Skip to main content
Log in

In Search of Ontological Emergence: Diachronic, But Non-supervenient

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most philosophical accounts of emergence are based on supervenience, with supervenience being an ontologically synchronic relation of determination. This conception of emergence as a relation of supervenience, I will argue, is unable to make sense of the kinds of emergence that are widespread in self-organizing and nonlinear dynamical systems, including distributed cognitive systems. In these dynamical systems, an emergent property is ontological (i.e., the causal capacities of P, where P is an emergent feature, are not reducible to causal capacities of the parts, and may exert a top-down causal influence on the parts of the system) and diachronic (i.e., the relata of emergence are temporally extended, and P emerges as a result of some dynamical lower-level processes that unfold in real time).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that when I use the term “cause” in this paper I use it in the sense of Aristotle’s efficient cause by which Aristotle refers to the entities (broadly construed) responsible (non-intentionally construed) for a quantity of matter coming to be formed, viz., the entities which jointly interact give rise to something else. Unlike Aristotle’s other three notions of ‘cause’—that is, the material cause, the formal cause, and the final cause—all of which are synchronic, the efficient cause is diachronic (thanks to one of the reviewers for suggesting the usefulness of Aristotle in this context (for an overview on the Aristotelian causal categories, see Shields (2008)).

  2. Note that “levels” implies “hierarchies”. In a recent paper, Salthe (2012) distinguishes between two different logical forms of hierarchy. The first he calls for the compositional hierarchy. The second he calls the subsumption hierarchy. In my account of ontological and diachronic emergence, the relation between levels is an example of what Salthe calls the subsumption hierarchy, in the sense that (and in contrast to the compositional hierarchy), this species of hierarchical organization between levels allows for new levels to emerge through diachronic processes (cf. Salthe 2012, p. 359) Indeed, in compositional hierarchies, the levels are dynamically separate due to the fact that their dynamics occur at rates that do not directly interacts. But, in the examples I will consider, there is mutual interactions between levels. As Salthe mentions, the “levels in a subsumption hierarchy have been referred to as ‘integrative levels’ inasmuch as the higher levels […] integrate the lower levels’ properties and dynamics under their own rules” (2012, p. 361).

  3. This would be an example of a compositional hierarchy in the terminology developed by Salthe (2012).

  4. Note that there are individual and global versions of supervenience, and that these can be decomposed further into stronger and weaker varieties. I mention these varieties here for the sake of completeness, nothing else. For instance, Kim (1984, 1987) defines weak and strong individual supervenience as follows:

    A-properties weakly supervene on B-properties if and only if for any possible world w and any individuals x and y in w, if x and y are B-indiscernible in w, then they are A-indiscernible in w.”

    A-properties strongly supervene on B-properties if and only if for any possible worlds w 1 and w 2 and any individuals x in w 1 and y in w 2 , if x in w 1 is B-indiscernible from y in w 2 , then x in w 1 is A-indiscernible from -indiscernible from y in w 2 .”

    The difference between these two is that strong supervenience is quantified over possible worlds. The weak version says that if individuals are B-indiscernible, there can be no possible world in which these are A-discernible. The strong formulation stipulates that if B-indiscernible, then it is not possible for two individuals to be A-discernible, whether in the same or different worlds. The basic idea of “global supervenience” is simply to apply the “indiscernibility considerations” globally to “worlds,” rather than to “individuals”. Kim (1987) defines the idea of global supervenience accordingly: “Worlds that are indiscernible in respect to subvenient properties are indiscernible in respect to supervenient properties.” For weak and strong versions of global supervenience, see Bennett (2004), McLaughlin (1997), Sider (1999), and Stalnaker (1996). Note that in the next section I present an argument developed by O’Connor (2000) that rejects both strong and weak formulation of both individual and global supervenience.

  5. See Humphreys’ (1997) “fusion” account of emergence for a different kind of critique of the standard account of emergence, although one the equally builds on the idea that emergence is diachronic and dynamic.

  6. Here it is important to distinguish between two kinds of entropy, that is, we must separate configurational (i.e., informational) entropy from physical entropy production, and vice versa. Generally speaking, information entropy is, as Friston specifies, “the average surprise of outcomes sampled from a probability distributed or density. A density with low entropy means, on average, the outcome is relatively predictable” (2009, p. 293). In terms of predictability (or uncertainty), the informational entropy in the example of convection rolls is low. Physical entropy, by contrast, refers to the number of degrees of freedom in a physical system, that is, it refers to the total number of states a given system can be in.

