1 Introduction

If a philosopher is committed to a conception of the freedom of will as the freedom of indifference, that is, the view that the will is the power to will, nill or to do nothing at all with respect to any object, as McCord Adams (1999, 245) puts it with regard to William Ockham (approx. 1288–1345), then this commitment is most likely motivated by a further commitment to the view that human morality is possible only if the will is free in the following way: human agents can be morally praised or blamed for their actions only if they could have acted differently than they actually did.Footnote 1

In the history of philosophy, voluntarists—that is, philosophers committed to some version of the freedom of indifference—have worried about its metaphysical credentials, but only a few, at least to my knowledge, have attempted to argue for more than its mere existence in this world. Ockham, for instance, admits that there is no non-circular argument for establishing the freedom of indifference. However, we can undeniably and “evidently,” as he puts it, know from experience that we are free in this way. The freedom of indifference, in his view, is real, albeit only contingently so.Footnote 2 Throughout the history of philosophy, voluntarists have seemed to minimally agree on that.

In this paper, I would like to present the ambitious attempt of the German pre-Kantian philosopher Christian August Crusius (1715–1775) to argue for the claim that it is not contingent that we have freedom of indifference—although it is a contingent truth that the world exists and that we exist. Rather, we have the freedom of indifference as a matter of hypothetical necessity.Footnote 3 The point is that, in his view, there can be no actual world without freedom of indifference. This is not a logical but a metaphysical truth.

I argue that a possible (motivational) reason for Crusius’s choice to tread this slippery path is that he wants to bestow some metaphysical dignity on the freedom of indifference by arguing that it is an inevitable, or essential, ingredient of any actual world. As a consequence, this metaphysical value of freedom of indifference shapes the relation between the divine and free, rational agents in a way that differs completely from a rationalist’s picture such as Leibniz’s. In this paper, I attempt to give a plausible interpretation of a metaphysical argument that has been neglected in the relevant literature.Footnote 4

I proceed as follows: First, I briefly sketch the relevant notion of God (2) before I turn to the different notions of cause (3) and (divine) freedom (4). Against this backdrop, I present and discuss Crusius’s argument and the metaphysical reasons for the freedom of indifference (5).

2 The Notion of God

Although Leibniz and Crusius hold opposing views on how exactly to conceive of God as a cause, they also partly agree in their notion of God. To see this, let us turn to what Crusius has to say. He writes:

…God is an intelligent and necessary, […] substance, different from the world, being the efficient cause of the world.Footnote 5

By “world” Crusius means

… the whole composed of all finite things (den Inbegriff aller endlichen Dinge), […] which we are part of.Footnote 6

Leibniz adds how these finite things are ordered:

The sufficient or ultimate reason must lie outside of the succession or series […] of these contingencies, […]. And that is why the ultimate reason for things must be a necessary substance, […]; and that is what we call God.Footnote 7

In this passage, Leibniz is literally talking about a reason, not a cause. It is clear from the context, however, that he thereby refers to an efficient cause. He is looking for the cause behind the whole series of “contingencies,” that is, contingent things. These things are concrete particulars that can be located spatiotemporally, such as substances (or to use Leibniz’s technical term: “monads”) and their doings. One can safely assume that “contingencies” are concrete particulars, because in the paragraph preceding the quote, Leibniz refers to “his present writing” as a particular.Footnote 8 In yet another section, Leibniz calls the “‘[w]orld’ the whole succession and the whole agglomeration of all existent things, …”Footnote 9 Thus, by the “succession or series […] of contingencies” Leibniz can be taken to mean the whole (or mereological sum) of the concrete particulars that make up the actual world in temporal succession.

