Skip to main content
Log in

Toward an Intermediate Position on Corporate Moral Personhood

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Models of moral responsibility rely on foundational views about moral agency. Many scholars believe that only humans can be moral agents, and therefore business needs to create models that foster greater receptivity to others through ethical dialog. This view leads to a difficulty if no specific person is the sole causal agent for an act, or if something comes about through aggregated action in a corporate setting. An alternate approach suggests that corporations are moral agents sufficiently like humans to be treated as persons, which leads to questions of intentionality and the organizational structure required to support the claim. In this article, I make an intermediate claim combining Goodpaster and Matthews' (60:132–141, 1982) view that a corporation may have a moral culture which affects subjective choices, with those of Painter-Morland (17(3):515–534, 2007) who points out that we should move from a model that posits discrete persons acting on each other to one where morality comes about through shared experience between agents who participate in each other’s lives. I argue that the discussion has been trapped in traditional dichotomies, and is better served by language that more accurately represents the dynamic interplay between organization and individual. I underwrite this claim by looking at recent changes in British and American legal approaches to corporate responsibility. These provide greater incentives for owners and business leaders to encourage employees to discuss the reflexive nature of legal and moral responsibility in business, facilitate workers to voice their moral concerns, and create structures and processes that allow those concerns to be heard.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sir Edward Coke, 1612, “Sutton’s Hospital Case” 77 Eng. Rep. 32. 960, which says in part “for a Corporation aggregate of many is invisible, immortal, and resteth only in intendment and consideration of the Law; and therefore cannot have predecessor nor successor. They may not commit treason, nor be outlawed, nor excommunicate, for they have no souls, neither can they appear in person, but by Attorney. A Corporation aggregate of many cannot do fealty, for an invisible body cannot be in person, nor can swear, it is not subject to imbecilities, or death of the natural, body, and divers other cases.”

  2. English law upheld the corporation as a separate entity from its individual members in a 1897 ruling, Salomon v. A Salomon & Co. Ltd. AC 22.

  3. “A company may in many ways be likened to a body. It has a brain and a nerve centre which controls what it does. It also has hands which hold the tools and act in accordance with the directors from the centre. Some of the people in the company are mere servants and agents who are nothing more than hands to do the work and cannot be said to represent the mind or will. Others are directors and managers who represent the mind and will of the company, and control what it does. The state of mind of these managers is the state of mind of the company and is treated by the law as such.” HL Bolton (Engineering) Co. Ltd. v. T. J. Graham & Sons Ltd. [1956] 3 All ER 624.

  4. Report available at www.railwaysarchive.co.uk/documents/DoT_KX1987.pdf.

  5. The Public Inquiry into the Piper Alpha Disaster, Cullen, The Honourable Lord, HM Stationery Office, 1990.

  6. Pdf available at http://www.parliament.uk/briefingpapers/commons/lib/research/briefings/snbt-00769.pdf.

  7. The website www.corporateaccountability.org tallies manslaughter case acquittals. See http://www.corporateaccountability.org/manslaughter/cases/acqcases/2.htm.

  8. In addition to unlimited fines, the court may also impose an order that demands the firm publicize the findings about incident and penalty imposed, something that Peter French once advocated as the “Hester Pryne Sanction” (French 1985).

References

  • Applbaum, A. I. (1995). Professional detachment: The executioner of Paris. Harvard Law Review, 109, 458–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, P., Jipson, A., & Bruce, A. (2002). State of Indiana v. Ford Motor Company revisited. American Journal of Criminal Justice, 26(2), 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennis, W., & O’Toole, J. (2005). How business schools lost their way, Harvard Business Review, May. Reprint R0505F.

  • Bevan, D., & Corvellec, H. (2007). The impossibility of a corporate ethics: for a Levinasian approach to managerial ethics. Business Ethics: A European Review, 16(3), 208–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boltanski, L., & Chiapello, E. (2005). The new spirit of capitalism. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, C. (1996). Case study: The Zeebrugge car ferry disaster. In Frederick & Post (Eds.), Business and society: Case studies in corporate social policy (pp. 498–511). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bucholz, R., & Rosenthal, S. (2006). Integrating ethics all the way through: the issue of moral agency reconsidered. Journal of Business Ethics, 66(2/3), 233–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Citizens United v Federal Election Commission. (2010). 130 S.Ct. 876.

  • Coffee, J. (1981). No soul to damn: no body to kick: an unscandalized inquiry into the problem of corporate punishment. Michigan Law Review, 79(3), 45–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coke, E. (2003). The selected writings and speeches of Sir Edward Coke. In S. Sheppard (Ed.), The case of Sutton’s hospital (Vol. 1). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/911/106352.

  • Courlander, M. (2004). Commission tightens requirements for corporate compliance and ethics programs. Washington, DC: US Sentencing Commission.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crainer, Stuart. (1993). Zeebrugge: learning from disaster—lessons in corporate responsibility. London: Herald Families Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crown Prosecution Service. (2009). Corporate Manslaughter. http://www.cps.gov.uk/legal/a_to_c/corporate_manslaughter/.