  7. Microscopically, no two examples will be exactly alike. It is the “motion” in this example that reflects the physical entropy production (thanks to one of the reviewers for making this clear).

  8. A hexamers is consider to be the smallest drop of water, because it is the smallest cluster of water that is three-dimensional.

  9. “Schewe et al. (2003): A water molecule’s chemical formula is really not H2O, at least not from the perspective of neutrons and electrons interacting with the molecule for only attoseconds (less than 10−15 s).” (Cited in Van Brakel 2010, p. 132; footnote 42).

  10. Note that thus far my discussion of supervenience has taken the relation between A-features and B-features to be one of indiscernibility such that “x and y are A-indiscernible if and only of they are exactly alike with respect to A-properties; similarly for B-indiscernibility.” (McLaughlin and Bennett 2011, p. 14) However, in addition to varieties of individual and global indiscernibility-based supervenience, there are also versions of similarity-based accounts of supervenience, where things “that are very much alike in B-respects must also be very much alike in A-respects. As with indiscernibility-based supervenience, similarity-based supervenience comes in both weak and strong versions:

    “A strongly supervenes sim on B if and only if for any worlds w 1 and w 2, and for any x in w 1 and y in w 2, if x in w 1 is not largely different from y in w 2 with respect to B-properties, then x in w 1 is not largely different from y in w 2 with respect to A-properties” (McLaughlin and Bennett 2011, p. 27; italics in original).

    “A weakly supervenes sim on B if and only if for any world w, and for any x and y in w, if x and y are not largely different with respect to B-properties, then they are not largely different with respect to A-properties.” (McLaughlin and Bennett 2011, p. 27; italics in original)

    I mention this issue here so as not to beg the question against similarity-based supervenience. Nevertheless, the point to note is that it remains an open question whether there are (or has been) any interesting philosophical uses of the idea of similarity-based supervenience (cf. McLaughlin and Bennett 2011, p. 27). Hence, as such it poses no immediate threat to my argument for ontological emergence that is diachronic/dynamic but non-supervenient.

  11. Wilson’s (1994, 2004) account of wide computationalism advances similar claims.

  12. Mereology refers to compositional hierarchies (cf. Salthe 2012).

References

  • Bedau M (1997) Weak emergence. Philos Perspect 11:375–399

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer R (1995) A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. Artif Intell 72:173–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belyaev VB, Motovilov AK, Sermyagin AV, Kuznetzov IV, Sobolev Y, Smolnikov A, Klimenko AA, Osetrov SB, Vasilev SI (2001) Search for nuclear reactions in water molecules. Phys Lett B 552(3–4):222–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett K (2004) Global supervenience and dependence. Philos Phenomenol Res 68(3):501–529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett K (2011) Construction area (no hard hat required). Philos Stud 154:79–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Richardson A, Stephan A, Westerhoff H (2005) Emergence and its place in nature: a case study of biochemical networks. Synthese 145:131–164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad CD (1925) The mind and its place in nature. Routledge & Paul Kegan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks R (1999) Cambrian intelligence. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell RJ, Bickhard M (2011) Physicalism, emergence and downward causation. Axiomathes 21:33–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiel JH, Beer DR (1997) The brain has a body: adaptive behavior emerges from interactions of nervous system, body and environment. Trends Neurosci 20(2):553–557

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2001) Mindware. Oxford University Press, New York & Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Chalmers D (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58:7–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Couzin ID, Krause J (2003) Self-organization and collective behavior in vertebrates. Adv Study Behav 33:1–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Bechtel W (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 22:547–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo E (2009) Extended life. Topoi 28:9–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan F (1992) Individualism, computation, and perceptual content. Mind 101:443–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1987) Psychosemantics. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston K (2009) The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the brain? Trends Cogn Sci 13(7):293–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P, Stotz K (2000) How the mind grows: a developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese 122:29–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helbing D, Schweitzer F, Keltsch J, Molnar P (1997a) Active walker model for the formation of human and animal trail systems. Phys Rev E 56:2527–2539

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helbing D, Keltsch J, Molnár P (1997b) Modelling the evolution of human trail systems. Nature 388:47–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber T, Velleman JD (2011) How to endure. Philos Q 61(242):37–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (1997) Emergence, not supervenience. Philoso Sci 64:337–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (2008) Synchronic and diachronic emergence. Mind Mach 18:431–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (1995) Cognition in the wild. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso S (1995) Dynamic patterns. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1984) Concepts of supervenience. Reprinted (1993) in Supervenience and mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 53–78