These particulars can causally interact. As Crusius puts it, there is a real connection between them.Footnote 10 This connection is either reciprocal or unilateral.Footnote 11 The fact that two particulars a and b are reciprocally connected means that a can causally act upon b and b can causally act upon a. When a and b are unilaterally connected, a (or b) can causally act upon b (or a), but b (or a) cannot causally act upon a (or b). For the present purpose, let us assume that Leibniz and Crusius agree on the following:

(worldact):

If x is the whole of all concrete particulars that can causally interact in temporal succession, then x is the actual world.Footnote 12

According to both Leibniz and Crusius, God can be described, at least in one sense, as a necessary substance that is the efficient cause of the actual world:

(God):

If x is a necessary substance and x is the efficient cause of the actual world, then x is God.

One aspect not being made explicit here is that God is not an efficient cause in the sense that a storm is the cause of a tree’s falling down. Rather, being the most intelligent and wisest being, God’s efficient causation is an intentional, voluntary action. That means that God has a reason for causing the world, since, according to Leibniz, God “always acts for the best.”Footnote 13 It is due to this fact that human actions can be modeled on divine action: according to both authors, human subjects are the efficient, yet intelligent and, as Crusius stresses, free causes of their actions.Footnote 14

Leibniz and Crusius agree on the conditions that something must comply with in order to count as God. They also both argue for the necessary existence of God given the existence of the actual world. Their arguments are versions of the so-called cosmological argument.Footnote 15 Leibniz’s version of it runs as follows:Footnote 16

  1. 1.

    The cause of any contingent, concrete particular is distinct from that particular.

  2. 2.

    The cause of a complete, conditioned series of all concrete particulars is not part of the series of particulars.

  3. 3.

    Only a necessary substance does not have a cause distinct from itself.

  4. 4.

    Thus, only a necessary substance can be the ultimate cause of a complete, conditioned series of particulars.

  5. 5.

    God is a necessary substance.

  6. 6.

    There is complete, conditioned series of particulars.

  7. K

    Therefore, there is God.

Crusius would not object to the overall structure of this argument, since his own version of it is based on the same fundamental idea that the actual, contingent world requires a necessary cause that is distinct from it. Crusius emphasizes the threat of an infinite regress if this cause is not conceived as necessary. He writes:

The contingent has its actuality (Wircklichkeit)Footnote 17 by an efficient cause. In this way, the whole world has its reality by an efficient cause distinct from it. And since one could endlessly infer yet another and another cause if that cause were not necessary, there is a necessary and intelligent cause of the world, that is, there is a God.Footnote 18

Note that although the threat of an infinite regress is formulated in epistemological terms, according to Crusius, it is also ontologically relevant. Leibniz and Crusius seem to agree that this regress would be vicious. There cannot be an infinite regress of efficient causes because the world, being contingent, has not always existed at every past point in time.Footnote 19 Crusius, however, does not agree with Leibniz’s notion of a cause underlying the argument.

3 The Notions of Cause

At this point, it is necessary to render explicit the version of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR for short) that underlies Leibniz’s argument. It concerns concrete particulars having efficient causes. These efficient causes are, as Leibniz says, “determinant.” In his Theodicy, Leibniz formulates the principle as follows:

[T]he other principle is that of the determinant reason: it states that nothing ever comes to pass without there being a cause or at least a reason determining it, that is, something to give a priori the reason why it is existent rather than nonexistent, and in this wise rather than in any other.Footnote 20

According to this version, an efficient cause is necessary, that is, it acts necessarily by determining its effect in the following way: if all conditions are met that are required for a cause to be set into operation, the effect cannot fail to be produced, that is, it cannot not exist. Moreover, it can only exist in the way it does and not in any other way. I take the latter to mean that the cause produces exactly one (kind of) effect.Footnote 21 This is why Leibniz also refers to it as a reason that can be given a priori: you can learn what kind of effect a cause produces just by studying its nature or essence.

