Skip to main content
Log in

The nature of scientific thought

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

‘Scientific thought’ is regarded here as both a type of goal-directed behaviour (practice) and its product, and the question of its ‘nature’ posed in terms of that goal and of means appropriate for achieving it, preferably with regard to an existing paradigm (exemplar) such as the ‘Galilean-Newtonian’. ‘Empiricism’, a widely received view of the nature of science, is examined and rejected, as is the general idea that scientific thought has ‘philosophical foundations’. The question of the actual or possible scientific status of ‘the human sciences’ is raised and some methodological guidelines for an answer to it suggested.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Althusser, L.: 1969, For Marx, Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, L.: 1990, Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of the Scientists, Verso, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, L. and Balibar, E.: 1970, Reading Capital, New Left Books, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachelard, G.: 1986, The New Scientific Spirit, Beacon Press, Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balibar, E.: 1978, ‘From Bachelard to Althusser: the Concept of “Epistemological Break”’, Economy and Society 7, 207–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., Gasper, P., and Trout, J. D. (eds.): 1991, The Philosophy of Science, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass..

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N.: 1983, How the Laws of Physics Lie, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, A. F.: 1982, What is this Thing Called Science? (2nd ed.), University of Queensland Press, St Lucia, Queensland, Australia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cromer, A.: 1993, Uncommon Sense. The Heretical Nature of Science, Oxford University Press.

  • Dewey, J.: 1938, Logic, the Theory of Inquiry, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K.: 1981, Philosophical Papers, 2 vols, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo: 1962, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems — Ptolemaic and Copernican (trans. S. Drake), University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo: 1974, Two New Sciences (trans. S. Drake), University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I.: 1983, Representing and Intervening, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H.: 1893/1968, Collected Papers, 4 vols, Greenwood Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I.: 1978, Philosophical Papers, 2 vols, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecourt, D.: 1975, Marxism and Epistemology, New Left Books, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, K.: 1935, ‘The Conflict between Aristotelian and Galilean Modes of Thought in Contemporary Psychology’, in K. Lewin (ed.), A Dynamic Theory of Personality, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. W.: 1987, Fact and Method, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mittelstrass, J.: 1972, ‘The Galilean Revolution. The Historical Fate of a Methodological Insight’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 2, 297–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, L.: 1980, The Structure of Idealization, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S.: 1994, The Language Instinct, Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R.: 1972, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (3rd ed.), Hutchinson, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R.: 1979, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruby, J. E.: 1986, ‘The Origins of Scientific “Law”’, Journal of the History of Ideas 47, 341–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sambursky, S. (ed.): 1975, Physical Theory, Pica Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W. A.: 1986, Marx and Philosophy, Macmillan, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W. A.: 1992, ‘Constructivism Deconstructed’, Science & Education 1, 223–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W. A.: 1994, ‘Notes on the Cultural Significance of the Sciences’, Science & Education 3, 1–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiles, M.: 1984, Bachelard: Science and Objectivity, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldrop, M. M.: 1994, Complexity, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M.: 1949, The Methodology of the Social Sciences, The Free Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall, R. S.: 1980, Never at Rest. A Biography of Isaac Newton, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L.: 1953, Philosophical Investigations, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zilsel, E.: 1942, ‘The Genesis of the Concept of Physical Law’, Philosophical Review 51, 245–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L.: 1992, The Unnatural Nature of Science, Faber and Faber, London.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

This paper is a version of one commissioned for the forthcoming International Handbook of Science Education edited by Ken Tobin and Barry Fraser (Kluwer Academic Publications). Thus it deals in a condensed way with wide-ranging and complex matters that would ordinarily be treated separately and at greater length. (Editor)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Suchting, W.A. The nature of scientific thought. Sci Educ 4, 1–22 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00486588

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00486588

Keywords

Navigation