Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Legal positivism and property rights: a critique of Hayek and Peczenik

  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scholars such as Friedrich Hayek and Aleksander Peczenik have criticized legal positivism for undermining constitutionalism and the rule of law, an implication of which is weakened private property rights. This conclusion is far from evident. First, I contend that legal positivism is compatible with a strong support for property rights. Second, the causal relationship between legal positivism and the degree to which property rights are applied and protected is analyzed. The main arguments for a negative relationship—that legal positivism centralizes and politicizes legislation and that it makes the legal culture servile in relation to the political sphere—are considered unconvincing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The effects of legal positivism on property rights are the focus of the analysis, in accordance with Mises (1949, p. 678) who states that “[p]rivate ownership ... is the fundamental institution of the market economy,” although the analysis can be readily applied to effects on the market economy more broadly. On the institutional basis of the market economy, see Vanberg (1999).

  2. For philosophical critiques of legal positivism, see Fuller (1964), Dworkin (1977, 1986) and Finnis (1980).

  3. For an analysis of such effects of a related idea, ethical subjectivism, see Berggren (2004).

  4. Cf. Soper (1995, p. 425) and Kramer (1999, p. 2). The version of legal positivism that is discussed here is the inclusive one—see Waluchow (1994) and Kramer (1999). The exclusive version, primarily represented by Raz (1979, 1986), claims that it is not, like the inclusivists think, sufficient to say that there is no necessary connection between laws and morality but denies that there can be any such connection. The exclusivists regard these phenomena as separate, not only, like the inclusivists, as separable. See Marmor (2002).

  5. See Kelsen (1967, p. 13). Cf. Hayek (1960, pp. 237–239).

  6. See Hart (1958). On Kelsen’s view, see Stewart (1990).

  7. See Green (2003).

  8. Weak private property rights, as well as collective property rights, are of course also compatible with legal positivism.

  9. See Bix (2002) for more on modern natural law theory.

  10. As remarked by Hartmut Kliemt in private conversation, the issue is really one of psychology: people could be induced by a formal idea to hold certain content ideas even though the formal idea as such really does not indicate any particular content ideas. This could come about through misunderstandings of the formal idea or through irrationally. But it is hard to find fault with a particular formal idea because the human brain sometimes works in certain mysterious ways.

  11. Cf. Peczenik (2002) for a critique of relatively unconstrained majority rule and for an argument in favor of a strong influence for courts and legal scholars based on their perceived rationality and coherence.

  12. For a detailed argument, see Hayek (1973, chs. 4–6).

  13. See Marmor (1998).

  14. For a critique of this way of interpreting the actions of judges, see Posner (2003, pp. 80–81, 268–269).

  15. See Kramer (1999, pp. 114–115, 152, 197–199). Hayek (1976, p. 56) admits as much!

  16. Buchanan and Tullock’s (1962, pp. 77–80) research in constitutional economics bears resemblance to this approach. Cf. Buchanan (1974, pp. 335–336) and Brennan and Buchanan (1985).

  17. Kelsen (1967, p. 152).

  18. More critics: Buchanan (1977), Okruch (2000, 2001) and Schubert (2004). For a discussion, see Barry (1982, pp. 31–33). Hayek (1973, pp. 88–89) himself acknowledges that the common law may stand in need of correction by legislation from time to time but offers so systematic account of when this is to be carried out.

  19. Gwartney and Lawson (2004) measure the degree of economic freedom in 123 countries from 1970 and onwards by means of an index which includes the quality of the legal system and how secure property rights are. It e.g. makes clear that property rights are relatively strong in Sweden, a country characterized by legal positivism, and that they have become stronger in recent decades, in spite of reliance on centralized, politicized legislation.

  20. As pointed out by Hartmut Kliemt in private conversation, this insight puts the focus on the normative arguments in favor of particular rules of recognition, arguments that are not merely conceptual.

  21. Hayek (1960, 1979, ch. 17) himself presented a constitutional proposal which implies that he thought it possible to reduce the problems with centralized, politicized legislation. This insight is, however, rarely present in his critique of legal positivism (or democracy). Rapaczynski (2004) claims that if constitutional rules have an effect in upholding strong property rights, this occurs through procedural rather than through substantive rules.