Crusius admits that Leibniz’s principle is valid on this reading. However, he prefers to call this version the “principle of sufficient cause” (“Satz von der zureichenden Ursache”). Like Leibniz, he applies it to concrete particulars that make up the actual world. Crusius writes:

We can conceive of a thing that exists and has formerly not existed only if we concede the existence of yet another [temporarily] prior thing; and it is by means of the latter’s sufficient power and effectiveness that the former has been produced. From this flows the rule: everything that begins to exist originates from (entsteht von) another thing that had sufficient power to produce it, and was effective without any prevailing impediment. This (other) thing we call an efficient cause, and if the cause is set into operation, and is sufficient, and not impeded, then the effect necessarily follows.Footnote 22

According to Crusius, a cause acts if all conditions are met that are required for a cause x to be set into operation and x is sufficient for producing y and there is nothing that could prevent x from exerting its power. Then, the effect y necessarily follows, that is, y comes into existence. The necessity involved here is hypothetical (as in Leibniz). By this, Crusius wants to stress that it is only contingently—and not necessarily—true that the conditions for a cause to be set into operation are met.Footnote 23 In other words, the claim that a cause only operates as a matter of hypothetical necessity means that its operating conditions are only contingently met.Footnote 24 It could have been the case that not all of these conditions were actually met on some occasion.

On the face of it, Leibniz would probably agree with Crusius’s description of the working of an efficient cause, since in his view “sufficient” just means “determinant.”Footnote 25 Crusius, however, would not agree with the latter. To see why Crusius denies this, we must bear in mind that—for both Crusius and Leibniz—the notion of a cause involves the basic notion of a power. Although their overall conception of efficient causes is very much alike, it differs in at least one important respect.Footnote 26 Crusius states:

The efficient cause, when it produces something, must be endued with a power. The power is the possibility of a conceived thing that inheres in some subject.Footnote 27

What does it mean to say that the power of a thing (a cause) is the possibility of another thing (its effect)? The idea is that if the power of a is actualized, then, as a result of its activity, b is produced. The existence of b depends on the actualization of a’s power.

I will say more about the relation of inherence shortly, which seems to be the same as the relation of subsistence, at least at first sight. Crusius further distinguishes between two kinds of powers—of which only the second is relevant in the present context:

[if] [the power] consists in an inner quality of the thing’s essence, then it is called an active power.Footnote 28

The notion of a power is intimately related to the notion of a substance, since powers can only “subsist,” as Crusius puts it, within a substance. Elsewhere he states:

[…] this power must always be connected with a substance. One can say that the power is the possibility—connected with a substance A—of a certain thing B, by virtue of which something subsists in A, by which B has or receives its reality.Footnote 29

One should note what “subsistence” and the related verb “to subsist in” mean: roughly speaking, subsistence is an asymmetrical relation of ontological dependence between things that Crusius calls “metaphysical subjects and their properties”: if a subsists in b, then b is the subject of a, and a is the property of b. The ontological relation of subsistence is asymmetrical: if a subsists in b, then b does not, and cannot, subsist in a.Footnote 30 For instance, if a person has the power to speak English, then this power “subsists in” her, since she is the subject of that property. It would not make any sense, however, to say that she, the person, “subsists in” her power to speak English.Footnote 31

Now a and b are what Crusius calls incomplete things. Together, they make up a complete thing, that is, a substance. As Crusius states, “a complete thing, insofar as it is conceived as consisting in a subject and properties, is called a substance.”Footnote 32 Note that only substances are complete things. To be complete in this sense means to be ontologically independent of any other (created) thing.Footnote 33 Thus, only substances are ontologically independent.

An example may help illustrate the relevant notion of subsistence.Footnote 34 I will paraphrase one of Crusius’s own examples.Footnote 35 Crusius asks the reader to imagine a book and to distinguish between its material (cardboard and paper) and its (brick-like) shape. Now, Crusius says that the (brick-like) shape subsists in the material (cardboard and paper). The shape is the property of the material, not the other way around. The material is the subject of the shape. If the material did not exist the way it does, the (brick-like) shape would not exist at all. Yet if the paper and cardboard were torn into pieces, the material would still exist, but with a different shape. More generally, a metaphysical subject can lose a particular property (due to some change) and still exist, whereas a metaphysical property cannot lose its particular subject without ceasing to exist.Footnote 36

