Skip to main content
Log in

Agency, Desire, and Changing Organizational Routines

  • Published:
Philosophy of Management Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Feldman (Organization Science 11(6): 611–629, 2000) describes the striving mechanism as a mode of routine change driven by successful organizational routines. Striving describes a process by which organization members gain a better understanding of the ideals undergirding their actions. In turn, this insight drives changes within routines. In this paper, I argue that the rational actor model, especially as articulated in Donald Davidson’s (1963) theory of action, is unable to account for the striving mechanism of endogenous routine change identified by Feldman (Organization Science 11(6): 611–629, 2000). Drawing upon Brewer’s (2011) criticisms of propositional theories of desire, the account of meta-language intentional attitudes developed by List and Pettit (2011), and MacIntyre’s (2007) theory of social practices, I introduce an expanded framework for conceptualizing agency at the individual level, and aggregation at the organization level, that better accounts for the striving mechanism as a process of endogenous routine change.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. MacLean et al. (2015) and MacLean and MacIntosh (2012) critique both rational actor and normative theories of action – the latter rooted in sociological theorizing – arguing that neither approach adequately accounts for creativity within organizations. Although considerations of the normative model of agency are outside the scope of this paper, similar criticisms apply to this approach insofar as applications of the normative model of agency fail to account for endogenous change within organizations. For example, Nilsson (2015) argues that perspectives in institutional theory, typically employing a normative model of agency, have failed to adequately theorize the role of shared values or ideals in positively shaping organizational change. Accordingly, the philosophical account of agency introduced in this paper can be understood as extending both rational actor and normative models of agency by (a) explicitly distinguishing non-operationalized values or ideals from concrete objectives and (b) introducing a mechanism – dialectical activity – for explaining how such values shape agents’ concrete objective (Brewer 2011: 136), but in this paper, I focus on the way in which the analytical philosophy of action can enrich the rational actor model.

  2. As Feldman (2000) explains, striving involves a reciprocal process whereby successfully achieved goals results in an improved understanding of ideals, which, in turn, result in the adoption of new concrete specified goals.

  3. When discussing an additional housing organization routine, Feldman (2000: 621) notes that multiple mechanisms may be implicated in one instance of routine change. In the case she describes, the ideal in question is efficiency. Here efficiency is not treated as a measurable outcome but as an ideal that the organization ought to achieve in its activities. Feldman describes how the move-in routine (which was ‘successful’ according members’ expectations) led to an instance of striving where organization members came to understand that their initial conceptions of the ideal of efficiency were inadequate. After broadening their understanding of this ideal, new possibilities became apparent. According to Feldman, this is a situation where striving lead to an instance of the expanding mechanism. Important for the purpose of my argument is Feldman’s point that the striving mechanism always involves an expanded or improved understanding of an ideal.

  4. In the discussion section, I consider the question of whether the account of action developed in this paper is applicable to for-profit, as opposed to public, organizations.

  5. Davidson (1969 & 1978) distinguishes between prima-facie desires and all-things-considered desires, but this distinction does not account for the difference between operational and non-operational goals (March and Simon 1993).

  6. Tsoukas (2005), following MacIntyre (2007), argues that social practices provide the context in which agents conceptualize the rational and historical continuity in their disparate experiences of acting. As I argue in greater detail below (Expanding the Davidsonian Theory of Agency section), social practices are the primary context in which agents reinterpret their objectives in the light of both their ideals and fellow practitioners’ reinterpretations, enabling them to distinguish between rational and arbitrary reinterpretations of ideals and objectives.

  7. Sebastian Rödl (2007: 36) employs the term infinite end to identify this concept: “An end to which the contrast of pursuing and having got does not apply is an infinite end.” This distinction does not apply because infinite ends are never fully realized by a discrete set of actions.

  8. Sebastian Rödl (2007: 36) calls such ideals, infinite ends, to capture their non-finite or indefinite character. Ideals such as health, justice, or beauty are never realized through a definite set of actions such that one is no longer able to strive to better achieve the ideal in question. Similarly, Candace Vogler (2009) argues that such ideals, which she terms befitting reasons for action, are time-general meaning that of their nature they are capable of being exemplified in an indefinite number of situations. This infinite or time-general characteristic of non-operational ideals underwrites Brewer’s (2011) claim that agents are continuously able to experience new aspects of the value or goodness of such ideals.

  9. Feldman (2000: 621) identifies two instances of the striving mechanism. The first case, which I have described above, concerns situations where the intended outcome of an action is not obtained. The second case, involves situations where a successful action produces additional negative consequences about which the agent was unaware prior to the action. In both cases the repairing mechanism functions by changing the agents’ beliefs about the consequences of an action.

