Skip to main content
Log in

A Correction to this article was published on 15 July 2020

This article has been updated

Abstract

Myth has a convoluted etymological history in terms of its origins, meanings, and functions. Throughout this essay, I explore the signification, structure, and essence of myth in terms of its source, force, form, object, and teleology derived from archaic ontology. Here, I offer a theoretic typology of myth by engaging the work of contemporary scholar, Robert A. Segal, who places fine distinctions on criteria of explanation versus interpretation when theorizing about myth historically derived from methodologies employed in analytic philosophy and the philosophy of science. Through my analysis of an explanandum and an explanans, I argue that both interpretation and explanation are acts of explication that signify the ontological significance, truth, and psychic reality of myth in both individuals and social collectives. I conclude that, in essence, myth is a form of inner sense.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

  • 15 July 2020

    In the original article published, the Greek term ���������������������a��� for muthologia is incorrect. The correct term is ������������������������.

Notes

  1. Initiated in the nineteenth century, and now in its 9th revised edition, Liddell and Scott’s Greek-English Lexicon is generally considered among classicists to be the finest compilation to date of the classical works of antiquity where the etymological sources of ancient words derive and correspond to contemporary linguistics and modes of discourse. All references to μῦθος begin on p. 1151, Vol. 2.

  2. See Anderson (2004, p. 61) for a discussion.

  3. Eliade (1963) asserts that “the myth is regarded as a sacred story, and hence a ‘true history,’ because it always deals with realities. The cosmogonic myth is ‘true’ because the existence of the World is there to prove it; the myth of the origin of death is equally true because man’s mortality proves it” (p. 6). Here we may say that Eliade is conflating myth with an actual portrayal of history and that such a portrayal conveys actual realities, which needs defined and demonstrated, hence proved. A myth may be true insofar as it is an artifact of culture, but it does not mean that it signifies a true reality apart from the experience of the subject or social collective. And just because the world exists does not make the myth real or true apart from the believer. The existence of the world does not remotely prove the reality of the myth other than it is an anthropological occasion or psychological projection. Projections do not necessarily correspond to objective reality. And just because we are mortal and die, does not mean that a myth of the origins of death proves it any more than the biological fact that we cease to be, as any anatomist or mortician will tell you.

References

  • Anderson, A. A. (2004). Mythos, logos, and telos: How to regain the love of wisdom. In A. A. Anderson, S. V. Hicks, & L. Witkowski (Eds.), Mythos and logos: How to regain the love of wisdom. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1984). Meteorology. In J. Barnes (Ed.). The complete works of Aristotle. 2 Vols (pp. 555-625) (The revised Oxford, Trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1946). The idea of history (T. M. Knox, Ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Dilthey, W. (1883/1923). Introduction to the human sciences (R. J. Betanzos, Trans.). Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1979.

  • Eliade, M. (1963). Myth and reality. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1962.

  • Homer. (800 B.C.E.). The Odyssey (S. Butler, Trans). Retrieved July 7, 2018 from http://classics.mit.edu/Homer/odyssey.html.

  • Homer. The Iliad (S. Butler, Trans). Retrieved July 7, 2018 from http://classics.mit.edu/Homer/iliad.html.

  • Liddell, H. G., & Scott, R. (1843). A Greek–English lexicon. 2 Vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, J. (2013). Freedom and determinism. The Humanistic Psychologist,41(2), 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, J. (2014). Truth. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association,62(2), 267–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, J. (2015). Psychoanalysis and the ideologies of science. Psychoanalytic Inquiry,35, 24–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato, (1961a). Phaedo. In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The collected dialogues of Plato (pp. 40–98). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato, (1961b). Phaedo. In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The collected dialogues of Plato (pp. 575–844). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981). Hermeneutics and the human sciences (J. B. Thompson, Trans. and Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Ryle, G. (1971). Collected papers. 2 Vols. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (1992). Explaining and interpreting religion. New York: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (1999). Theorizing about myth. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (2004). Myth: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (2009). Religion as ritual: Roy Rappaport’s changing views from pigs of the ancestors (1968) to ritual and religion in the making of humanity (1999). In M. Stausberg (Ed.), Contemporary theories of religion: A critical companion (pp. 66–82). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (2014a). Weber, Geertz, and Ricoeur on explanation and interpretation. Bulletin for the Study of Religion,43(1), 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, R. A. (2014b). Explanation and interpretation. In R. A. Jones (Ed.), Jung and the question of science (pp. 82–97). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1968). Economy and society, Vol. 1 (E. Fischoff, Trans.; G. Roth and C. Wittich, Eds.). New York: Bedminster Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jon Mills.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mills, J. The Essence of Myth. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 37, 191–205 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-020-00198-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-020-00198-3

Keywords

Navigation