Concerning the asymmetry mentioned earlier, Crusius states that since the material of the book can be located spatially, it is in some sense, but not in the same sense, “in” something else. It is in space, as the shape is “in” the material. The merely spatial relation is, of course, not the same as the relation of subsistence. These relations are not on a par, metaphysically speaking. The material is not a property of the space. Therefore, since the material does not subsist in anything else, it can be identified as the metaphysical subject of the shape.Footnote 37 The book can also be called a substance insofar as it is possible to conceive of it as something consisting in a metaphysical subject (the material) and its properties (such as its shape).Footnote 38

Applying this sense of “subsistence” to the account of powers and efficient causes, the following picture emerges: an efficient cause produces its effect by means of a power; and the power, as an “inner quality of a thing’s essence” can also be described as a property subsisting in a (metaphysical) subject. The metaphysical subject together with its properties is what a substance ultimately consists in. Therefore, substances are efficient causes, at least in the cases that are relevant here. Now, it becomes clear—at least as far as Crusius’s conception is concerned—why God is conceived of as a substance: substances, by virtue of being the metaphysical subject of powers they can exert, are efficient causes. Only substances are ontologically independent of any other (created) thing. Of course, God is also independent of any other thing: He is ontologically autonomous, so to speak. It seems that God’s perfection partly consists in this fact. What is more relevant in the present context is that Crusius also conceives of God’s perfection in terms of His freedom, that is, His free will. The important difference to Leibniz is that, as mentioned earlier, in Crusius’s view, not all causes are determinant. Again, I take “determinant” to mean that the cause (by means of exerting its power) necessarily produces exactly one (kind of) effect. The cause produces its effect such that if all conditions for a power to be actualized are met, then the effect necessarily follows.Footnote 39

Now, suppose I raise my arm. Then, I, by exerting my power to raise my arm without any prevailing impediment (my arm was not broken or tied to my back, etc.), was the sufficient cause of that action. In general, an “impediment” to the exertion of a power can be the actualization of another power. But was the cause of it also determinant?

According to Crusius, this depends on whether I also exerted another power—a power by means of which I can cause more than one (kind of) effect.Footnote 40 Roughly speaking, this is Crusius’s idea of a sufficient, yet non-determinant cause: the substance, insofar as it can exert a power that is apt to produce an effect F, or an effect non-F, or an effect G at one and the same time, is a sufficient, yet not determinant cause. The point is that if the required conditions for this power to be actualized are met, it thereby becomes merely possible, but not hypothetically necessary, that the power is set into operation.Footnote 41 This is why the reason for an action of this power can only be given a posteriori, as Crusius notes.Footnote 42 Crusius calls this power “freedom.” Only actions involving the actualization of the power of freedom are not hypothetically necessary. Against this backdrop, it is now time to turn to the different conceptions of (divine) freedom.Footnote 43

4 (Divine) Freedom

According to Crusius, God, as a substance, is the sufficient, yet not determinant cause of the world, since God exerted the power Crusius calls “freedom.” It is one of the powers that make up the will.Footnote 44 In general, the will, according to Crusius, is “the power of a mind to act according to its ideas.”Footnote 45 However, the will is not just one single power but rather a (ordered) bunch of two different kinds of powers, namely a free and a non-free power.Footnote 46 Leibniz rejects this distinction because he rejects Crusius’s notion of freedom as a power of the will. Non-free volitions are actualized states of desiring. These states can differ in degree of intensity or strength.Footnote 47 For instance, it is adequate to say that one’s desiring A is stronger than one’s desiring B. Desires, Crusius tells us, are—in most cases—not strong enough for causing us to act in order to satisfy them, and normally, more than one such state is actualized at the same time.Footnote 48 The point is that desires, at least with respect to human substances, can be caused by perceiving or imagining external things, or by thoughts and considerations. Crusius stresses that, as soon as we wake up in the morning, the perception of things actualizes many desires in us.Footnote 49 The actualization of these states is not “up to us”: we cannot choose which desires we want to have and which, even more importantly, we do not want to have in the first place. What is up to us, however, is the adoption of a desire as action-guiding. In other words, we can choose among the desires that we do not choose to have. This is the freedom of will that we have. As Crusius states:

Freedom is a power that can only choose one among its many desires; and it chooses to act in accordance with this [desire] or to connect its activity to it.Footnote 50

The key notion here is that of a choice. Crusius literally and somewhat improperly says that the power chooses one of the prevailing desires. However, as we saw above, the power is just the (metaphysical) property, not even the metaphysical subject here. Rather, the metaphysical subject is the mind in which the power of will subsists. The mind, in turn, is identical with the substance. That is, the substance chooses between desires, not the power. For instance, choosing in one and the same situation whether to pursue one’s desire for having a piece of cheesecake (which one is craving) or to go for a run instead (which one does not desire so much) is what exerting one’s power of freedom amounts to. As Crusius puts it:

Willing is called “free” when it can also be omitted or directed at something different in the same situation, and the power to do so [is called] freedom. The actual use of freedom (that is, the attempt to make real what one wills) is called “intention” or “decision”.Footnote 51

In general, the following holds:

(Free):

A substance S freely chooses to do x at T1 if and only if S chooses to do x at T1 and S could have chosen not to do x at T1 (to omit to do x) or to do y at T1.Footnote 52

One might accuse me of ascribing a notion of human—and not divine—freedom to Crusius. Recall, however, that for both Crusius and Leibniz, human freedom mirrors divine freedom (due to the so-called image thesis).Footnote 53 And Crusius further explains that, just as there are non-free and free kinds of volitions as regards the human will, one can distinguish between divine states of desiring that are constantly (and necessarily) actualized, and free activities of divine will.Footnote 54 By the latter, “something is produced or the state of an existing thing is changed.”Footnote 55 God caused the world by means of such a free activity.Footnote 56 Crusius has an argument for this. It that can be paraphrased as follows:

  1. 1.

    Some actions, that is, actualizations of powers (call them “first actions”), are such that (a) they do not constantly occur and (b) if their conditions are met, the efficient cause having the power to produce such actions can either perform an action A, or omit A, or perform some action B (at one and the same time) as long as no contradiction arises.Footnote 57

  2. 2.

    God’s action of causing the world was such a “first action,” since

  3. 3.

    neither could the world have existed before its creation

  4. 4.

    nor could it have been created from eternity,

    since this would imply the following contradiction:

  5. 5.

    the world is eternal (such that there is no cause of the world prior to it) and the world is created (such that there is a cause of the world prior to it).

  6. 6.

    Therefore, God created the world freely, that is, in a way such that He could also have not created the world at all, or could have created at least a different world.Footnote 58

Again: the world, that is, the whole of all concrete particulars that can causally interact in temporal succession,Footnote 59 is contingent and the world’s being contingent implies that the act of creating it was not necessary, but contingent.Footnote 60 The idea is this: God created the world by exerting the power of His will. According to Crusius, there are two kinds of volitional powers—a non-free and a free power. The actualized power involved in the creation of the world cannot be of the non-free kind, that is, it cannot be one of the constantly actualized states of desiring, since it is hard to see how a state that is always actualized in God could have caused the world to exist at a certain point in time. Thus, Crusius concludes, the act of creating the world (causing it to exist) must have involved an actualization of the free power, since such free or “first” acts do not constantly occur, but at a certain point of time—if at all.

