Skip to main content
Log in

Reconstructing the Moral Logic of the Stakeholder Approach, and Reconsidering the Participation Requirement

  • Published:
Philosophy of Management Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The most recent restatements of stakeholder theory formulate that approach in terms of the distribution of value: “A stakeholder approach to business is about creating as much value as possible for stakeholders, without resorting to tradeoffs” (Freeman et al. 2010: 28). This formulation marks a shift from earlier work, which included a procedural dimension—a requirement that stakeholders participate in organization decision making. The present paper pushes back against this shift: it argues that orienting the stakeholder approach around the participation requirement provides for a different moral logic, one not available to (now) conventional stakeholder theorizing (without that requirement), and one that may be more compelling to many. This argument requires critical re-examination of the moral arguments offered in the most recent restatements of the stakeholder approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Another telling example: Between 2006 and 2010, the investment bank Goldman Sachs assured investors that, “Our reputation is one of our most important assets. As we have expanded the scope of our business and our client base, we increasingly have to address potential conflicts of interest, including situations where our services to a particular client or our own proprietary investments or other interests conflict, or are perceived to conflict, with the interest of another client.” And: “We have extensive procedures and controls that are designed to identify and address conflicts of interest.” And, most important, Goldman said, “our client’s interests always come first.”

    Goldman during this period, leading up to the 2008–2009 financial crisis, sold securities that had been constructed to fail to benefit a hedge fund. In 2011, Goldman acknowledged that it provided “incomplete information” to investors and paid a $550 million penalty. But that payment did not provide compensation to customers who lost money, so the Arkansas Teacher Retirement System lead a group of investors and sued Goldman for $13 billion—alleging that the bank violated these stated commitments to customers.

    The case was argued at the U.S. Supreme Court in spring 2021. The plaintiffs’ case depended on a technical point in the law about corporate representations to stockholders; news accounts reported that some of the Court justices were confused by the issues at stake. What is relevant here—and striking—is this: Goldman Sach’s lawyers argued that those explicit commitments to customers created no substantive obligations on the firm’s part, they were instead “exceptionally generic and aspirational statements.” So, Goldman doesn’t seem to think that putting its own interests ahead of customers would hurt the company; Goldman doesn’t think the profit-oriented approach is doomed to failure, at least not economic failure; and that firm tends to be a good judge of such things. See Bravin 2021 and Liptak 2021.

  2. The Business Roundtable endorsed the stakeholder approach to business in 2019, 181 member CEOs from the largest corporations operating in the United States signed the statement. Here some see endorsement of the stakeholder approach, recognition (at least) of its instrumental benefits. This is not clear: Recently, two Harvard Business School professors studied Roundtable signatories’ corporate governance guidelines. They found that none of the signatories updated those guidelines to reflect a change in the status of stakeholder concerns, demonstrating lack of intention to reorient decision making around stakeholder considerations. And the companies’ compensation systems support their conclusion: “most of the companies [signatories to the Roundtable statement] still have guidelines that explicitly align the interests of directors and stockholders. In contrast, no company’s compensation practices or guidelines link director compensation with stakeholder interests. The strong alignment of director pay with stock price sends a clear signal that shareholder value is the object directors are expected or pursue” (Bebchuk and Tallarita 2021).

    Separately, Robert Reich (2021) documents the hypocrisy in Jamie Dimon’s claims to be practicing stakeholder management (Dimon is CEO of J.P. Morgan Chase, and he initiated the Business Roundtable statement while serving as Chairman of that organizations). Reich’s analysis is required reading for anyone taking the Roundtable statement at face value.

  3. At multiple points, across a number of publications including the (2010) restatement, Freeman and collaborators reject the so-called separation thesis, the idea that economic and ethical considerations are distinct in the context of business practice. The main text first presented instrumental arguments for the stakeholder approach and at this point turns to moral argument, so the main text might seem to endorse separation. But note: Freeman and collaborators allow that arguments can be made from one perspective or the other; Freeman and collaborators themselves make instrumental economic arguments (“doomed to failure”), and they also make separate moral arguments involving different “normative cores” (more on these in the main text, in a moment). The present paper follows their practice. This practice allows that instrumental economic decisions and actions will have moral effect, and vice versa.