  22. See Buchanan and Congleton (1997). The generality that Hayek regarded as characteristic of the common law can also be introduced as a constitutional rule in a centralized legal order.

  23. Okruch (2000) claims that in the civil law tradition there is also a strong element of following precedents in adjudication, and so he thinks Hayek’s distinction between the systems too strong.

  24. He also held that a constitution could contain substantive norms such as freedom of expression and religion—see Kelsen (1986).

  25. Cf. Posner (2003, p. 261).

  26. There was a debate on this topic between Radbruch and Hart: see Hart (1983, pp. 72–78).

  27. Carlsson (2001, pp. 72–73) questions whether the fact that many high judges in Sweden have a background as minstry officials has all that much to do with leading Swedish legal positivist Axel Hägerström, as is often claimed. Rather, the tradition goes back much longer.

  28. Hart (1961, ch. 7) e.g. stresses the open texture of the legal language which gives judges room to actually create laws in concrete cases. This room can, if the rule of recognition admits it, legitimately be characterized by ethical considerations and, of course, the rationality of legal argumentation (see Peczenik, 1989).

  29. This appears to be the case in e.g. Sweden: see Maccormick and Summers (1991).

  30. Natural law can be seen as both a formal idea and a set of content ideas.

  31. In addition, legal positivism is compatible med moral realism, and people can find the proposition ”the law should contain strong property rights” objectively true, regardless of whether they accept natural law.

  32. It is a negative thing if the change occurs as a result of a misunderstanding of legal positivism—for instance, that it implies socialism solely because some legal positivists have been socialists.

  33. Cf. Kuran (1995) and his theory of preference falsification.

References

  • Barry, N. (1982). The tradition of spontaneous order. Literature of Liberty, 5(2), 7–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benson, B. (1990). The enterprise of law: Justice without the state. San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. [1931 (1864)]. The theory of legislation. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Bentham, J. [1987 (1816)]. Anarchical fallacies. In J. Waldron (Ed.), “Nonsense upon stilts”: Bentham, Burke and Marx on the rights of man. London: Methuen.

  • Berggren, N. (2004). Does belief in ethical subjectivism pose a challenge to classical liberalism? Reason Papers, 27, 69–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bix, B. H. (2002). Natural law: The modern tradition. In J. Coleman & S. Shapiro (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence and philosophy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985). The reason of rules: constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1974). Good economics – bad law. Virginia Law Review, 60, 483–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1977). Law and the invisible hand. In B. H. Siegan (Ed.), The interaction of economics and the law. Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1997). Politics by principle, not interest: Towards nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlsson, J. (2001). Statsabsolutismens rättsfilosofi: en studie av Boströms och Hägerströms rättsfilosofi med avseende på deras bakgrund, innehåll och konsekvenser för juridiken. Master’s thesis, Faculty of Law, Lund University, Sweden.

  • Cooter, R., & Ulen, T. (1988). Law and economics. New York, NY: Harper Collins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. M. (1977). Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. M. (1986). Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyzenahaus, D. (1997). Legality and legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and Hermann Heller in Weimar. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1980). Natural law and natural rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. L. (1964). The morality of law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glaeser, E., & Shleifer, A. (2002). Legal origins. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(4), 1193–1229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, L. (2003). Legal positivism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/legal-positivism/>.

  • Gwartney, J. D., & Lawson, R. D. (2004). Economic freedom of the world: 2004 annual report. Vancouver: The Frasier Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadfield, G. K. (1992). Bias in the evolution of legal rules. Georgetown University Law Journal, 80, 583–616.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1955). Are there any natural rights? Philosophical Review, 64(2), 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review, 71, 593–629.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1983). Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1973). Law, legislation and liberty. Vol. 1: Rules and order. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation and liberty. Vol. 2: The mirage of social justice. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1979). Law, legislation and liberty. Vol. 3: The political order of a free people. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma, K. E. (2002). Inclusive legal positivism. In J. Coleman & S. Shapiro (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence and philosophy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, S., & Sunstein, C. R. (1999). The cost of rights: Why liberty depends on taxes. NewYork: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. [1967 (1934)]. The pure theory of law. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  • Kelsen, H. (1986). The function of a constitution. In R. Tur & W. Twining (Eds.), Essays on Kelsen. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. [1953 (1936)]. The general theory of employment, interest, and money. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

  • Kramer, M. H. (1999). In defense of legal positivism: Law without trimmings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuran, T. (1995). Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leoni, B. [1991 (1961)]. Freedom and the law. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

  • Maccormick, D. N., & Summers, R. S. (Eds.). (1991). Interpreting statutes: A comparative study. Aldershot: Dartmouth.