Although Leibniz agrees that God created the world contingently,Footnote 61 he rejects Crusius’s conception of a sufficient yet not determinant cause and its application to God’s power of will. Even more importantly, he rejects Crusius’s notion of contingency as it is tied to the latter’s conception of freedom. For Leibniz, God necessarily acts for the best reason, since He is the wisest, that is, most rational being. For Leibniz, just as for Crusius, freedom comes in degrees. For Crusius, the point is that a power can be exerted with more or less intensity. Leibniz writes:

The more we act according to reason, the freer we are, and there is so much more servitude the more we act in accordance with the passions. For the more we act according to reason, the more we act according to the perfections of our own nature, and insofar as we allow ourselves to be carried away by passions, we are slaves to external things, which act upon us. […] For God, being the freest and most perfect substance is also the most determined by himself to do the most perfect.Footnote 62

According to this picture, human actions are never completely free insofar as they are most often influenced by passions and other non-rational elements. Only God is completely exempt from any non-rational influence. The fact that God is perfectly free means that He is wholly determined by reason. More precisely, He is determined by the best reason.Footnote 63 Perfect freedom is perfect self-determination, where reason in its highest degree is the determining principle.

As mentioned earlier, God, according to Leibniz, created the best possible world, not just any possible world, since by doing the latter He would have acted less than fully rationally, and thus, less than perfectly. This, however, would contradict His perfection, which implies perfect rationality. In Leibniz’s view, then, the following question arises as regards Crusius’s account: if God created the world in such a way that He could have created a different world or no world at all, what was His reason for choosing this world? Was it just any reason, or did He, in fact, have no reason at all? In Leibniz’s view, the problem would be the same in both cases: both would contradict God’s perfection. It should become clear in the next section that the metaphysical credentials of freedom of indifference play a crucial role in Crusius’s endeavors to show that divine freedom is compatible with a contingent creation and God’s perfection.

5 The “Non-futility Argument” and Crusius’s Analysis of Ends

If God, in Crusius’s conception, is to be perfectly rational, based on the assumption that we do not live in the best possible world, then Crusius has to provide an alternative divine principle of action.Footnote 64 Such a principle is presented in two different versions or wordings: according to the first, God never acts in vain, that is, in such a way that whatever He does is futile.Footnote 65 According to the second, God never acts without an end (or “against an end”).Footnote 66 How do the two versions relate to one another?

It should be clear that, in the sense relevant in the context of intentional actions, acting without an end (or “against” it) could count as acting in vain, or as doing something futile. This, of course, applies to human actions, which can be, and actually are, less than perfectly rational—and not to divine actions. The point just is that, due to His perfection, it is impossible for God to act without (or “against”) an end.

In order to better understand what exactly is at stake here, we must consider the relevant notion of futility and Crusius’s analysis of ends. The notion of futility is an ontological notion. In general, something is, ontologically speaking, futile if nothing different from that thing becomes either possible or actual by the thing alone or in combination with other things.Footnote 67 To put it more formally:

(futile)ont:

x is futile if and only if there is no y such that y is possible or actual because of x (or because of x together with z, …) where y is different from x.

“Futile” in this ontological sense also applies to actions, since they are a kind of thing. It is possible to say that an action is futile (or not futile) and thereby to say something true or false. One difference between divine and human action is that if one says that a human action is futile (or not), one says something contingently true (or false). If one says that a divine action is futile (or not), one says something necessarily true (or false), since God cannot do anything futile, whereas humans can.

“Futile” can also have a different sense, which involves a failed intentional action, that is, an action that brought about something one did not intend to bring about.Footnote 68 For instance, if Peter intended to kiss Anne in order to make her happy, but due to a mistake ended up kissing her twin sister, then he failed to make Anne happy by kissing her. However, he might have made her twin sister happy, however, unintentionally.Footnote 69 In this case, his action was not futile in the purely ontological sense. It is, of course, impossible that there could be any failed action by God. The reason is the same as for why He cannot do anything—ontologically—futile: it would be incompatible with His perfection.

The ontological sense of “futile” is at work in the principle that God cannot do anything futile. This is why it is metaphysically impossible for there to be one single thing in the actual world which would be futile in the ontological sense. The point is that God’s free actions are acts of creating (and sustaining) things, that is, substances and their powers.Footnote 70 Crusius states:

… God cannot do anything whose existence would be totally futile at any moment, that is, neither with respect to the thing created nor with respect to Him, so that by (that thing) it would not be the case that anything different from that thing would constantly be made real or possible.Footnote 71

More formally, we can hold:

(futile)div:

A divine action A is futile if and only if nothing different from A becomes constantly possible or real by A, that is, either in relation to the thing created by A, or in relation to the divine agent.

