Skip to main content
Log in

Thomas Hunt Morgan and the invisible gene: the right tool for the job

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper analyzes the early theory building process of Thomas Hunt Morgan (1866–1945) from the 1910s to the 1930s and the introduction of the invisible gene as a main explanatory unit of heredity. Morgan’s work marks the transition between two different styles of thought. In the early 1900s, he shifted from an embryological study of the development of the organism to a study of the mechanism of genetic inheritance and gene action. According to his contemporaries as well as to historiography, Morgan separated genetics from embryology, and the gene from the whole organism. Other scholars identified an underlying embryological focus in Morgan’s work throughout his career. Our paper aims to clarify the debate by concentrating on Morgan’s theory building—characterized by his confidence in the power of experimental methods, and carefully avoiding any ontological commitment towards the gene—and on the continuity of the questions to be addressed by both embryology and genetics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Morgan’s prolific output as an author, which documents his changes of opinion about several matters (including Darwinian natural selection and Mendelian inheritance), has prompted a similar divergence of opinion among commentators, with some authors highlighting internal inconsistencies. See for instance Gilbert (1978, 1991). See also below the comments on Falk (2007) and Maienschein (1992), notes 13 and 28 respectively. For Morgan’s “theoretical pluralism” as a sign of his “particular understanding of the experimental method” see Manier (1969, p. 201 and note 12) and Kingsland (2007).

  2. We will not enter into a detailed investigation of Morgan’s scientific career. For a general reconstruction of Morgan’s scientific life, see Sturtevant (1959), Allen (1978a, b), and Kohler (1994).

  3. Maienschein uses the term “(w)holism” to identify an ontological position whereby: “what exists in the world is complex, interactive wholes” (p. 135). Holism, by contrast, is instead considered an epistemological position.

  4. On subsequent conceptual developments in classical genetics after Morgan, see also Kohler (1994), Burian (2000) and Carlson (2004).

  5. On Drosophila research, see Sturtevant (1965), Allen (1975), Kohler (1994) and Carlson (2013).

  6. The reconstruction of the context of this debate is beyond the scope of this article, but there is a wealth of available literature on these themes. See e.g. Sturtevant (1965), Gilbert (1978, 1998), Benson (2001) and Falk (2007), on Mendel and Mendelism see the classic Olby (1979), see also Olby (1997), Müller-Wille and Orel (2007).

  7. An example of this kind of controversy, as described by Vorms (2013), is the debate opposing Morgan and William E. Castle (1867–1962) about linkage maps. The two scientists agreed at a general level (chromosome theory), but their views differed at the local level (physical explanation of the structure of the chromosome).

  8. Other theoretical debates were also implicated, including the development of the notion of heredity as the rich literature on the subject has revealed. See Bowler (1989), Amundson (2005) and Müller-Wille and Rheinberger (2007a, b).

  9. On the subject see also Churchill’s book (2015) August Weismann: Development, Heredity, and Evolution. See also Waters (2004) for a discussion of Morgan aims and strategies in pursuing genetic research.

  10. Note the comment by Allen (2003, p. 67): “For Morgan and others, the Mendelian ‘factor’ or ‘gene’ smacked too much of the embryologists' old bugbear, preformationism […]. Epigenesis, the alternative view, had replaced preformationism by the mid-19th century, so that Mendel's work in the form presented by Mendelians, seemed like an outdated throwback to a long-discarded idea”.

  11. Eventually, this approach became known as Morgan’s chromosome theory of heredity. Morgan’s early anti-nuclear and anti-Mendelian approach has been studied variously, by Allen (1966, 1985), Manier (1969), Gilbert (1978), Benson (2001) and Falk (2007). For a detailed analysis of the reception of the chromosome theory, see Brush (2002).

  12. See Manier’s (1969, p. 202) distinction in Morgan’s work between an alleged empiric approach and a true experimental one: his “confidence in […] the epigenetic theories forced him to submit Mendelian preformationism to such a wide variety of experimental tests that his own final version of Mendelism was considerably strengthened in the process”.

  13. Falk (2007) starts from our same point of view, “[Morgan] saw in Johannsen’s conception of disparate hereditary factors and traits a ‘developmental’ way out of the de Vriesian notion of hereditary preformationism, allowing him to maintain an organismic approach to development while accepting a particulate theory of inheritance”. Yet, he explains this by reference to Morgan’s reductionist approach: “Morgan and his students reduced causation to patterns conjunction” (Falk 2007, p. 258) and that “from its early steps, genetic analysis was paradigmatically reductionist” (Falk 2007, p. 250). As explained later, our perspective on Morgan’s theoretical commitment towards reductionism is different.

  14. About the shift from a descriptive to an experimental paradigm in biology, see for example Coleman (1984). For the introduction of quantitative analysis in genetics, see Falk (2007).

