Skip to main content
Log in

Symmetry and partial belief geometry

  • Paper in Formal Methods and Exact Sciences
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When beliefs are quantified as credences, they are related to each other in terms of closeness and accuracy. The “accuracy first” approach in formal epistemology wants to establish a normative account for credences (probabilism, Bayesian conditioning, principle of indifference, and so on) based entirely on the alethic properties of the credence: how close it is to the truth. To pull off this project, there is a need for a scoring rule. There is widespread agreement about some constraints on this scoring rule (for example propriety), but not whether a unique scoring rule stands above the rest. The Brier score equips credences with a structure similar to metric space and induces a “geometry of reason.” It enjoys great popularity in the current debate. I point out many of its weaknesses in this article. An alternative approach is to reject the geometry of reason and accept information theory in its stead. Information theory comes fully equipped with an axiomatic approach which covers probabilism, standard conditioning, and Jeffrey conditioning. It is not based on an underlying topology of a metric space, but uses a non-commutative divergence instead of a symmetric distance measure. I show that information theory, despite initial promise, also fails to accommodate basic epistemic intuitions; and speculate on its remediation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armendt, B. (1980). Is there a dutch book argument for probability kinematics?. Philosophy of Science, 47(4), 583–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borges, J. (1962). Ficciones. New York, NY: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bregman, L. (1967). The relaxation method of finding the common point of convex sets and its application to the solution of problems in convex programming. USSR Computational Mathematics and Mathematical Physics, 7(3), 200–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bronfman, A. (2009). A gap in joyce’s argument for probabilism. University of Michigan: unpublished manuscript.

  • Chino, N. (1978). A graphical technique for representing the asymmetric relationships between n objects. Behaviormetrika, 5(5), 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1999). Measuring confirmation. Journal of Philosophy, 96(9), 437–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coombs, C.H. (1964). A theory of data. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coxon, A. (1982). The user’s guide to multidimensional scaling. Exeter: Heinemann Educational Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csiszár, I., & Shields, P.C. (2004). Information theory and statistics: A tutorial. Hanover: Now Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dawid, A.P., Lauritzen, S., & Parry, M. (2012). Proper local scoring rules on discrete sample spaces. Annals of Statistics, 40(1), 593–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (2017). Theory of probability. Chichester: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gentleman, R., Ding, B., Dudoit, S., & Ibrahim, J. (2006). Distance measures in dna microarray data analysis. In R. Gentleman, V. Carey, W. Huber, R. Irizarry, & S. Dudoit (Eds.) Bioinformatics and Computational Biology Solutions Using R and Bioconductor. Springer.

  • Goldstein, M. (1983). The prevision of a prevision. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 78(384), 817–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I.J. (1952). Rational decisions. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B (Methodological), 14(1), 107–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünwald, P.D., & Dawid, A.P. (2004). Game theory, maximum entropy, minimum discrepancy and robust bayesian decision theory. The Annals of Statistics, 32(4), 1367–1433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2003). What conditional probability could not be. Synthese, 137(3), 273–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harshman, R., & Lundy, M. (1984). The parafac model for three-way factor analysis and multidimensional scaling. In H.G. Law (Ed.) Research methods for multimode data analysis (pp. 122–215). New York: Praeger.

  • Harshman, R.A., Green, P.E., Wind, Y., & Lundy, M.E. (1982). A model for the analysis of asymmetric data in marketing research. Marketing Science, 1(2), 205–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendrickson, A., & Buehler, R. (1971). Proper scores for probability forecasters. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 42(6), 1916–1921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2008). De finetti, countable additivity, consistency and coherence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific reasoning: The bayesian approach, 3rd edn. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2015). The value of truth: A reply to howson. Analysis, 75(3), 413–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopperman, R. (1988). All topologies come from generalized metrics. American Mathematical Monthly, 95(2), 89–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, J. (2015). Probabilism, entropies and strictly proper scoring rules. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 63, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010). An objective justification of bayesianism i: Measuring inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 201–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1987). The demons of decision. The Monist, 70(2), 193–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinstein, B.A. (2012). Leitgeb and pettigrew on accuracy and updating. Philosophy of Science, 79(3), 413–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lukits, S. (2013). The principle of maximum entropy and a problem in probability kinematics. Synthese, 1–23.

  • MacKay, D. (2003). Information theory, inference and learning algorithms. Cambridge: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1992). Diachronic rationality. Philosophy of Science, 120–141.

  • Marschak, J. (1959). Remarks on the economics of information. Technical Report, Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics, Yale University.

  • McCarthy, J. (1956). Measures of the value of information. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 42(9), 654–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1984). A geometry of logic. In H. Skala, S. Termini, & E. Trillas (Eds.) Aspects of Vagueness (pp. 91–104). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Mormann, T. (2005). Geometry of logic and truth approximation. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 83(1), 431–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L.A. (2016). Transformative experience. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pemberton, M., & Rau, N. (2016). Mathematics for economists: An introductory textbook. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the laws of credence. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Predd, J., Seiringer, R., Lieb, E., Osherson, D., Poor, H.V., & Kulkarni, S. (2009). Probabilistic coherence and proper scoring rules. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, 55(10), 4786–4792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rockafellar, R. (1997). Convex analysis. Princeton: Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. (1971). Elicitation of personal probabilities and expectations. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 66(336), 783–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R. (1998). Axiomatic characterization of the quadratic scoring rule. Experimental Economics, 1(1), 43–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(1), 379–423, 623–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1986). Dynamic coherence. In Advances in the Statistical Sciences: Foundations of Statistical Inference (pp. 233–243). Springer.

  • Talbott, W.J. (1991). Two principles of bayesian epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 62(2), 135–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tobler, W. (1975). Spatial interaction patterns. Schloss Laxenburg: International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Ommen, S., Hendriks, P., Gilbers, D., van Heuven, V., & Gooskens, C. (2013). Is diachronic lenition a factor in the asymmetry in intelligibility between danish and swedish?. Lingua, 137, 193–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wroński, L. (2016). Belief update methods and rules: Some comparisons. Ergo, 3(11).

Download references

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Paul Bartha at the University of British Columbia and Franz Huber at the University of Toronto for their support as I worked on this paper.

Funding

The author received financial support for the research, authorship, and publication of this article from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, SSHRC award 756-2017-0286.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefan Lukits.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Ethical Approval

The author declares that no ethical approval was needed for this paper and the study was conducted in accordance with the Helsinki Declaration.

Informed Consent

The author declares that no informed consent was needed for this paper.

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the Topical Collection: EPSA2019: Selected papers from the biennial conference in Geneva

Guest Editors: Anouk Barberousse, Richard Dawid, Marcel Weber

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lukits, S. Symmetry and partial belief geometry. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 11, 79 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00398-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00398-x

Keywords

Navigation