  • Kim J (1987) Strong and global supervenience revisited. Reprinted (1993) in Supervenience and mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 79–91

  • Kim J (1999) Making sense of emergence. Philos Stud 95:3–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2006) Emergence: core ideas and issues. Synthese 151:547–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D (2007) Everything must go: metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN (2004) Extending the extended phenotype. Biol Philos 19:313–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Feldman MW (2000) Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural change. Behav Brain Sci 23:131–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1983) Extrinsic properties. Philos Stud 44:197–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin B (1997) Emergence and supervenience. Intellectica 25:25–43

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin B, Bennett K (2011) Supervenience. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/

  • Menary R (2007) Cognitive integration: mind and cognition unbounded. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell S (2012) Emergence: logical, functional and dynamical. Synthese 185:171–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Näätänen R, Lehtokoski A, Lennes M, Cheour M, Huotilainen M, Livonen A, Vainio M, Alku P, IImoniemi RJ, Luuk A, AIIik J, Sinkkonen J, Alho K (1997) Language-specific phoneme representations revealed by electric and magnetic brain responses. Nature 385(30):432–434

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor T (2000) Causality, mind, and free will. Philos Perspect 14:105–117

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor T, Wong HY (2005) The metaphysics of emergence. Nous 39:658–678

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor T, Wong HY (2012) Emergent properties. In Stanford online encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ properties-emergent/

  • Odling-Smee FJ (1988) Niche constructing phenotypes. In: Plotkin HC (ed) The role of behavior in evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 73–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (2001) Terms in tension: what do you do when all the good words are taken? In: Oyama S, Griffiths P, Gray R (eds) Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 177–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S, Griffiths P, Gray R (2001) Introduction: what is developmental systems theory? In: Oyama S, Griffiths P, Gray R (eds) Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer R, Lida F, Bongard J (2005) New robotics: design principles for intelligent systems. Artif Life 11(99):120

    Google Scholar 

  • Roepstorff A, Niewohner J, Beck S (2010) Enculturating brains through patterned practices. Neural Networks 23:1051–1059

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross D, Ladyman J (2010) The alleged coupling-constitution fallacy and the mature sciences. In: Menary R (ed) The Extended Mind. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 155–166

  • Salthe SN (2012) Hierarchical structures. Axiomathes 22:355–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schewe PF, Stein B, Riordon J (2003) A water molecule’s chemical formula is really not H2O. Physics news update (The American Institute of Physics Bulletin of Physics News), 648 (July 31)

  • Segal G (1991) Defense of a reasonable individualism. Mind 100:485–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J (2009) Forms of emergent interaction in general process theory. Synthese 166:479–512

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shields C (2008) Aristotle. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle/

  • Sider T (1999) Global supervenience and identity across times and worlds. Philos Phenomenol Res 59:913–937

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein M (2012) Emergence and reduction in context: philosophy of science and/or analytical metaphysics. Metascience 21:627–642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein M, McGeever J (1999) The search for ontological emergence. Philos Q 49:182–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spivey M (2007) The continuity of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R (1996) Varieties of supervenience. Philos Perspect 10:221–241

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephan A (1999) Varieties of emergentism. Evol Cogn 5(1):49–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton J (2010) Exograms and interdisciplinarity: history, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In: Menary R (ed) The extended mind. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 189–225

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Theiner G, Allen C, Goldstone RL (2010) Recognizing group cognition. Cogn Syst Res 11:378–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Brakel J (2010) Chemistry and physics: no need for metaphysical glue. Found Chem 12:123–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve J (1990) Emergence vs. pansychism: mind dust or magic? Philos Perspect 4:215–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder T (1998) The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 21:615–665

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela F, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler M (2005) Reconstructing the cognitive world. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (1986) Forms of aggregativity. In: Donagan A, Perovich AN, Wedin MV (eds) Human nature and natural knowledge. D. Reidel, Boston, pp 259–291

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (2000) Emergence as non-aggregative and the biases of reductionism. Found Sci 5:269–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Kirchhoff.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kirchhoff, M. In Search of Ontological Emergence: Diachronic, But Non-supervenient. Axiomathes 24, 89–116 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-013-9214-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-013-9214-7

Keywords

Navigation