How are we to take the two relational specifications here—(a) with respect to the thing created and (b) with respect to the divine agent? In order to answer this, we must turn to Crusius’s analysis of ends. Intentional actions, divine or human, are determined by their ends. An end is, in the widest sense, “what a mind wills.”Footnote 72 Crusius adds that, in the proper, or narrower, sense, to will something as an end implies to will it “consciously and with distinct knowledge.”Footnote 73 Free intentional actions require reason, as Crusius repeatedly emphasizes.Footnote 74 An end has three components which make up one complete end. Crusius also speaks of the “end’s integrity.”Footnote 75

Whenever an agent consciously and knowingly wills to do something for the sake of an end, these three components are involved: (i) an actual state of desiring (this is called the “subjective end”), (ii) an object of this actual state of desiring (“the objectual end”) and (iii) some relation the action is taken to establish between the subject and the desired object (the “formal end”). Crusius gives the example of Alexander the Great, who went to war against the Persian Empire. In this case, (i) Alexander’s desire was to rule (“subjective end”), (ii) the object of his desire was the Persian Empire (“objectual end”) which (iii) he wanted to bring under his command by going to war (“formal end”).Footnote 76

This analysis also applies to the ends of God’s action of creating the world. Crusius has no difficulties in identifying God’s integral end of creating the actual world. As to (i), the state of desiring, Crusius identifies it as God’s “longing for perfection and for love and goodness.”Footnote 77 This kind of desiring or willing is constantly and necessarily actualized in God, since it is part of the non-free and necessary kind of willing.Footnote 78

(ii) The object of God’s desire is the world, which, before it was created, existed as something that was possible in God’s mind.Footnote 79 Among all things that are created, free rational minds play a privileged role, since they are the “final objectual end” of creation.Footnote 80 Why is that? The problem with divine action is that there cannot be any action by means of which God’s perfection could be increased, since His perfection is infinite.Footnote 81 So why should God, according to this picture, act at all, given that His actions will make no difference with respect to God himself and His divine properties? Referring to divine goodness, as Leibniz seems to do, will not suffice for solving the problem that—according to Crusius’s analysis of ends—there seems to be no proper reason for God to create the world at all. The problem is that creating the world neither increases His power, wisdom or goodness, nor His knowledge of them.Footnote 82 Crusius’s answer is that—although God cannot act in order to add anything to, or qualitatively “improve,” His essential properties—He can nevertheless act in order to add something in relation to Him.

The point is that (iii) the formal end of creation is something that can only be established by free rational creatures: God wants rational agents to freely act in accordance with what He has determined to be (morally) good.Footnote 83 The formal end of creation is that rational agents freely obey the natural law implemented by God. It is a matter of relation insofar as the fact that rational agents act freely and, in accordance with God’s wishes, sometimes even morally, affects their relation to God as their “overlord.” If rational agents were determined to act in accordance with this natural law, it would make no difference whether they existed as possible beings in God’s mind or as actual creations of God: His relation to them would be the same with respect to their actions, since in both cases God would be the one who determined them. This does not apply to free actions, since it is only their possibility that wholly depends on God insofar as He created freedom as a power.

Crusius provides an argument by means of which he wants to establish that there actually are free (human) actions. They are the formal end of creation. The “non-futility” argument runs as follows:

  1. 1.

    If a concrete particular p is not free or is not the effect of a free action, then God is the determinant cause of p.

  2. 2.

    If God were the determinant cause of every concrete particular (p1, p2, p3, …pn), then the relation between God and all particulars (p1, p2, p3, …pn) would be the same before and after the particulars were created: all particulars would be totally dependent on God in both cases.

  3. 3.