  15. For an analysis of linkage maps, see Falk (2004) and Vorms (2013).

  16. To several students this model seems too limited for understanding emergent properties such as the formation of gametic frequencies (Wimsatt 2006).

  17. These “discrete particles” corresponded to specific phenotypic traits, which would be extensively studied in Drosophila during the next 5 years. The results showed a hundred new and inherited traits (clustered in 4 main groups) such as olive, speck, white or fringed and affecting different parts of the body (such as body color, thorax, eye color, wings). For an analysis of how the changing of the nomenclature meant also a changing in the approach in Morgan’s work (from developmental function to simpler phenotypic deviation) see Falk (2007, p. 258). It is worth noting that while Morgan had already started to relate chemical substances to underlying elementary particles, there is not yet any mention of the gene.

  18. The concept of organization is used extensively by Morgan in his pre-Drosophila research on regeneration. See Morgan (1901) and Maienschein (2016).

  19. Morgan’s embryological background was, for example, matched by Muller’s expertise in physics. See Maienschein (1984) for an analysis of this convergence of traditions. See also Jordan (1988) for an interesting perspective on the interdisciplinary innovation in experimental biology.

  20. The quotes are from Morgan (1917, pp. 513–514).

  21. Morgan rephrased the same concepts—deemed “a priori objections”—2 years later in “The physical basis of heredity” (1919), with slight though significant differences: for example, “molecules” replaced “atoms”.

  22. The process by which “virtual chromosomes of linkage data were finally bolstered by physical reality” is described in Falk (2004). Skopek (2011) has recently put in evidence how the early Mendelians generated a new way of experimental seeing; using pedigrees, linkage-maps and Mendelian ratios they taught students how to “see through”, going beyond the visible appearance of the organism. See also the two volumes edited by Rheinberger and Gaudillière (2004a, b).

  23. When looking at the editor’s announcement of “The physical basis of heredity” (1919), signed by Jacques Loeb, Winthrop John Van Leuven Osterhout and Morgan himself, it is important to remember the context: the “new experimental biology” was struggling to secure a place among the other “real” sciences, trying to shed its reputation as a “purely speculative and descriptive” approach (Morgan 1919, p. 5).

  24. This is what Falk (2007) described as the passage “from phenotype to genotype to stereotype”, p. 281 ff. See also Wheeler (2007) discussing genes as “privileged causal elements in the developmental process”, p. 370 ff.

  25. “[The term ‘gene’] should express only the simple conception that the characteristics of an organism are, or can be, caused or co-determined by ‘something’ in the make-up [Konstitution] of the gametes. The word ‘gene’ is thus completely free of any hypothesis” (Johannsen 1909; translated by Burian 2000, pp. 143–144).

  26. For Morgan’s efforts to establish consistent terminology, see his letter to Driesch in January 1900, quoted in Sunderland (2010, p. 335); see also Kingsland (2007).

  27. For the relevance of development in history of heredity, see Amundson (2005) about Morgan see especially pp. 177 ff.

  28. Maienschein’s position is peculiar because it seems to combine Morgan’s gene-centric perspective with an opposed embryological perspective: “Even in his role as geneticist, Morgan remained at least loyal in principle, if not in practice, to his embryological roots” (1992, p. 124); some lines later, we read: “For Castle, unlike the Morgan group, the gene was not inviolable and sacrosanct”. See also a recent comment by Maienschein: “Morgan’s words here [(Morgan 1924)] and in his many, many other articles and books might mislead readers looking with particular genetics-oriented assumptions to miss the emphasis on development” (Maienschein 2016, p. 592).

  29. At the meeting of the American Society of Naturalists, in December 1906, Morgan said that the biological "question of the hour" was that of preformation vs. epigenesis, and he compared Mendelian inheritance to preformation (Allen 1966).

  30. For an analysis of why Morgan cannot be considered a forerunner of present-day Evo-Devo thinking, despite providing a potential bridge between genetics and developmental issues, see Schwartz (2006).

  31. For example, Waters (2004) account of Morgan’s work supports our view: the distinction between investigation and explanation largely match with our hypothesis that Morgan was mostly pragmatic in his methodology, and was wary of strong ontological commitments.

