Skip to main content
Log in

Forms and objects of thought

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is generally assumed that if it is possible to believe that p without believing that q, then there is some difference between the object of the thought that p and the object of the thought that q. This assumption is challenged in the present paper, opening the way to an account of epistemic opacity that improves on existing accounts, not least because it casts doubt on various arguments that attempt to derive startling ontological conclusions from seemingly innocent epistemic premises.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Barwise J., Perry J. (1981). Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations. Midwest Studies in Philosophy VI: 387–403

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow J., Pargetter R. (1990). Acquaintance with qualia. Theoria 56: 129–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun D. (1998). Understanding belief reports. Philosophical Review 107(4): 555–595

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad C.D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1956). Meaning and necessity: A study in semantics and modal logic (2nd ed.). Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda H.-N. (1966). “He”: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio 8: 130–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (2004a). Epistemic two-dimensional semantics. Philosophical Studies 118(1–2): 153–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (2004b). Phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument. In: Ludlow P., Nagasawa Y., Stoljar D. (eds). There’s something about Mary: Essays on Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument against physicalism. Cambridge, MIT Press, pp. 269–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell M. (1985). Structured meanings: The semantics of propositional attitudes. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Crimmins M. (1992). Talk about belief. MIT Press.

  • Crimmins M., Perry J. (1989). The prince and the phone booth: reporting puzzling beliefs. Journal of Philosophy 86(12): 685–711

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D. (1975). On saying that. In: Davidson D., Hintikka J. (eds). Words and objections: Essays on the work of W.V. Quine. Dordrecht, D. Reidel, pp. 158–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, Little Brown and Company

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52(4): 913–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes G. (1990). The indispensability of Sinn. Philosophical Review 99(4): 535–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes G. (1996). Substitutivity and the coherence of quantifying in. Philosophical Review 105(3): 337–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege G. (1966/1892). On sense and reference. In: Black M., Geach P. (eds). Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford, Basil Blackwell, pp. 56–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G. (1997/1918). Thought. In: Beaney M. (ed). The Frege reader. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 325–345

    Google Scholar 

  • Green M.S. (1996). Direct reference and implicature. Philosophical Studies 41(1): 61–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellie B. (2004). Inexpressible truths and the allure of the knowledge argument. In: Ludlow P., Nagasawa Y., Stoljar D. (eds). There’s something about Mary: Essays on Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument against physicalism. Cambridge, MIT Press.

  • Horgan T. (1984). Jackson on physical information and qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 34(135): 147–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 32(127): 23–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F. (1998a). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998b). Postscript on qualia. In Mind, method, and conditionals: Selected essays (pp. 76–79). Routledge: London.

  • Jackson F. (2004). Why we need a-intensions. Philosophical Studies 118(1–2): 257–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I. (1965/1781). Critique of pure reason (Norman Kemp Smith, trans.). New York, St. Martin’s Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1969). Quantifying in. In: Davidson D., Hintikka J. (eds). Words and objections: Essays on the work of W.V. Quine. Dordrecht, D. Reidel, pp. 206–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1989). Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In: Almog J., Perry J., Wettstein H. (eds). Themes from Kaplan. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 481–566

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1990). Thoughts on demonstratives. In: Yourgrau P. (ed). Demonstratives. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 34–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S. (1988). A puzzle about belief. In: Salmon N., Soames S. (eds). Propositions and attitudes. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 102–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson R., Ludlow P. (1993). Interpreted logical forms. Synthese 95(3): 305–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larson R., Segal G. (1995). Knowledge of meaning: Semantic value and logical form. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese 22(1–2): 18–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1979a). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review 88(4): 513–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1979b). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8(4): 339–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar B. (1990). Phenomenal states. Philosophical Perspectives, 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind 81–108

  • Lycan W.G. (1990). What is the “subjectivity” of the mental?. In: Tomberlin J. (ed). Philosophical perspectives IV: Action theory and philosophy of mind . Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp. 109–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Mates B. (1952). Synonymity. In: Linsky L. (ed). Semantics and the philosophy of language: A collection of readings. Urbana, University of Illinois Press, pp. 111–136

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay T. (1981). On proper names in belief ascriptions. Philosophical Studies 39(3): 287–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore G.E. (1903). Principia ethica. New York, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat?. Philosophical Review. 83(4): 435–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. In: Salmon N., Soames S. (eds). Propositions and attitudes. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 83–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry J. (1990). Frege on demonstratives. In: Yourgrau P. (ed). Demonstratives. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 50–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953a). On what there is. In From a logical point of view: 9 Logico-philosophical essays (2nd ed., pp. 1–19). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953b). Reference and modality. In From a logical point of view: 9 Logico-Philosophical essays (2nd ed., pp. 139–159). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine W.V.O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 53(5): 177–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine W.V.O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F. (1993). Direct reference: From language to thought. Oxford, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer M. (1996). What do belief ascribers really mean? A reply to Stephen Schiffer. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77(4): 404–423

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard M. (1988). Direct reference and ascriptions of belief. In: Salmon N., Soames S. (eds). Propositions and attitudes. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 169–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard M. (1990). Propositional attitudes: An essay on thoughts and how we ascribe them. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1905). On denoting. Mind 14(56): 479–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1985/1918). The philosophy of logical atomism. La Salle, Open Court

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S. (1992). Belief ascription. Journal of Philosophy 89(10): 499–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames S. (1987). Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. Philosophical Topics 15(1): 47–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R.C. (1987). Inquiry. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar D., Nagasawa Y. (2004). Introduction. In: Ludlow P., Nagasawa Y., Stoljar D. (eds). There’s something about Mary: Essays on Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument against physicalism. Cambridge, MIT Press, pp. 1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger P.K. (1984). Philosophical relativity. Oxford, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961/1921). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness, trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Wittgenstein L. (1965/1930). A lecture on ethics. Philosophical Review 74(1): 3–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta E.N. (1988). Intensional logic and the metaphysics of intentionality. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael W. Pelczar.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pelczar, M.W. Forms and objects of thought. Linguistics & Philosophy 30, 97–122 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-006-9012-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-006-9012-4

Keywords

Navigation