Skip to main content
Log in

Beyond persons: extending the personal/subpersonal distinction to non-rational animals and artificial agents

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The distinction between personal level explanations and subpersonal ones has been subject to much debate in philosophy. We understand it as one between explanations that focus on an agent’s interaction with its environment, and explanations that focus on the physical or computational enabling conditions of such an interaction. The distinction, understood this way, is necessary for a complete account of any agent, rational or not, biological or artificial. In particular, we review some recent research in Artificial Life that pretends to do completely without the distinction, while using agent-centred concepts all the way. It is argued that the rejection of agent level explanations in favour of mechanistic ones is due to an unmotivated need to choose among representationalism and eliminativism. The dilemma is a false one if the possibility of a radical form of externalism is considered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The reference to persons in “personal” and “subpersonal” should be read as accidental. We use the adjectives to refer generally to agents and to their internal machinery.

  2. This is, in fact, the position we find in Dennett’s paper mentioned above. His take on these issues is far more complex and oscillating than this. For instance, we can observe a move from blunt intrumentalism (1971) to some form of transcendentalism regarding the presumption of rationality for agents (1981) and back again to instrumentalism with realistic undertones (1991). Each of these accounts of intentionality are worth studying on their own. However, the position defended in his paper from 1978 is sufficiently popular to deserve discussion independently of the subtleties of Dennett’s work.

  3. The tradition we are referring to includes Wittgenstein (1953), Ryle (1949), Davidson (1970) and Dennett (1978).

  4. It could be argued that even the simplest designed artifact or program (say, a thermostat) would also demand both agent-level concepts and an appeal to macroproperties to explain its behaviour. In this paper we are only committed to the idea that it is a sufficient condition for treating something as an agent (and, in parallel, to defend the need for concepts making reference to features of the environment that are relevant to the agent as a whole) that the thing in question is the result of an adaptive evolutionary process. Whether this is also a necessary condition for agenthood is a question that we would like to leave open. We will briefly return to it in our discussion of ecological explanations of animal behaviour.

  5. Having said that, we have insisted on the need for agent-centered concepts to make sense of subpersonal explanations and place them in their proper context, and we have suggested that functional and ecological explanations work both at the personal and the subpersonal level.

  6. However, we have endorsed Hurley’s idea that a simplistic understanding of the subpersonal, such as the roughly Cartesian input/output picture, may work as a hidden assumption guiding our conception of the personal level. We have praised Beer’s profound analysis of the dynamical system that makes possible the cognitive achievement of his agent precisely as acting as an antidote against representationalist reductionism and as being a perfect complement to an ecological and functional view of the agent/environment pair.

References

  • Beer RD (1990) Intelligence as adaptive behavior: an experiment in computational neuroethology. Academic Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (1996) Toward the evolution of dynamical neural networks for minimally cognitive behavior. In: Maes P, Mataric M, Meyer J-A, Pollack J, Wilson SW (eds) From animals to animats 4: proceedings of the fourth international conference on simulation of adaptive behavior. MIT Press/Bradford Books, Cambridge, MA, pp 421–429

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (2003) The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved agent. Adapt Behav 11:209–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez JL (2000) Personal and subpersonal: a difference without a distinction. Philos Explor 2:63–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braitenberg V (1984) Vehicles: experiments in synthetic psychology. MA, MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks RA (1991) Intelligence without representation. Artif Intell 47:139–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cliff D, Harvey I, Husbands P (1993) Explorations in evolutionary robotics. Adapt Behav 2:73–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1970) Mental events, in his Essays on Actions and Events. Clarendon Press, 1980, Oxford, pp 207–225

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1973) The material mind, in his Essays on Actions and Events. Clarendon Press, 1980, Oxford, pp 245–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1971) “Intentional Systems”, his Brainstorms. Harvester Press, 1978, Sussex, pp 3–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1978) Toward a cognitive theory of consciousness, in his Brainstorms. Harvester Press, 1978, Sussex, pp 149–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1981) Making sense of ourselves in his The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press, 1987, Cambridge, Mass, pp 83–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1991) Real patterns, J Philos 88:27–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson JJ (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey I (1996) Untimed and misrepresented: connectionism and the computer metaphor. AISB Quart 96:20–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley SL (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lettvin JY, Maturana HR, McCulloch WS, Pitts WH (1959) What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain. PIRE 47:1940–1955

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marr D (1982) Vision. W. H. Freeman & Co, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis: the organization of the living. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living, Dordrecht, Reidel, pp 59–138

  • McDowell J (1994) The content of perceptual experience, in his mind, value, & reality, Harvard University Press, 1998, Cambridge, MA, pp 341–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1984) Language, thought and other biological categories. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle G (1949) The concept of mind. Penguin, 1963, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen N (1963) On aims and methods of ethology. Z Tierpsychol 20:410–433

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophical investigations, Oxford, Blackwell (trans. of Philosophische Untersuchungen by Anscombe GEM, edited by Anscombe GEM, Rhees R)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manuel de Pinedo-Garcia.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

de Pinedo-Garcia, M., Noble, J. Beyond persons: extending the personal/subpersonal distinction to non-rational animals and artificial agents. Biol Philos 23, 87–100 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9077-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9077-7

Keywords

Navigation