References

  • Allen, G. E. (1966). Thomas hunt morgan and the problem of sex determination, 1903–1910. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 110(1), 48–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (1975). The introduction of Drosophila into the Study of Heredity, 1900–1910. Isis, 66, 322–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (1978a). Thomas hunt Morgan: The man and his science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (1978b). Thomas Hunt morgan, pioneer of genetics by Ian shine, Sylvia Wrobel. ISIS, 69(4), 635–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (1985). TH Morgan and the split between embryology and genetics 1910–1935. In T. J. Horder, J. A. Witkowski, & C. C. Wylie (Eds.), History of embryology (pp. 113–146). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (2003). Mendel and modern genetics: The legacy for today. Endeavour, 27(2), 63–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. E. (2007). A century of Evo-Devo: The dialectics of analysis and synthesis in twentieth-century life science. In M. D. Laubichler & J. Maienschein (Eds.), From embryology to Evo-Devo. A history of developmental evolution (pp. 123–167). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. (2005). The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of Evo-Devo. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, S. B., & Dupré, J. (2008). Genomes and what to make of them. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1901). Introductory note to the translation of experiments in plant hybridisation by Gregor Mendel. Journal of the Royal Horticultural Society, 26, 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benson, K. R. (2001). T. H. Morgan’s resistance to the chromosome theory. Nature Reviews Genetics, 2, 469–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. (1989). The Mendelian revolution: The emergence of hereditarian concepts in Modern science and society. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S. G. (2002). How theories became knowledge: Morgan’s chromosome theory of heredity in America and Britain. Journal of the History of Biology, 35, 471–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. M. (2000). On the internal dynamics of mendelian genetics. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, Paris, Sciences de la vie/Life Sciences, 323, 1127–1137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E. A. (1966). The gene: A critical history. Philadelphia and London: W.B. Saunders.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E. A. (2004). Mendel’s Legacy: The origin of classical genetics. Cold Spring Harbor: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E. A. (2013). How fruit flies came to launch the chromosome theory of heredity. Mutation Research, 753, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castle, W. E. (1919). Piebald rats and the theory of the genes. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 5, 126–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchill, F. B. (2015). August Weismann: Development, heredity, and evolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, W. (1984). Biology in the nineteenth century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, R., & Frezza, G. (2015). Crossovers between epigenesis and epigenetics. A multicenter approach to the history of epigenetics (1901–1975). Medicina nei Secoli, 27(1), 931–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beer, G. R. (1947). Thomas hunt morgan, experimental embryologist. Obituary Notices of Fellows of the Royal Society, 5(15), 451–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2005). Are there genes? In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Philosophy, biology and life (pp. 193–210). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • East, E. M. (1912). The mendelian notation as a description of physiological facts. American Naturalist, 46, 633–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ephrussi, B. (1958). The cytoplasm and somatic cell variation. Journal of Cellular and Comparative Physiology, 52, 35–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2000). The gene—A concept in tension. In P. J. Beurton, R. Falk, & H.-J. Rheinberger (Eds.), The concept of the gene in development and evolution: Historical and epistemological perspectives (pp. 317–348). Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2004). Applying and extending the notion of genetic linkage: The first thirty years. In H.-J. Rheinberger & J.-P. Gaudillière (Eds.), Classical genetic research and its legacy. The mapping cultures of twentieth-century genetics (pp. 34–56). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2007). Genetic analysis. In M. Matten & C. Stephens (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: Philosophy of biology (pp. 249–308). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox-Keller, E. (2000). The century of the gene. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox-Keller, E., & Harel, D. (2007). Beyond the gene. PLoS ONE, 2(11), e1231. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0001231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. G. (1977). Thomas Hunt Morgan: Pioneer of genetics by Ian Shine; Sylvia Wrobel. Journal of the History of Biology, 10(2), 365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. (1978). The embryological origins of the gene theory. Journal of the History of Biology, 11, 307–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. (1991). Developmental biology. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. (1998). Bearing crosses: A historiography of genetics and embryology. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 76, 168–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. (2012). Commentary: ‘The Epigenotype’ by C. H. Waddington. International Journal of Epidemiology, 41, 20–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B. K., & Olson, W. M. (Eds.). (2003). Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, W. (1909). Elemente der exakten Erblichkeitslehre. Jena: G. Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, T. (1988). Organisms and the mysterious X: Interdisciplinary innovation in experimental biology. Issues in Interdisciplinary Studies, 6, 51–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland, S. E. (2007). Maintaining continuity through a scientific revolution: A rereading of E. B. Wilson and T. H. Morgan on sex determination and mendelism. Isis, 98(3), 468–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, R. E. (1994). Lords of the fly: Drosophila genetics and the experimental life. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M. D., & Maienschein, J. (Eds.). (2007). From embryology to Evo-Devo. A history of developmental evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (2000). The Triple Helix: Gene, organism and environment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein, J. (1984). What determines sex: A study of converging approaches, 1880–1916. Isis, 75(3), 456–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein, J. (1991). TH Morgan’s regeneration, epigenesis, and (w)holism. In C. E. Dinsmore (Ed.), A history of regeneration research: Milestones in the evolution of a science (pp. 133–149). Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein, J. (1992). Gene: Historical perspectives. In E. Fox-Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 122–127). Boston: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein, J. (2016). Garland Allen, Thomas Hunt Morgan, and Development. Journal of the History of Biology, 49(4), 587–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manier, E. (1969). The experimental method in biology. T. H. Morgan and the theory of the gene. Synthese, 20, 185–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1901). Regeneration. New York: MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1907). Sex-determining factors in animals. Science, 25(636), 382–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1909). What are ‘factors’ in Mendelian explanations? American Breeders Association Reports, 5, 365–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1910a). Sex limited inheritance in Drosophila. Science, 32(812), 120–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1910b). Chromosomes and heredity. American Naturalist, 44, 449–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1911). An attempt to analyze the constitution of the chromosomes on the basis of sex-limited inheritance in Drosophila. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 11, 365–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1915). Constitution of heredity material. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 54(217), 143–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1917). The theory of the gene. American Naturalist, 51, 513–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1919). The physical basis of heredity. Philadelphia: Lippincott.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1922). Croonian lecture, on the mechanism of heredity. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 94, 162–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1924). Mendelian heredity and cytology. In E. V. Cowdry (Ed.), General cytology (pp. 693–728). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1926). The theory of the gene. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1927). The relation of biology to physics. Science, 65(1679), 213–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H. (1934). Embryology and genetics. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, T. H., Sturtevant, A. H., Muller, H. J., & Bridges, C. B. (1915). The mechanism of Mendelian heredity. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (2003). What genes can’t do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller, H. J. (1927). Artificial transmutation of the gene. Science, 66(1699), 84–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Orel, V. (2007). From Linnaean species to mendelian factors: Elements of Hybridism, 1751–1870. Annals of Science, 64(2), 171–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (Eds.). (2007a). Heredity produced: At the crossroad of biology, politics, and culture, 1500–1870. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (2007b). Heredity: The production of an epistemic space. In S. Müller-Wille & H.-J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Heredity produced: At the crossroad of biology, politics, and culture, 1500–1870 (pp. 3–34). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olby, R. C. (1979). Mendel no mendelian? History of Science, 17, 53–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olby R. C. (1997), Mendel, mendelism and genetics. MendelWeb. http://www.mendelweb.org/MWolby.html. Accessed 31 March 2017.

