & J. Grady (Eds.), From perception to meaning: Image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, S. (1987). Cross modal abilities in human infants. In J. Osofsky (Ed.), Handbook of infant development (pp. 318–362). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., et al. (1991). Modeling perceptual grouping and figure-ground segregation by means of active reentrant connections. Proceedings of the National Academy Science of the United States of America, 88, 129–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J., & Begley, S. (2002). The mind and the brain: Neuroplasticity and the power of mental force p. 118. New York: Regent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., et al. (1995). Measures of degeneracy and redundancy in biological networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 96, 3188–3208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umilta, M., et al. (2001). I know what you are doing: A neurophysiological study. Neuron, 31, 155–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. (1992). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. (1985). Complexity of the brain and autonomy of the living. In G. Bocchi, & M. Ceruti (Eds.),La Sfida della Complessit (pp. 141–157). Feltrinelli: Milano.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Kaag.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kaag, J. The neurological dynamics of the imagination. Phenom Cogn Sci 8, 183–204 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9106-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9106-2

Keywords

Navigation