  4. To be sure, evolutionary arguments for this suggestion are tempting, and these might be modern versions of Aristotle’s arguments about what is “natural.” For example, across a long series of comparative experiments on small children and primates, Michael Tomasello (2009) has shown that humans evolved special skills in order to engage in cooperative behavior. And we can read Tomasello as suggesting that humans are distinct in engaging in (what he calls, following Tuomela) we-mode cooperation—acting with others for cooperative as opposed to strictly individual reasons. The suggestion in the main text is consistent with this line of research, but the evolutionary arguments are dangerous, we don’t want to associate all evolved capacities with the human good. At the same time, however, the evolutionary account provides a psychological explanation for why human beings are frustrated when put in non-cooperative environments—those environments frustrate deep instincts.

  5. Alfano (2015) uses this kind of example, with latitude and longitude, in a different context.

References

  • Acherkamp, M.C., and J.F.J. Vos. 2008. Investigating the use of the stakeholder notion in project management literature, a meta-analysis. International Journal of Project Management 26 (7): 749–757.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Agle, B.R., R.K. Mitchell, and J.A. Sonnenfeld. 1999. Who matters to CEOs? An investigation of stakeholder attributes and salience, corporate performance, and CEO values. Academy of Management Journal 42 (5): 507–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano, M. 2015. Friendship and the structure of trust. In From personality to virtue, ed. A. Masala and J. Webber, 186–206. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E., and R. Pildes. 2002. Expressive theories of law: a general restatement. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148: 1503–1575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. 1984. The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bebchuk, L. A., and R. Tallarita. 2021. ’Stakeholder’ talk proves empty again. The Wall Street Journal : A17. August 19.

  • Berkey, B. 2020. The value of fairness and the wrong of wage exploitation. Business Ethics Quarterly 30 (3): 414–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosse, D.A., R.A. Phillips, and J.S. Harrison. 2009. Stakeholders, reciprocity, and firm performance. Strategic Management Journal 30 (4): 447–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Business Roundtable. 2019. Business Roundtable redefines the purpose of a corporation to promote ‘An Economy That Serves All Americans.’ Press release. https://www.businessroundtable.org/business-roundtable-redefines-the-purpose-of-a-corporation-to-promote-an-economy-that-serves-all-americans.

  • Bravin, J. 2021. Supreme court weighs merit of Goldman Sach’s ethics statements. The Wall Street Journal. March 29. https://www.wsj.com/articles/supreme-court-weighs-merit-of-goldman-sachs-ethics-statements-11617050980.

  • Cohen, M.A. 2019. The problem of imposing risk and the procedural dimension of stakeholder management. Business and Society Review 124 (3): 413–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evan, W.M., and R.E. Freeman. 1988. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In Ethical Theory and Business, ed. T.L. Beauchamp and N.E. Bowie, 97–106. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1990. The moral limits of the criminal law, volume 4: harmless wrongdoing. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E. 1994. The politics of stakeholder theory: some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly 4 (4): 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E., and W.M. Evan. 1990. Corporate governance: a stakeholder interpretation. Journal of Behavioral Economics 19 (4): 337–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, and A.C. Wicks. 2007. Managing for stakeholders: survival, reputation, and success. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R.E., J.S. Harrison, A.C. Wicks, B. Parmar, and S. de Colle. 2010. Stakeholder theory: the state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frooman, J. 1999. Stakeholder influence strategies. Academy of Management Review 24 (2): 191–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. 1990. Walking together: a paradigmatic social phenomenon. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15: 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey, P.C., and B. Lewis. 2019. Pragmatism and pluralism. In The Cambridge companion to stakeholder theory, ed. J.S. Harrison, et al., 19–34. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, M. 2007. Beyond the myth of corporate responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics 74 (7): 315–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, M., and R. Mir. 2019. Critical management studies and stakeholder theory. In The Cambridge companion to stakeholder theory, ed. J.S. Harrison, et al., 35–52. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, M.R., and J. Simmons. 2004. A stakeholder approach to ethical human resource management. Business and Professional Ethics Journal 23 (3): 23–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J.D., S.E. Bodily, and J. Mead. 2011. Caprica energy and its choices: teaching note. Charlottesville, VA: Darden Business Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J.D., S.E. Bodily, J. Mead, D. Adolphson, and B. Carmack. 2013. Caprica energy and its choices. Charlottesville, VA: Darden Business Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, J.S., J.B. Barney, R.E. Freeman, and R.A. Phillips, eds. 2019. The Cambridge companion to stakeholder theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersher, R. 2018. After decades of air pollution, a Louisiana town rebels against a chemical giant. National Public Radio. March 6. https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2018/03/06/583973428/after-decades-of-air-pollution-a-louisiana-town-rebels-against-a-chemical-giant.