  • Oppenheimer, J. (1983). Thomas Hunt Morgan as an embryologist: The view from Bryn Mawr. American Zoology, 23(4), 845–854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2008). Heredity and its entities around 1900. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 39, 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J., & Gaudillière, J.-P. (Eds.). (2004a). Classical genetic research and its legacy. The mapping cultures of Twentieth-century genetics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J., & Gaudillière, J.-P. (Eds.). (2004b). From molecular genetics to genomics. The mapping cultures of twentieth-century genetics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger H.-J., Müller-Wille S., & Meunier R. (2015). Gene. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Spring 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/gene/. Accessed 16 March 2017.

  • Schwartz, J. H. (2006). Decisions, decisions: Why Thomas Hunt Morgan was not the ‘Father’ of Evo-Devo. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 918–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skopek, J. M. (2011). Principles, exemplars, and uses of history in early 20th century genetics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42, 210–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturtevant, A. H. (1959). Thomas Hunt Morgan 1866–1945. Biographical Memoirs of the National Academy of Sciences, 33, 280–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturtevant, A. H. (1965). A history of genetics. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunderland, M. E. (2007) Thomas Hunt Morgan (1866–1945). Embryo Project Encyclopedia. http://embryo.asu.edu/handle/10776/1675. Accessed 31 July 2017.

  • Sunderland, M. E. (2010). Regeneration: Thomas Hunt Morgan’s window into development. Journal of the History of Biology, 43(2), 325–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Speybroeck, L. (2002). From epigenesis to epigenetics. The case of C. H. Waddington. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 981, 61–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M. (2013). Models of data and theoretical hypotheses: A case-study in classical genetic. Synthese, 190(2), 293–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1942). The epigenotype. Endeavour, 1, 18–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. (2004). What was classical genetics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 15, 83–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2007). Traits, genes, and coding. In M. Matten & C. Stephens (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: Philosophy of biology (pp. 369–402). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2006). Aggregate, composed, and evolved systems: Reductionistic heuristics as means to more holistic theories. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 667–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank the organizers and the participants of the workshop “The ‘Artificial’ and the ‘Natural’ in the Life Sciences, c. 1850–1950” (University of Exeter, 26–28 June 2014) for the inspiring discussion of our paper, and in particular John Hodges and Staffan Müller-Wille for their insightful comments. We are also grateful to the anonymous referees: the points they raised forced us to make the paper stronger. We thank the Editorial Board for their valued help while reviewing the manuscript.

Funding

Funding was provided by MIUR - Italian Government (Grant No. Futuro in Ricerca 2010-RBFR10Q67A_002).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giulia Frezza.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Frezza, G., Capocci, M. Thomas Hunt Morgan and the invisible gene: the right tool for the job. HPLS 40, 31 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-018-0196-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-018-0196-z

Keywords

Navigation