Skip to main content
Log in

How to Live a Life of One’s Own: Heidegger, Marcuse and Jonas on Technology and Alienation

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I explore Martin Heidegger’s and Herbert Marcuse’s critiques of technology, and their suggestions on how to neutralise the negative effects of technology, in order to articulate a potential path to an authentic, unalienated life. Martin Heidegger’s view of technology and its negative effects are first explored before presenting Marcuse’s critique of Heidegger. The dissimilarities between Heidegger’s ‘Gestell’ and Marcuse’s ‘Technological Rationality’ are then explored, before then examining the differences between Heidegger’s and Marcuse’s ideas of how one may overcome the alienating impact of technology. Favouring Marcuse’s suggestions, Hans Jonas’ work on technological ethics is then posited as a necessary guide for Marcuse’s vision of a post-alienated existence. I conclude that the continued appropriation and integration of Heideggerian thought into critiques of technology could be valuable for the field, especially when answering questions concerning individual authenticity in the context of rapid technological progress and ecological decline.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This point is one that is also made by more recent critiques of technology. Perhaps, most explicitly by John Gray: “There is a deeper reason why ‘humanity’ will never control technology. Technology is not something humankind can control. It is an event that has befallen the world.” (Gray 2003: 14).

  2. Like Heidegger, Richard Rorty is also hostile towards the loss of interpretive diversity. See Rorty 1979., ch. 7 and 8.

  3. It is not just in a social sense that this warning applies—consideration of the work of synthetic biologists that seek to manipulate our genetic make up for various functional ends (see Schyfter 2011) or the role that technology has in our evolutionary history (see Idhe and Malafouris 2019) reveals that Heidegger’s warning also applies in a very literal sense.

  4. The image of technology as a fatalistic force is again one that reappears in contemporary expositions of technology. See Kelly 2017 and Zuboff 2019, respectively, for a sympathetic and hostile engagement with technological inevitability and its effects.

  5. So much so that it seems that Heidegger’s Gestell could have directly influenced Marcuse’s idea of Technological Rationality, but this does not actually appear to be the case. The notion of Gestell was introduced by Heidegger in his 1949 lecture Positionality and was later developed in his 1954 The Question Concerning Technology. Marcuse’s notion of Technological Rationality was first introduced in 1941, in his Some Implications of Modern Technology. One could speculate that Heidegger’s influence on Technological Rationality originated from Marcuse’s development of related ideas found within Being and Time—such as Heidegger’s exposition of equipment—but one cannot know this for certain, nor can one rule out the possibility that Heidegger’s own thinking was influenced by that of his former student.

  6. Heidegger is not invoking history in the sense of “that which is chronicled” (Heidegger 1954: 329)—i.e. in its historiographical historisch sense—but rather in its ontological geschichtlich sense, as “the process of human activity … [that becomes] accessible as an object for historiography” (ibid).

  7. Here, there is resonance between the telos of Marcuse’s and Jonas’ work and the vital interests identified by J. S. Mill: “The moral rules which forbid mankind to hurt one another (in which we must never forget to include wrongful interference with each other’s freedom) are more vital to human well-being than any maxims, however important, which only point out the best mode of managing some department of human affairs” (Mill 1863: 96).

References

  • Dreyfus, H. L., & Spinosa, C. (1997). Highway bridges and feasts: Heidegger and Borgmann on how to affirm technology. Man and World, 30, 159–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (2003). Straw dogs: thoughts on humans and other animals. London: Granta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. 1951. Building Dwelling Thinking. Translated from German by W. Lovitt. 1977. In: Basic Writings: Revised and expanded edition. 1993. D. F. Krell (ed). Oxford, UK: Routledge.

  • Heidegger, M. 1954. The Question Concerning Technology. Translated from German by W. Lovitt. 1977. In: Basic Writings: Revised and expanded edition. 1993. D. F. Krell (ed). Oxford, UK: Routledge.

  • Heidegger, M. 1959/1966. Discourse on Thinking. Translated from German by J. M. Anderson and E. H. Freud. New York, NY: Harper and Row.

  • Idhe, D. and Malafouris, L., 2019. Homo faber revisited: postphenomenology and material engagement theory. Philosophy & Technology. 32. 195-214.

  • Jonas, H. 1979. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age. Translated from German by H. Jonas and D. Herr. 1984. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Kelly, K., 2017. The Inevitable: Understanding the 12 Technological Forces that will Shape our Future. London, UK: Penguin.

  • Marcuse, H., 1938. On Hedonism. Translated from German by J. J. Shapiro. In: Negations: Essays in Critical Theory. 2009. London, UK: Mayfly.

  • Marcuse, H., 1941. Some social implications of modern technology. In: Technology, War and Fascism: Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, Volume One. 2004. D. Kellner (ed). New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Marcuse, H. (1964/2002). One-Dimensional Man (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, H., 1965. Industrialization and capitalism in the work of Max Weber. Translated from German by J. J. Shapiro. In: Negations: Essays in Critical Theory. 2009. London, UK: Mayfly.

  • Marcuse, H., 1970. Five Lectures: Psychoanalysis, Politics, and Utopia. Translated From German by J. J. Shapiro and S. M. Weber. London, UK: Allen Lane.

  • Marcuse, H. 1977. Heidegger’s Politics: An Interview. In: Heideggerian Marxism. 2005. R. Wolin and J. Abromeit (eds). Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska Press

  • Mill, J. S., 1863/2017. Utilitarianism: With Related Remarks from Mill’s Other Writings. Edited by B. Eggleston. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Rorty, R. (1979/2009). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature: Thirtieth-Anniversary Edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schyfter, P. (2011). Standing reserves of function: a Heideggerian reading of synthetic biology. Philosophy & Technology, 25, 199–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuboff, S. (2019). The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier of Power. London: Profile Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kieran M. Brayford.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brayford, K.M. How to Live a Life of One’s Own: Heidegger, Marcuse and Jonas on Technology and Alienation. Philos. Technol. 34, 609–617 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-020-00417-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-020-00417-4

Keywords

Navigation