  10. Harry Frankfurt (1988: 12) famously elaborated upon the concept of second-order desires as follows: “Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have (or not to have) certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are.” Charles Taylor (1985b) explicitly links Frankfurt’s concept of second-order desire with the concept of an ideal or value. The fundamental idea behind the concept of a second-order desire is that human beings possess the capacity to adopt a disengaged stance toward any particular desire for an operational goal and, potentially, to desire either to maintain or change the particular first-order desire in question. See also Hartman (2013) for an application of this concept to business ethics.

  11. “Practitioners discover and commit to goals that lie beyond their own selfish, short-term needs and desires. They realize that they can only achieve the internal goods that are of value to themselves, their social practice, and wider society when they emulate the standards of excellence already established within

    the practice” (von Krogh et al. 2012: 660).

References

  • Argyris, Chris. 1976. Single-loop and double-loop models in research on decision making. Administrative science quarterly. 21 (3): 363–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Argyris, Chris. 2004. Reasons and Rationalizations: The Limits to Organizational Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Argyris, Chris, and Donald Schon. 1978. Organizational learning: A theory of action approach. Reading: Addision Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard, Chester. 1971. The Functions of the Executive: 30th Anniversary Edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barney, Jay, and Teppo Felin. 2013. What are Microfoundations? Academy of Management Review: 138–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, Ron. 2008. Why Business Cannot Be a Practice. Analyse & Kritik 30: 229–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, Ron. 2013. Managerial Work in a Practice-Embodying Institution: The Role of Calling, The Virtue of Constancy. Journal of Business Ethics 113 (4):679–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. 2015. MacIntyre's Influence on Business Ethics (pp. 1-9). In Handbook of Virtue Ethics in Business and Management, ed. A. Sison, G. Beabout, and I. Ferrero, 1–9. Springer.

  • Beadle, Ron, and Geoffery Moore. 2011. MacIntyre, Neo-Aristotelianism and Organization Theory (pp.85–121). In Research in the Sociology of Organizations, ed. H. Tsoukas and R. Chia. Emerald Group Publishing Limited.

  • Bernacchio, Caleb. 2015. Rival Versions of Corporate Governance as Rival Theories of Agency. Philosophy of Management. 14 (1): 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blau, Peter. 1977. A Macrosociological Theory of Social Structure. The American Journal of Sociology. 83 (1): 26–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, Talbot. 2011. The Retrieval of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1963, [2001]. Actions, Reasons, Causes (pp. 3–20). In D. Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidson, Donald. 1969, [2011]. How is Weakness of the Will Possible (pp. 21–42). In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidson, Donald. 1971, [2001]. Agency (pp. 43–60). In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1976, [2001]. Hempel on Explaining Action (pp. 261–276). In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1978, [2001]. Intending (pp. 83–102). In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • DiMaggio, P., and W.W. Powell. 1983. The iron cage revisited: Collective rationality and institutional isomorphism in organizational fields. American Sociological Review 48 (2): 147–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eells, Ellery. 2016. Rational decision and causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Eisenhardt, Kathleen. 1989. Building Theories from Case Study Research. Academy of Management Review 14 (4): 532–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 2009. Alexis de Tocqueville, the First Social Scientist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Elster, Jon. 2015. Explaining social behavior: More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Feldman, Martha. 2000. Organizational Routines as a Source of Continuous Change. Organization Science. 11 (6): 611–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felin, Teppo and Knudsen, Thorbjørn. 2012. A Theory of Nascent Entrepreneurship and Organization. Managerial and Decision Economics. 33 (5–6): 409–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fontrodona, Joan, and Alejo Sison. 2006. The Nature of the Firm, Agency Theory and Shareholder Theory: A Critique from Philosophical Anthropology. Journal of Business Ethics 66 (1): 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the Person (pp. 11–25). In The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gersick, Connie, and J. Richard Hackman. 1990. Habitual Routines in Task-Performing Groups. Organizational Behavior Human Decision Process. 47 (1): 65–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, Sumantra. 2005. Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education 4 (1): 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, Sumantra, and Peter Moran. 1996. Bad for practice: A critique of the transaction cost theory. Academy of Management Review 21 (1): 13–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hain, Raymond. 2015. Consilium and the Foundations of Ethics. The Thomist 79 (1): 43–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, Edwin. 2013. Virtue in Business: An Aristotelian Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter. 2005. Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, Michael. 2002. Stakeholder Theory, and the Corporate Objective Function. Business Ethics Quarterly. 12 (2): 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, Michael, and William Meckling. 1976. The of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure. Journal of Financial Economics 3: 305–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, Kelvin. 2008. Goods. Philosophy of Management. 7 (1): 107–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koppl, Roger, Stuart Kauffman, Teppo Felin, and Giuseppe Longo. 2015. Economics for a creative world. Journal of Institutional Economics 11 (1): 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, David. 1988. Notes on the Theory of Choice. Boulder: Westview press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Philip Pettit. 2011. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After Virtue. 3rd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1979. Corporate Modernity and Moral Judgment: Are They Mutually Exclusive? (pp. 122–135). In Ethics and the Problems of the 21st Century, ed. K. Sayre and K. Goodpaster. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2006. Social Structures and their Threats to Moral Agency. In Ethics and Politics, 186–203. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2016. Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning and Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacLean, Donald, and Robert Macintosh. 2012. Strategic Change as Creative Action. The International Journal of Strategic Change Management. 4 (1): 80–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacLean, Donald, Robert MacIntosh, and David Seidl. 2015. Rethinking Dynamic Capabilities from a Creative Action Perspective. Strategic Organization. 13 (4): 340–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • March, James, and Herbert Simon. 1993. Organizations. New York: Wiley.