  • Jensen, M. 2002. Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly 12 (2): 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T.M. 1995. Instrumental stakeholder theory: a synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of Management Review 20 (2): 404–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liptak, A. 2021. Supreme Court looks for narrow path in investor’s suit against Goldman Sachs. The New York Times. March 29. https://www.nytimes.com/2021/03/29/us/politics/supreme-court-goldman-sachs.html.

  • Meyers, C. 2004. Wrongful beneficence: exploitation and third world sweatshops. Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (3): 319–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. 2014. The connection between stakeholder theory and stakeholder democracy: an excavation and defense. Business & Society 53 (6): 820–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, R.M. 1974. Aristotle’s doctrine that Man is a political animal. Hermes 102: 438–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orts, E.W., and A. Strudler. 2009. Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics 88 (supplement 4): 605–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parmar, B.L., R.E. Freeman, J.S. Harrison, A.C. Wicks, L. Purnell, and S. de Colle. 2010. Stakeholder theory: state of the art. The Academy of Management Annals 4 (1): 403–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parrino, R., T. Bates, S. L. Gillan, and D. S. Kidwell. 2017. Fundamentals of corporate finance, 4th Edition. Hoboken: Wiley.

  • Phillips, R. 2003. Stakeholder theory and organizational ethics. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, R.A., J.B. Barney, R.E. Freeman, and J.S. Harrison. 2019. Stakeholder theory. In The Cambridge companion to stakeholder theory, ed. J.S. Harrison, et al., 3–18. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, R., R.E. Freeman, and A.C. Wicks. 2003. What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics Quarterly 13 (4): 479–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Post, J., L. Preston, and S. Sachs. 2002. Redefining the corporation: stakeholder management and organizational wealth. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999. A theory of justice, revised edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reich, R. 2021. The system: Who rigged it, how we fix it. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N.C., and D. Ronnegard. 2016. Shareholder primacy, corporate social responsibility, and the role of business schools. Journal of Business Ethics 134 (3): 463–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starik, M. 1995. Should trees have managerial standing? Toward stakeholder status for non-human nature. Journal of Business Ethics 14 (3): 207–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2009. The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009.

  • Ton, Z. 2014. The good jobs strategy: how the smartest companies invest in employees to lower costs and boost profits. New York: New Harvest, Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 2010. Cooperation as joint action. Analyse and Kritik 2: 65–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valkila, J., P. Haaparanta, and N. Niemi. 2010. Empowering coffee traders? The coffee value chain from Nicaraguan Fair Trade farmers to Finnish consumers. Journal of Business Ethics 97 (2): 257–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, A. 1999. Exploitation. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, D. M. 2011. The purpose of corporations in business and law school curricula. Governance Studies at Brookings. http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2011/07/19-corporation-west.

  • Wicks, A., D.R. Gilbert Jr, and R.E. Freeman. 1994. A feminist reinterpretation of the stakeholder concept. Business Ethics Quarterly 4 (4): 475–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. 2004. Responsibility and global labor justice. Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (4): 365–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc A. Cohen.

Ethics declarations

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose and no conflicts of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cohen, M.A. Reconstructing the Moral Logic of the Stakeholder Approach, and Reconsidering the Participation Requirement. Philosophy of Management 22, 293–308 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-022-00227-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-022-00227-y

Keywords

Navigation