    Thus, if all particulars (= the whole world) were totally dependent on God, whether possible or actual, then there would be no formal end of God’s act of creating the world, that is, there would never be any relation between any of the particulars and God that did not obtain before creation.

  4. 4.

    However, it is contradictory to God’s perfection that He could act without a formal end. (“God never acts without an end”).

  5. 5.

    Free actions of human substances are the formal end of creation, since only the power of freedom, not its actualization, wholly depends on God.

  6. 6.

    God created the world.

  7. 7.

    Therefore, there are free actions of human substances.Footnote 84

The formal end of divine action requires that it can establish something that (a) did not exist before and (b) that—in some respect—does not totally depend on God. The latter can only be an agent who can act freely, but in accordance with natural law: this is what God desires free agents to accomplish due to His perfection.

By the “non-futility argument,” Crusius wants to establish that we are free in this way. At least this argument is non-circular: recall that I mentioned in the Introduction that Ockham, another voluntarist, even doubts the possibility of arguing for the existence of freedom of indifference in a non-circular way. What is more, Crusius provides a metaphysical reason for why there is freedom of indifference in any actual world as a matter of hypothetical necessity. In other words, he provides a reason why the conditional, if there is a world, then there is freedom of indifference, necessarily holds: because it is metaphysically impossible that there be any futile divine action in the previously explained sense.

Of course, you may not find this argument very convincing and the metaphysical assumptions it rests upon questionable and obsolete. They can be seen, however, as part of Crusius’s attempt to bestow some metaphysical value or dignity upon the freedom of indifference.Footnote 85

6 Conclusion

My aim in this paper was to make plausible the claim that Crusius’s metaphysical argument for the hypothetical necessity of freedom of indifference can be interpreted as an attempt to bestow some metaphysical value or dignity upon this kind of freedom. In the history of philosophy, it has been suspected of favoring and promoting the possibility of acting “outside the bounds of reason,” as McCord Adams puts it (1999, 266). Crusius, however, makes it very clear that this kind of freedom necessarily presupposes rationality.Footnote 86 The fact that people can freely act against their rational insights merely affirms what experiences teaches us. But it neither shows that one is allowed to act stupidly, nor that one should act in that way.Footnote 87

If Crusius’s argument, as reconstructed here, were successful, he could maintain that, although we might not live in the best of all possible worlds, our freedom of indifference carries the metaphysical weight of being the one indispensable ingredient of any actual world. It is no coincidence, of course, that according to the “image” thesis,Footnote 88 the most important and “superb” aspect in which man is made in the image of God, is freedom of indifference. Only a creature that has that power can—at least to some extent—act independently of its maker.Footnote 89

According to this picture, the relation between rational and free agents and the divine agent is one of total ontological dependence, but the moral dependence of rational agents has a clearly voluntary element: becoming a moral agent and thus perfecting oneself is not simply, as Leibniz claims, a matter of merely removing the obstacles to rational self-determination, but a matter of actively and positively taking a step in the morally “right” direction. It is literally up to us whether we comply with the divine wish to see us act morally (Figs. 1, 2).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Picture of the voluntarist: the rational agent has to actively take a step toward the morally good

Fig. 2
figure 2

Picture of the rationalist: the rational agent has to remove any obstacle to the determining power of reason by which he knows what is morally good

Besides its metaphysical value as a hypothetically necessary element of any actual world, freedom of indifference allows us to actively make a difference in this world on the basis of the available reasons—and not just by making sure that the determining power of reason can do its work unimpeded. In the end, the difference between the rationalist’s and the voluntarist’s approach could be framed in terms of the agents’ own activity or passivity concerning their attempt at doing what is morally right (or wrong).Footnote 90 The voluntarist has to actively embrace what she recognizes to be good in order to let reason become effective. By contrast, the rationalist has to make sure that nothing impedes reason’s insight into what is good (and right). She has to let her action be determined by what is good. Although the voluntarist’s approach might, in some sense, imply as real the possibility of acting less than perfectly rational, it also implies a kind of independence or autonomy that values the agent’s own activity at least as much as rationality.