  • McPherson, Miller, Lynn Smith-Lovin, and James Cook. 2001. Birds of a Feather: Homophily in Social Networks. Annual Review of Sociology. 27: 415–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, John, and Bryan Rowan. 1977. Institutionalized Organizations: Formal Structure as Myth and Ceremony. American Journal of Sociology. 83 (2): 340–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Geoff. 2005. Corporate Character: Modern Virtue Ethics and the Virtuous Corporation. Business Ethics Quarterly 15 (4): 659–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Geoff. 2008. Re-Imagining the Morality of Management: A Modern Virtue Ethics Approach. Business Ethics Quarterly 18 (4): 483–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Geoff. 2017. Virtue at Work. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Geoff, and Ron Beadle. 2006. In Search of Organizational Virtue in Business: Agents, Goods, Practices, and Environments. Organization Studies. 27 (3): 369–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Geoff, and Gina Grandy. 2017. Bringing Morality Back in: Institutional Theory and MacIntyre. Journal of Management Inquiry 26 (2): 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Richard R. 1991. Why do firms differ, and how does it matter? Strategic Management Journal 12 (S2): 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Richard, and Sidney Winter. 1985. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Nicholas, Jeffery. 2012. Reason, Tradition, and the Good: Frankfurt School Critical Theory and MacIntyre's Reason of Traditions. Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nilsson, Warren. 2015. Positive institutional work: Exploring institutional work through the lens of positive organizational scholarship. Academy of Management Review 40 (3): 370–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka, Ikujiro, and Ryoko Toyama. 2007. Strategic management as distributed practical wisdom (phronesis). Industrial and Corporate Change 16 (3): 371–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quante, Michael. 2004. Hegel's Concept of Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rhonheimer, Martin. 2011. The Perspective of Morality. Washington, D. C: Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robson, Angus. 2015. Constancy and integrity:(un) measurable virtues? Business Ethics: A European Review 24 (S2): S115–S129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, Sebastian. 2007. Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Ruef, Martin, Howard Aldrich, and Nancy Carter. 2003. The Structure of Founding Teams: Homophily, Strong Ties, and Isolation Among U.S. Entrepreneurs. American Sociological Review. 86 (2): 195–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selznick, Philip. 2011. Leadership in Administration: A Sociological Interpretation. New Orleans: Quid Pro.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Herbert. 1997. Administrative Behavior. 4th ed. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985a. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind (pp. 77–96). In Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University of Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985b. What is Human Agency? (pp. 15–44). In Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University of Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1997. To Follow a Rule (pp. 165–180). In Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Teece, David, Gary Pisano, and Amy Schuen. 1997. Dynamic Capabilities and Strategic Management. Strategic Management Journal 18 (7): 509–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tost, Leigh Plunkett. 2011. An integrative model of legitimacy judgments. Academy of Management Review 36 (4): 686–710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, Hardimos. 2005. Forms of Knowledge and Forms of Life in Organized Contexts (pp. 69–93). In Complex Knowledge: Studies in Organizational Epistemology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Visser, M. 2007. Deutero-learning in organizations: A review and a reformulation. Academy of Management Review 32 (2): 659–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogler, Candace. 2009. Reasonably Viscious. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • von Krogh, Georg, Stefan Haefliger, Sebastian Spaeth, and Martin Wallin. 2012. Carrots and Rainbows: Motivation and Social Practice in Open Source Software Development. MIS Quarterly 46 (2): 649–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, Oliver. 1979. Transaction Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations. The Journal of Law and Economics. 22 (2): 233–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Caleb Bernacchio.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

I would like to gratefully acknowledge Robert Couch for reading and commenting on an earlier draft of this paper, two anonymous reviewers who provided insightful comments, and Wim Vandekerckhove, the editor of Philosophy of Management along with the participants of the 11th Annual Philosophy of Management International Conference held in 2016 at St. Anne’s College Oxford and sponsored by University of Greenwich Business School, where this paper was originally presented.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bernacchio, C. Agency, Desire, and Changing Organizational Routines. Philosophy of Management 17, 279–301 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-017-0081-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-017-0081-y

Keywords

Navigation