  • Dade Community Foundation Quarterly. (2004). State Attorney Supports Education and Honors ValueJet Crash Victims’, Fall. www.dadecommunityfoundation.org/Site/docs/FallNewsletter04BW.pdf.

  • Danley, J. R. (1995). Corporate moral agency: the case for anthropological bigotry. In W. M. Hoffman & R. E. Frederick (Eds.), Business ethics: readings and cases in corporate morality (pp. 183–188). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (1982). Corporations and morality. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drucker, P. (1998). Peter Drucker on the profession of management. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(3), 207–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1985). The Hester Prynne sanction. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 4(2), 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1994). Corporate ethics. New York: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society: outline of the theory of structuration. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. (1997). ‘Teleopathy’, blackwell encyclopedic dictionary of business ethics (p. 627). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. (2007). ‘Teleopathy’, encyclopedia of business ethics and society (p. 2067). New York: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K., & Matthews, J. (1982). Can a corporation have a conscience? Harvard Business Review, 60, 132–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Health and Safety Executive (UK). (2010). Human factors: fatigue. http://www.hse.gov.uk/humanfactors/topics/fatigue.htm.

  • Held, V. (1970). Can a random collective of individuals be morally responsible? Journal of Philosophy, 67, 471–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izraeli, D., & Schwartz, M. (1998). What can we learn from the US Federal sentencing guidelines for organizational ethics? Journal of Business Ethics, 17(9/10), 1045–1055.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, C., Parker, M., & ten Bos, R. (2005). For business ethics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerlin, M. (1997). ‘Peter French, corporate ethics and the wizard of Oz’. Journal of Business Ethics, 16(12/13), 1431–1438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladd, J. (1970). Morality and the ideal of rationality in formal organizations. Monist, 54, 488–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manning, R. (1984). Corporate responsibility and corporate personhood. Journal of Business Ethics, 3(1), 77–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansell, S. (2008). Proximity and rationalisation: the limits of a Levinasian ethics in the context of corporate governance and regulation. Journal of Business Ethics, 83(3), 565–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (1983). Vicarious agency and corporate responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 43, 69–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (1987). The morality of groups. West Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (1992). Sharing responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCabe, D., & Trevino, L. (1996). The influence of collegiate and corporate codes of conduct on ethics-related behavior in the workplace. Business Ethics Quarterly, 6(4), 461–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Messick, D., & Bazerman, M. (1996). Ethical leadership and the psychology of decision making. Sloan Management Review, 37(2), 213–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, L. (2003). Value shift. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Painter-Morland, M. (2007). Defining accountability in a network society. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 515–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, L., Angle, H., & Allen, R. (2003). Organizational influence processes. New York: M.E. Sharp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quigley, W. (2003–2004). Catholic social thought and the amorality of large corporations: time to abolish corporate personhood’, 5. Loyola Journal of Public Interest Law, 109.

  • Roberts, J. (2005). The power of the ‘imaginary’ in disciplinary processes. Organization, 12(5), 619–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roux-Dufort, C. (2000). Why organizations don’t learn from crises: the perverse power of normalization. Review of Business, Fall, 21(3), 25–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozuel, C. (2011). The moral threat of compartmentalization: self, roles and responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics, 102(4), 685–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seabright, M., & Kurke, L. (1997). Organizational ontology and the moral status of the corporation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 7(4), 91–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sekerka, L. (2009). Organizational ethics education and training: a review of best practices and their application. International Journal of Training and Development, 13(2), 77–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheen, J. (1987). MV Herald of free enterprise, report of court 8074. London: Department of Transport.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slapper, G. (2007). Corporate manslaughter law is a vast improvement, The Times Online, July 18. http://business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/law/article2097907.ece.

  • Soares, C. (2008). Corporate legal responsibility: a Levinasian perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 81(3), 545–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stansel, J. (1987). Testing firm’s warning about ferries unheeded. The Scientist, 1(10), 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaara, E., & Faÿ, E. (2011). How Can a Bourdieusian perspective aid analysis of MBA education? Academy of Management Learning and Education, 10(1), 27–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. (1983). Why corporations are not morally responsible for anything they do. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenger, E. (1998). Communities of practice–learning, meaning, and identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. (1999). Moral imagination and management decision-making. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yates, J. (1997). Using Giddens’ structuration theory to inform business history. Business and Economic History, 26(1), 159–183.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is indebted to the editors and anonymous reviewers for making contributions by way of their constructive advice and hard work. The author is also grateful to Elizabeth Lentini and Jennifer Kiefer for their assistance.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin Gibson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gibson, K. Toward an Intermediate Position on Corporate Moral Personhood. J Bus Ethics 101 (Suppl 1), 71–81 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1174-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1174-5

Keywords

Navigation