  • Marmor, A. (1998). Legal conventionalism. Legal theory, 4, 509–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2002). Exclusive legal positivism. In J. Coleman & S. Shapiro (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence and philosophy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menger, C. [1963 (1883)]. Problems of economics and sociology. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

  • Mises, L. von (1949). Human action: a treatise on economics. Chicago, IL: Contemporary Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nergelius, J. (1996). Konstitutionellt rättighetsskydd: svensk rätt i ett komparativt perspektiv. Stockholm: Fritzes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okruch, S. (2000). The evolution of property rights in European civil law: Competition and cooperation among jurisdictions. Paper presented for the International Society for New Institutional Economics, Tübingen, Germany.

  • Okruch, S. (2001). Der Richter als Institution einer spontanen Ordnung: Einige kritische Bemerkungen zu einer Zentralfigur in Hayeks Theorie der kulturellen Evolution. ORDO: Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 52, 131–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. (1989). On law and reason. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. (1995). Vad är rätt? Om demokrati, rättssäkerhet, etik och juridisk argumentation. Stockholm: Fritzes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. (1999). Lagstiftningen, domstolarna, rättsmedvetendet och rättsvetenskapen. In Löser juridiken demokratins problem? SOU 1999:58. Report to the Democracy Commission. Stockholm: Fakta Info Direkt.

  • Peczenik, A. (2001). Den skandinaviska rättsrealismen. In J. Nergelius (Ed.), Rättsfilosofi: samhälle och moral genom tiderna. Lund: Studentlitteratur.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. (2002). Why constitution? What constitution? Constraints on majority rule. In N. Berggren, N. Karlson, & J. Nergelius (Eds.), Why constitutions matter. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (2001). Kelsen, Hayek, and the economic analysis of law. Lecture to the 18th Annual Meeting of the European Association for Law and Economics, Vienna, September 14.

  • Posner, R. A. (2003). Law, pragmatism, and democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (2005). Hayek, law, and cognition. NYU Journal of Law & Liberty, 1, 147–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaczynski, A. (2004). Can constitutions protect private property against governmental predation? In E. Colombatto (Ed.), The Elgar companion to the economics of property rights. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1979). The authority of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, P. H. (2004). Why was the common law efficient? Working Paper No. 04-06. Law & Economics Research Paper Series, Emory School of Law, Emory University, Atlanta.

  • Schofield, P. (2003). Jeremy Bentham, the principle of utility, and legal positivism. Current Legal Problems, 56, 1–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, C. (2004). Hayek and the evolution of designed institutions: A critical assessment. Paper on Economics and Evolution No. 0411. Max Planck Institut, Jena, Germany.

  • Simpson, A. W. B. (1973). The common law and legal theory. In A. W. B. Simpson (Ed.), Oxford essays in jurisprudence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soper, P. (1995). Legal positivism. In R. Audi (Ed.), The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, I. (1990). The critical legal science of Hans Kelsen. Journal of Law and Society, 17(3), 273–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Undén, Ö. (1927). Juridik och politik. Stockholm: Tiden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1999). Markets and regulation: On the contrast between free-market liberalism and constitutional liberalism. Constitutional Political Economy, 10(3), 219–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow, W. J. (1994). Inclusive legal positivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is especially grateful for comments from Hartmut Kliemt but also for comments from Andreas Bergh, Anders Fogelklou, Alan Hamlin, Rolf Henriksson, Dan Johansson, Henrik Jordahl, Nils Karlson, the late Aleksander Peczenik, an anonymous referee and participants at the Public Choice Meetings in New Orleans 2006, as well as for financial support from the Torsten and Ragnar Söderberg Foundations and the Marcus and Amalia Wallenberg Memorial Fund Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Niclas Berggren.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Berggren, N. Legal positivism and property rights: a critique of Hayek and Peczenik. Constit Polit Econ 17, 217–235 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-006-9004-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-006-9004-y

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation