1 Introduction

A perusal of the literature reveals that rather little has been written down concerning the analogies between interpretations of quantum mechanics and of statistical mechanics—though such analogies have hardly escaped notice. Indeed, interpretive work on the two theories has proceeded largely independently. My aim in this paper is to go some way in rectifying the omission by drawing out these analogies explicitly, in particular by showing how they may be grounded on the way in which the theories’ stochasticity, as I will call it, is represented and interpreted, with the further aims of showing how this integrative perspective can shed light on current issues in the philosophy of physics and suggest fruitful possibilities for future investigation.

Quantum mechanics and classical statistical mechanics are both theories of statistical physics, whose empirical content depends on the objective probabilities that arise in these theories.Footnote 1 The presence of these objective probabilities indicates that an element of randomness—or stochasticity,Footnote 2 as I will prefer to say—is an essential element in the theories’ explanations and descriptions.Footnote 3 My first point is that this stochasticity can be represented theoretically in three ways: in the determination of the system’s initial conditions, in the evolution of its states, or in the realization of its physical properties. I then show that this furnishes a nice typology of familiar interpretations of statistical mechanics and of quantum mechanics, one where the apparent analogies between corresponding interpretations are made manifest.

Although, as said, there has been little written on these analogies in general, there is one well-known interpretational analogy which has been drawn out in some detail, namely, between (a certain popular version of) Bohmian mechanics and the so-called “Boltzmannian” approach to classical statistical mechanics (Allori et al. 2014; Allori and Zanghì 2004; Dürr 2001; Dürr et al.1992, 1995; Goldstein 2001, 2012). The basis of this particular analogy has been identified by their proponents as ontological in character. In both theories the basic entities of the world are characterized as particles moving deterministically in space and time, just as in classical particle mechanics. However, each necessarily goes beyond classical particle mechanics by, inter alia, introducing probabilities (or likelihoods of some kind), via macroscopic states and quantum states, respectively. Since the underlying dynamics is deterministic in both cases, the only way that objective probabilistic indeterminism can enter these interpretive pictures is in the setting of initial conditions (or, equivalently, in the realization of a particular complete deterministic history of particle motions from the set of possible motions). Accordingly, in statistical mechanics one sees the invocation of an initial “past state” (Albert 2000) and, analogously, in quantum mechanics the positing of a “quantum equilibrium” initial state (Dürr et al. 1992), both of which serve this essential requirement.

While proponents of these interpretations tend to highlight the common “primitive ontology” as the origin of the analogy (Allori and Zanghì 2004), I suggest that one can equally well point to the common implementation of stochasticity in terms of the selection of initial conditions. It follows from taking this point of view—that the implementation of stochasticity grounds the analogy and not a common ontological picture—that the possible interpretive analogies between quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics do not end at Bohmian mechanics and Boltzmannian statistical mechanics.

There are several reasons to take up the interpretive framework proposed here. In the first place, it makes heretofore merely implicit analogies explicit and explains them. In the second, it opens up the landscape of interpretations that may be considered in classical statistical mechanics, a landscape which has been little explored so far. In the third, it suggests how one might take advantage of ideas developed in one theoretical context and apply them to the other. This is because having an explicit grounding for the analogies serves as a conceptual map, of sorts, between the two theories, which one can use to connect or translate interpretational issues between them. In some cases this might problematize some unexamined presuppositions on one side of the analogy; in others it might suggest novel solutions which were apparent on one side but not the other.Footnote 4

To indicate some of the potentially fruitful possibilities afforded by this point of view, I will consider how two interpretive issues in quantum mechanics, the quantum measurement problem and primitive ontology, arise also in statistical mechanics by exploiting the analogies I draw. First, I show how debates on primitive ontology in quantum mechanics can be reprised in classical statistical mechanics when one makes use of the full menu of interpretive options suggested by my proposal. I focus on the particular problems presented in Belot (2011) to illustrate its application. Second, I show how certain presentations of the quantum measurement problem may be seen as essentially posing an interpretive question concerning how to conceive of the stochasticity of quantum mechanics. I do this by constructing an analog of one of these presentations (Maudlin 1995) in classical statistical mechanics and indicating that the possible solutions to the problem are precisely the possibilities identified by my framework. Note, however, that in neither case will I advance any particular resolution to these problems here, as this paper’s focus is on developing the interpretive framework itself.

I begin in Section 2 with the aforementioned Boltzmann-Bohm analogy, as it is most familiar and will be a useful contrast for my approach. In Section 3 I motivate and introduce my interpretive framework, situating various interpretations of statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics within it along the way. In Section 4 I connect the discussion of primitive ontology in quantum mechanics to the interpretive framework of this paper. Then in Section 5 I suggest how one can generate a statistical mechanical measurement problem analogous to (a certain presentation of) the quantum measurement problem, to which each of the implementations of stochasticity offers a solution strategy. Finally, Section 6 is a brief conclusion.

2 Boltzmannian-Bohmian interpretations of mechanics

According to their supporters, the key idea behind Boltzmannian statistical mechanics and Bohmian quantum mechanics is that these theories are fundamentally about individual systems of microscopic entities (Allori et al. 2014; Allori and Zanghì 2004; Dürr 2001; Dürr et al. 1992, 1995; Goldstein 2001, 2012), usually assumed to be collections of particles. Whereas the standard “Gibbsian” techniques in statistical mechanics are often understood to invoke a fictitious ensemble of microscopic systems (Lavis 1977) and standard quantum mechanics a “wave function” in place of classical particles or fields, Boltzmannian and Bohmian mechanics are said to have a clear ontology of “local beables” (Bell 2004). This is said to be a virtue because, as a matter of method, “the first step in the construction of a physical theory is to establish what are the mathematical entities (particles, fields, strings,...) with which one intends to describe physical reality” (Allori and Zanghì 2004, 1744). Supposing that this is a sage piece of guidance, let us follow it to see where it leads.Footnote 5

2.1 Classical mechanics

So let us begin with a mathematically precise description of the physical reality which these theories purport.Footnote 6 This physical reality is essentially based on the description of physical reality given by classical particle mechanics. It is set within the classical conception of Euclidean space Σ and time τ (where these are supplied with the appropriate mathematical description—set theory will be mostly sufficient for my purposes here). At each instant tτ, every physical particle iN (for n labeled particles) has some location x(t,i) ∈Σ in space, which one may describe mathematically with a map τ ×N →Σ. Thus, for a particular particle i at time t we have (t,i)↦x(t,i).

If one models classical space and time as a four-dimensional spacetime Στ, then each particle traces out a continuous motion \(\gamma _{i} \subset {\Sigma }^{\tau }\) (the image set of a curve with pre-image τ) in spacetime (its worldline).Footnote 7 The key idea behind this construction is that, with a particular motion γi in one’s hands, one has all the physical content related to an individual particle available (given relevant observable functions to represent its physical properties). So in the simple case of classical mechanics, this ontological starting point leads directly to the complete descriptive content of the theory.

Mechanics is not usually described in terms of this space-and-time picture, instead making use of the notion of a configuration \(q=(x_{1},x_{2},\dots ,x_{N})\), which specifies the location xi of each particle i in the abstract configuration space Q = ΣN. With configuration space, we can re-express the map τ ×N →Σ as a new map τQ = ΣN (i.e., by currying). Thus, for a particular time t we have \(t \mapsto q_{t} = (x_{1}, x_{2},\dots ,x_{N})_{t}\). This move to configuration space is fully equivalent to the space-and-time picture; it is just a convenient redescription.

To describe motions based on configuration space we need to make use of the extended configuration space Qτ. Each individual motion γi of each particle i in spacetime can be incorporated into a single continuous motion ζQτ in extended configuration space.Footnote 8 Again, nothing is lost (and equally nothing is gained, save convenience) by moving to configuration space, as a motion ζ is sufficient to capture all the physical content related to a complete physical system, an entire classical system of particles (given relevant observable functions to represent their physical properties).

The establishment of physical reality has so far proceeded handsomely, and there is no reason to question the ontological starting point from a physical point of view. Still, while the collection of motions γi or the single motion ζ is descriptively adequate, it is not yet explanatorily adequate, for we lack the dynamical underpinnings (which may or may not be part of reality, depending on one’s point of view) required for a mechanical explanation. To incorporate these underpinnings into our description of physical reality, we need to specify not only of the position of each particle at a time but also its velocity (or momentum) for an initial value problem to be well-posed. Therefore, it is necessary to expand configuration space to incorporate the additional “degrees of freedom”, constructing the (time-indexed) phase space Γt, which has twice the degrees of freedom of Q: half of them are the positional degrees of freedom and half the velocital or momental degrees of freedom.

A deterministic dynamics for a specific system can then be represented as a one-parameter family of bijective maps ϕt :Γ tU, indexed by time t, where U is the space of dynamically possible motions of the system in extended configuration space Qτ. These dynamical maps send elements of the phase space (“microstates”) at a time t, (q,p)tΓt, to the system’s full motion ζ through extended configuration space Qτ. In the usual case the time subscript may be dropped, as the time-indexed phase spaces are isomorphic. Note also that we may obtain time evolution between instants by composing dynamical maps with inverse dynamical maps. For example, for the evolution of a state between time t and \(t^{\prime }\) we use the map \(\phi_{tt}^{\prime}: \phi_{t^{\prime}}^{-1} \circ \phi_{t}\), so that \((q,p)_{t} \in \varGamma _{t} \mapsto (q^{\prime },p^{\prime })_{t^{\prime }} \in \varGamma _{t^{\prime }}\), or, when the instantaneous phase spaces are isomorphic, simply (q,p)↦(q,p).

Mathematically speaking, the picture of reality obtained by following these incremental steps, beginning with nothing more than space, time, and particles, is unquestionably elegant and powerful. Perhaps there is room to question the ontological grounds of the dynamics, which may seem obscure. Various philosophical strategies may be employed, however, to reduce, eliminate, or otherwise prescind from the ostensible ontological significance of dynamical laws. After all, the descriptive content is contained entirely in the kinematical motions, not the dynamics.

2.2 Bohmian and Boltzmannian addenda

In Boltzmannian statistical mechanics one adds to the classical picture above first the notion of a macrostate. While microstates are characterized (as before) by certain microscopic properties of particles (position and either momentum or velocity), macrostates are introduced to represent various macroscopic properties (like pressure). In the Boltzmannian picture, the latter are realized, however, by microstates in the following sense: if M is the collection of the macrostates of some system, then there is a projection map π :ΓM that partitions the phase space Γ into macroregions associated bijectively with the macrostates. Therefore, if one knows the macrostate of a system, then one does not automatically know its underlying microstate; however, given a microstate, the corresponding macrostate of the system is absolutely determined. Furthermore, the macrostate dynamics is entirely determined by the microstate dynamics in virtue of this projection relation: a “macrostate motion” ν through Mτ is given by the projected microstate dynamics πϕt (where I abuse terminology to allow π to project from microscopic motions in Qτ to macroscopic motions Mτ in the obvious way). Thus, much as in classical particle mechanics, a motion in an extended (microscopic) phase space is sufficient to capture all the descriptive content of a system described by Boltzmannian statistical mechanics. So far so good.

Bohmian mechanics also goes beyond the classical picture, adding quantum states in the form of quantum wave functions. These are particular (L2) complex-valued functions on configuration space QC. The wave function dynamics is given by the Schrödinger equation (which is not determined completely by the particle dynamics, as the macrostate dynamics is in Boltzmannian statistical mechanics). I treat the wave function dynamics as maps of the form \(U_{t}: {\mathcal{H}} \to {\mathcal{H}}^{\tau }\) indexed by time t, where \({\mathcal{H}}\) is the Hilbert space of wave functions (ignoring overall phase factors). Importantly, the particle dynamics in Bohmian mechanics is not the same as the dynamics in classical particle mechanics. Instead, it depends only on the particle configuration (not the system’s state in phase space) and on the wave function. Thus, the particle dynamics of Bohmian mechanics, usually represented by the so-called “guidance equation” (for the particles are said to be “guided” by the wave function), can be given by maps of the form \(\phi _{t}^{\psi _{t}}: Q \to Q^{\tau }\), indexed by time t and the quantum state ψt at time t. Nevertheless, despite the differences, a motion ζ in the extended particle configuration space is sufficient to capture all the physical content of a system described by Bohmian mechanics, exactly as in classical particle mechanics.

Clearly, Boltzmannian statistical mechanics and Bohmian quantum mechanics share many salient features. First, the basic ontology of the interpretations, our starting point, is particles moving in space and time. But, importantly, they also include some extra structure: macroscopic states or quantum wave functions (which may or may not be part of the basic ontology, depending on how these are interpreted (Ney and Albert 2013)). Still, since a motion in extended configuration space is sufficient to capture the physical content of a system described by Bohmian mechanics, Boltzmannian statistical mechanics, or classical mechanics, one might well say, with Bell, that “in physics the only observations we must consider are position observations, if only the positions of instrument pointers” (Bell 1982, 996). Second, the dynamics of the particles and of the extra ontology are fully deterministic. Therefore, the core of the two theories is essentially that of classical mechanics, with only slight modifications needed to account, respectively, for certain macroscopic phenomena (temperature, the approach to equilibrium, etc.) or quantum phenomena (spin, entanglement, etc.).Footnote 9 That this common picture of microscopic entities moving in space and time is applicable in such varied theories is, one must admit, surely a point in its favor.

2.3 Probability

However, this picture is still incomplete in the cases of statistical mechanics and of quantum mechanics, since both theories depend essentially on probabilities for their empirical content, and this is captured principally by statistics of observables. In statistical mechanics the relevant empirical frequencies are of the macroscopic properties; in Bohmian mechanics they are of quantum observables (that are, according to Bohmian doctrine, of course, ultimately reducible to particle positions). Thus we must account for probabilities in our theoretical description in addition to everything that has come so far. Probabilities are implemented in the theory in somewhat different ways, but the statistics come out looking very similar, as we will now see.

In Boltzmannian statistical mechanics, probability distributions are associated with macrostates (with finite-measure macroregions of the microscopic phase space). The initial probability distribution ρ0 (on phase space Γ) of a system in an initial macrostate M0 is stipulated to be uniform with respect to the Liouville measure μ associated with the underlying phase space and to have this uniform support only on the macroregion π− 1M0 (identified with the macrostate M0). Since the probability distributions are defined on phase space (they are maps Γ → [0,1]), the dynamics of these probability distributions (the Liouville dynamics) is fully determined by the deterministic particle dynamics. Thus, the probability distribution at time t, ρt, is given by ρ0ϕt0. In effect, one pushes ρ0 forward from Γ0 to Γt using the dynamical maps for the microstates.

In statistical mechanics, the empirically relevant observables are macroscopic observables, since it is presumed that microstates are epistemically (or at least practically) inaccessible. These should naturally be defined on macrostates, but it is just as well to define them on phase space (since one could easily pull macroscopic observables defined on the macrostates back onto phase space with the projection map π). Thus, we may treat any observable \(\mathcal {O}\) as a map ΓR, just as in classical mechanics, and use it to calculate statistics. For example, the expectation value of \(\mathcal {O}\) at time t for a system that started in an initial macrostate with associated probability distribution ρ0 is given by the following formula:

$$ \langle \mathcal{O} \rangle_{\rho_{t}} = {\int}_{\varGamma} \rho_{t} \mathcal{O} \mathrm{d}\mu. $$
(1)

As one can see, the expectation value essentially sums together the values of the observable \(\mathcal {O}\) in each microstate in Γ, weighted by the probability assigned to that microstate by ρt.

In quantum mechanics, the wave function, while certainly no probability distribution in and of itself, is nevertheless a proxy of sorts for the probabilistic content of the theory. Bohmian mechanics, which privileges the position basis, and, hence, the wave function, does permit the identification of an initial probability distribution in “quantum equilibrium” (Dürr et al. 1992). This means that the initial probability distribution ρ0 (on configuration space) is such that the probability of a particular initial configuration is given by the squared amplitude of the initial wave function: ρ0 = |ψ0|2. In this case the guidance equation consistently gives the dynamics of ρ0, so that one can write the probability distribution at time t as \(\rho _{t} = \rho _{0} \circ \phi _{t0}^{\psi _{0}}\).Footnote 10

Quantum mechanical observables (like position q) are standardly represented as self-adjoint operators \(\mathcal {O}: {\mathcal{H}} \to {\mathcal{H}}\) on the space of quantum states. In Bohmian mechanics, quantum observables are, again, understood to be ultimately reducible to position measurements, so they are not to be interpreted “realistically” (Daumer et al. 1996). Nevertheless, their formal use is unobjectionable to the Bohmian. Still, we may simplify our formalism by preferring the position basis and writing observables as functions of particle configurations: \(\mathcal {O}: \mathcal {Q} \to \mathbf {R}\). The expectation value for an observable \(\mathcal {O}\) in Bohmian mechanics then closely resembles the expectation value in statistical mechanics:

$$ \langle \mathcal{O} \rangle_{\rho_{t}} = {\int}_{Q} \rho_{t} \mathcal{O} \mathrm{d}q. $$
(2)

Thus the analogy which began with the theories’ primitive ontology continues all the way to their empirical content (which takes the form of statistics of observables).

2.4 Deterministic probabilities

It is here, though, that the purported picture of reality wavers somewhat. Trying to assimilate the probabilistic posits of the previous section into theories that aim to maintain a classical ontic picture of deterministic particle mechanics leads to a significant philosophical problem in interpreting these probabilities.Footnote 11 In brief, it is as follows. On the one hand, if the particle configurations determine all observable properties, what can probability represent other than a measure of uncertainty over what the actual configurations are? On the other hand, it cannot be mere uncertainty, since the empirical content of the theories is entirely contained in statistics of observables and, hence, is determined by the probability distribution one uses to describe a system—these probability distributions, in other words, have empirical significance. In statistical mechanics such conflicting concerns have been raised in the context of discussions over the “paradox of deterministic probabilities” (Loewer 2001; Winsberg 2008; Lyon 2011). Bohmian mechanics, given the relevantly shared structure, faces the same concern (Callender 2007).

Many philosophers interested in the question of how to interpret such physical probabilities have been motivated by the “Humean” approach to laws and chances popularized by Lewis (1973, 1981, 1983).Footnote 12 The Humean is skeptical of strong ontological interpretations of laws, chances, and other modal connections which would inflate ontology beyond simple, familiar, actual entities (particles moving around in space and time being a particular favorite). Although Humeans accept that laws, chances, etc. play an important explanatory role in science, they argue that these things objectively reduce to their preferred ontology.

To avoid the potential conflict between the determinism of the dynamical laws and any indeterminism arising from statistical mechanical probabilities, Loewer (2001) chooses to adopt just such a Humean approach in his prominent solution, in which he proposes that probabilities be assigned to possible microscopic initial conditions. That is, there are (Humean) chances for a system (or the whole universe) to begin in the various initial microstates, after which the actual initial microstate’s evolution is deterministic ever after. The Humean, of course, does not believe that there was an actual “chancy” event which brought about the initial state of the system (or universe). A Humean of Loewer’s stripe only claims that the best, objective systematization of the actual, occurrent facts about the world allows one to describe the world theoretically in just this way. Evidently, though, setting such Humean scruples aside, one can give a realist interpretation of these chances as well Demarest (2016).

As it happens, a similar solution to this problem is offered by Dürr et al. (1992) in the context of quantum mechanics, by way of the already mentioned “quantum equilibrium”. Although their preferred story differs in detail,Footnote 13 Loewer’s Humean account might well be applied here too, by supposing that the initial chances for the particles of the system (or universe) to begin in the possible initial configurations are given by |ψ|2, the norm squared of its wave function.Footnote 14

2.5 Reflections

Having seen the analogies between Boltzmannian statistical mechanics and Bohmian quantum mechanics drawn out in detail, let us now reflect on where following the methodological advice with which we began has led us. From common ontological assumptions we were led to a common interpretive challenge and then to similar approaches to resolving it. Indeed, the shared mathematical and physical structure of the two theories makes this seemingly inevitable. As said, the Bohmian-Boltzmannians emphasize the shared structure that comes from common ontological assumptions as the basis of the analogies between the two theories, and they take this “clear” ontological starting point as a point in their favor.Footnote 15 But given the significant philosophical maneuvering required to make sense of the probabilities introduced by statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics, this appears to require taking on quite a lot of “quantum philosophy” with one’s “quantum physics”.

While I find the inherent philosophical tensions in such an approach interesting, what is immediately relevant for my purposes is that a different common assumption has emerged through efforts to avoid the potential conflict with determinism. That assumption was that the source of all objective probabilities is an initial assignment of probabilities to initial configurations or states. What if we take this idea as the source of the analogy instead? Let us suppose that as a first step in the interpretation of a probabilistic physical theory we establish where stochasticity enters into physical reality. Then, by taking what is stochastic about the theory to be the selection of initial conditions, we might realize that this interpretation is precisely one which allows for a microscopic ontology of deterministically evolving classical particles—should one like to “insist that ‘particles’ means particles” (Dürr et al. 1995, 137). I will pursue the idea behind this starting point in the next section by developing three alternative implementations of stochasticity, which will show that the particular way that Boltzmannians and Bohmians interpret their theories is merely one particular choice of how to characterize the probabilistic content of statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics.

3 Stochasticity in physics

In interpreting classical statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics, we should recognize as a first step that these are theories of statistical physics: their predictive empirical content depends essentially on probabilities and is captured in the form of statistics (Wallace 2015). This is in contrast to other physical theories, like particle mechanics, general relativity, and thermodynamics, whose empirical content is not essentially statistical and does not rely essentially on probabilities. This difference tells us that probabilities play an epistemically special role in statistical physics. Philosophically, one would like to understand how to speak about the world such that the empirical content of the theory takes this form.

As this task depends on understanding how probabilities are involved in generating empirical content, much of the distinctive interpretational challenge will concern understanding the nature of probability. This is a notoriously vexed subject in philosophy, and my approach cannot hope to comprehend all the possibilities that have been considered. My strategy is instead to presume a generically ontic interpretation of physical probabilities in this paper.

What I mean by an ontic interpretation of physical probabilities is that the probabilities reflect some element of randomness or chanciness in the world. This presumption makes it easiest to demonstrate the interpretive analogies I see between statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics. It also makes the probabilities of the theories trivially objective, something which can be difficult to obtain on other interpretations.Footnote 16 An ontic interpretation is simple and clear: it straightforwardly presumes that probabilities represent real worldly structure, much like other formal features of physical theories are taken to represent real worldly structure. Of course, one can always raise skeptical challenges to this presumption and alternative interpretations, but indulging in them here would only be a distraction. Nevertheless, I am also not endorsing any particular interpretive position about the nature of probabilities by employing an ontic manner of speaking about probabilities; much less do I commit to any further metaphysical characterization of ontic probabilities in terms of dispositions, propensities, or whatnot.

Given an ontic interpretation of probabilities in statistical physics, I suggest that there are only a few distinct options available for implementing genuine chances in quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics. To see how these three options are suggested, we need to look at how the empirical content of the theories is represented. This is, again, in the form of statistics. The simplest statistical moment, the mean or expectation value, will be sufficient to demonstrate the point.

In classical statistical mechanics, the statistical state of a system is conveniently taken to be represented by a probability distribution ρ :Γ→ [0,1] on phase space Γ. One can construct the corresponding probability measure out of it by making use of the natural Liouville measure dμ associated with the phase space.Footnote 17 The expectation value of an observable \(\mathcal {O}\) when the system is in state ρ is then

$$ \langle\mathcal{O}\rangle_{\rho} = {\int}_{\varGamma} \rho \mathcal{O} \mathrm{d}\mu, $$
(3)

where the integral is over all phase space points xΓ.

For the moment, I enjoin resistance against the familiar interpretation of the points xΓ as microscopic states with ontic significance—especially as configurations of particles with specific momenta. To make this interpretation less inviting, we may confine our attention to a particular observable \(\mathcal {O}:\varGamma \to \mathbf {R}\) and look at the probability space associated with its image set \(\mathcal {O}[\varGamma ]\) (McCoy 2018b): The Lebesgue measurable sets \({\mathcal{L}}\) may be pushed forward onto \(\mathcal {O}[\varGamma ]\) using \(\mathcal {O}\); I denote this collection of subsets as \({\mathcal{L}}_{\mathcal {O}}\). The statistical state ρ can be pushed forward onto \(\mathcal {O}[\varGamma ]\) as well using \(\mathcal {O}\); the probability distribution \(\rho _{\mathcal {O}}\) is therefore \(\mathcal {O}_{*} \rho \). With these three pieces, \(\mathcal {O}[\varGamma ]\), \({\mathcal{L}}_{\mathcal {O}}\), and \(\rho _{\mathcal {O}}\), we have defined a probability space. The Lebesgue measure dω on R is a natural standard of integration which we could use to write an expectation value formula like (3), but for future convenience I will incorporate the probability distribution into a new integration measure \(\mathrm {d}\mathcal {O}_{\rho }\) by defining it as \(\rho _{\mathcal {O}} \mathrm {d}\omega \). In this case one may write the expectation value of any particular observable \(\mathcal {O}\) as

$$ \langle\mathcal{O}\rangle_{\rho_{\mathcal{O}}} = {\int}_{\mathcal{O}[\varGamma]} \omega \mathrm{d}\mathcal{O}_{\rho}, $$
(4)

where \(\omega \in \mathcal {O}[\varGamma ]\) is a particular observable outcome. By this procedure we have quined away the microstates of phase space, with the additional benefit of making the theory’s empirical content manifest solely in terms of observable outcomes (ω) and (proxies for) statistical states (\(\mathrm {d}\mathcal {O}_{\rho }\)).

While this formal redescription may aid in the avoidance of the premature reification of microstates, it more importantly reveals a key formal similarity to expectation values in quantum mechanics. Taking the simple case of projection-valued measures, if we let \(\mathcal {O}\) be a self-adjoint operator on the Hilbert space \({\mathcal{H}}\) and ψ be a particular pure quantum state, then the probability distribution \(\rho _{\mathcal {O}}\) on the set of possible observable outcomes \(\sigma (\mathcal {O})\) (the spectrum of \(\mathcal {O}\)) is determined by the Born rule: \(\rho : \omega \mapsto \langle \psi ,\mathcal {P}_{\omega }\psi \rangle \), the inner product of ψ and the projection operator \(\mathcal {P}_{\omega }\) (that projects onto the eigenspace associated with ω) applied to ψ. Now, let \(\mathrm {d}\mathcal {O}_{\rho }\) be the integration measure incorporating the probability distribution \(\rho _{\mathcal {O}}\). Then the quantum expectation value is expressible essentially just as in (4):

$$ \langle\mathcal{O}\rangle_{\rho_{\mathcal{O}}} = {\int}_{\mathcal{O}[\mathcal{H}]} \omega \mathrm{d}\mathcal{O}_{\rho}. $$
(5)

In formulas like this, orthodox quantum mechanics (Wallace 2016b) transparently supplies us with the empirical content of the theory. Moreover, in orthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics there are, of course, no underlying “microscopic states” (let alone states interpreted in terms of particles). There are just quantum states represented by vectors in Hilbert space. Although presenting statistical mechanics’ empirical content in a similar form, solely in terms of observables and statistical states, is somewhat unorthodox, it does serve to neatly highlight the theories’ shared structure used to represent their empirical content. From this ontologically neutral point, one can then freely ask further questions about unexpressed representational structure, without ontological prejudice.Footnote 18

Time evolution must also be incorporated into the picture we have so far. Let us assume that the states, or rather our proxies for states, the probabilistic integration measure \(\mathrm {d}\mathcal {O}_{\rho }\), evolve in time rather than the operators. I defer saying more about whether the dynamics is deterministic or indeterministic and how it operates for the moment. In any such case, since I assume that the observables do not change over time, any operation of the dynamics can only affect the integration measure. To mark its time-dependence, therefore, I will add a superscripted t to it as a reminder:

$$ \langle\mathcal{O}\rangle_{\rho}^{t} = {\int}_{\mathcal{O}[\cdot]} \omega \mathrm{d}\mathcal{O}_{\rho}^{t}. $$
(6)

Thus, the empirical content of statistical physics, here demonstrated by example in the form of an expectation value, is generated by observables, states, and dynamics (where the latter two have been combined in the integration measure). By merely inspecting how their empirical content is formulated, it is apparent that there are essentially three possible ways to conceive of chances operating in statistical physics—three possible interpretations of stochasticity. These are (1) that initial states are chancy, (2) that the operation of the dynamics is chancy, and (3) that the realization of (observable) properties themselves is chancy.Footnote 19 Let us consider each of these in turn.

First, if one supposes that what is random about a physical system (as described by these two theories) is its initial conditions and nothing else, then it follows that every observable property \(\mathcal {O}\) of the system has a value determined by the outcome of this random trial for all times ever after. Nothing else is left to chance but this initial random trial or chance event, and the chances for each outcome are given by an initial probability distribution ρ0. If follows that the use of statistical states at times other than the initial one (such as expectation values like (6)) must be essentially epistemic in nature: they represent uncertainty over the actual realized outcome of the trial. Importantly, this interpretation mandates characterizing the deterministic evolution of the system after the initial random trial by introducing “hidden variables”. These actual (hidden variable) states can be used to construct a deterministic dynamics for all times (except for the initial time, where the state is indeterminstically fixed by a random trial) and can represent the system’s actual properties via an ontological interpretation (in terms of particles or whatnot).

This interpretation of stochasticity is the one found in the specific interpretations of statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics discussed in the previous section. In Boltzmannian statistical mechanics the hidden variable are classical mechanical states (usually interpreted as particle states), and in Bohmian quantum mechanics they are configurations of local beables (particles or whatnot). The outcome of the initial chance event, then, is a particular initial classical state or configuration of beables. This state evolves deterministically and at every time all observable properties of the system are determined by it. As observers, we assume that we know the initial probabilities associated with the initial states (ρ0) but not the initial microstate. With ρ0, however, we can calculate statistics for the system’s observables since we know how it evolves in time (via the deterministic dynamics). In this way, the “initial chance” story makes sense of all the formalism introduced in the previous section (recognizing, of course, that this story may be modified by fictionalizing or otherwise eschewing the reality of initial chances, as in the Humean chance account).

Second, if one supposes that what is random about a physical system is solely its state transitions (the operation of its dynamics), then there are (at least some) state transitions that are not completely determined by the sequence of preceding states. That is, at least some of the evolution of the probability distribution incorporated into the expectation value formula is not determined. In such interpretations involving dynamical stochasticity, expectation values and the other statistical moments determined by the state are the complete predictable empirical content of the system. Of course, in the wake of state transitions (whether indeterministic or deterministic), a history of observable outcomes is generated by the system’s evolution. However, as this generated history is to some extent subject to randomness, one cannot expect exact agreement between the generated histories of observable outcomes and the expectations generated by the statistical predictions (although one does of course expect statistical agreement).

There are many ways indeterministic evolution could be implemented with stochastic dynamics.Footnote 20 Accordingly, there are several examples of this kind of interpretation of stochasticity in quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics. Although the details of how stochastic mechanisms are incorporated into dynamics vary between quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics (and even within the theories), it is not worth examining them in all their details here; my aim is simply to capture what they have in common and mention a few examples for illustration.

In quantum mechanics, approaches with indeterministic dynamics are generically called collapse theories (Ghirardi 2016). The traditional Copenhagen interpretation invokes wave function collapses during measurement; insofar as it is an interpretation of quantum mechanics, it is a collapse theory. The reader may well be acquainted with more rigorous collapse theories. For example, in the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber (GRW) approach, quantum states evolve according to the Schrödinger equation most of the time, but the state of the system occasionally experiences indeterministic “collapses” to different quantum states. Other versions allow for continuously indeterministic evolution (e.g., Pearle’s continuous spontaneous localization).Footnote 21

It is worth noting that in all familiar cases the collapse dynamics is implemented solely on the level of the quantum state. Nevertheless, the stochastic dynamics account can be supplied with “hidden variables” which can then be characterized ontically, just as in the initial chance approach. The dynamics of the statistical states in this case will be given in terms of the microscopic dynamics, and the observable properties of the system can be determined by the hidden variables. This is actually the usual way that stochastic dynamics is implemented in classical statistical mechanics (Wallace 2014; Luczak 2016).Footnote 22 Indeed, many of the most well-known equations from non-equilibrium statistical mechanics implement the dynamics directly on microstates, such as the Langevin equation; others, like the Fokker-Planck equation, implement a dynamics on the level of the statistical state (but are generally constructed out of a microscopic dynamics). One is not, however, forced to posit classical microstructure in non-equilibrium statistical mechanics; one could, that is, follow the example of quantum mechanics and take, say, the Fokker-Planck equation at face value as a dynamics of statistical states.

Third, and finally, if one supposes that what is random about a physical system is solely its observable properties, then it follows that state transitions must be deterministic. That is, while the evolution of the statistical state ρ is deterministic, the realization of actual properties of the system is stochastic. This is contrast to the previous case, where the evolution of the statistical state is stochastic, and the realization of actual properties is fully determined by the state. In both cases, however, it is because of the physical indeterminism present in the system that statistical moments determined by the state are the complete predictable empirical content of the system. Again, a history of observable outcomes is generated by the physical stochastic process, but this may not be a perfect match with the expectations generated by statistical predictions based on the statistical state.

Before saying more about this interpretation of stochasticity, it is useful to contrast the second and third interpretations with classical mechanics. In classical mechanics, the state dynamics is deterministic and states are individuated by the properties of the system. That is, the states determine the observable properties. Thus there is a “double determinism” in classical mechanics. The indeterminism of a probabilistic physical theory like classical statistical mechanics or quantum mechanics (on an ontic interpretation) means that (at least) one of these two roles of state must become indeterministic. In the stochastic dynamics interpretation, the state dynamics is indeterministic, while the observable outcomes remain fully determined by the state. In other words, observables are not random variables, states are. In the stochastic observables interpretation, the state dynamics is deterministic, but the observable outcomes are random. In other words, observables are true random variables, states are not.

This third interpretive possibility has seldom been acknowledged in the literature, although there has been some recent discussion (McCoy 2018b; Frigg and Werndl 2018) in the context of classical statistical mechanics. There are several older approaches that appear to conform roughly to the basic idea of deterministic state dynamics with stochastic observables, such as those programs that Uffink (2007) calls “statistical thermodynamics”; also, some aspects of Prigogine’s or Khinchin’s approach agree with the interpretive philosophy given here, especially in their rejection of classical microstates.Footnote 23Frigg and Werndl (2018) also suggest several ways in which Gibbs’ approach to equilibrium statistical mechanics might be interpreted, one of which (that they call “bare probabilism’) is perhaps naturally characterized as a stochastic observables interpretation.Footnote 24

It is less obvious which interpretations of quantum mechanics are compatible with this way of conceiving of probabilities. There is at least one popular candidate which might be thought of as having stochastic observables, that is, were its quantum probabilities understood as chances. This is the many worlds interpretation (or, perhaps better, the more general “orthodox quantum mechanics” discussed by Wallace 2016b). I say this because many worlds quantum mechanics eschews a primitive ontology of deterministically evolving particles, and it maintains a deterministic state dynamics at all times. In this way it is similar to the bare probabilism of Frigg and Werndl (although one must acknowledge the fact that quantum probability is a far more subtle matter to handle than classical probability). That said, most proponents of the many worlds interpretation do not attempt to give an ontic interpretation to quantum probabilities at all, instead favoring, for example, a “functional” interpretation (Saunders 2010; Wallace 2012) or an “epistemic” interpretation (Sebens and Carroll 2016). What probabilities in many worlds quantum mechanics are has, indeed, been a matter of much debate (Greaves 2007), and it would be too much of a diversion to enter into the debate here, much less propose a novel interpretation of quantum probabilities along these lines. So I do not mean to push the case that many worlds quantum mechanic is in the general category of stochastic observables very far here. In any case, other ideas, for example, an “ensemble” interpretation of quantum mechanics (Ballentine 1970) or, perhaps, the consistent histories approach (Griffiths 2019), might also be seen as falling under the stochastic observables interpretation when supplied with an ontic interpretation of probability, especially insofar as they share relevant features of the approaches to statistical mechanics mentioned in the previous paragraph.

These, then, are three ways of conceiving of the stochasticity of statistical physics. They are most easily seen by assuming an ontic interpretation of probability, which is why I chose to do so, but their usefulness as categories can be extended to other interpretations of such theories which identify probabilities as merely epistemic. Furthermore, the different starting point of this section, compared to the previous one, is noteworthy, as it should now be clear that strong assumptions about the primitive ontology of the theories can easily obscure significant alternative possibilities. It is for this reason that I began by looking at the statistics which account for the empirical content of such theories. These can be cast in a suggestive form by making use of the common dynamical structures of statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics. As we observed, stochasticity can be associated, on the face of it, with one of three different components. These three components were the initial conditions, the dynamics, and the observables of a physical system.

A choice of one of these then suggested a particular interpretation (or class of interpretations) of statistical mechanics and of quantum mechanics. The first leads to, for example, Boltzmannian statistical mechanics and Bohmian quantum mechanics, the analogy between which was described in the previous section. Whereas there I began as the Boltzmannian/Bohmians prefer, with the common ontological posit of particles moving in space and time, I argued in this section that it is also possible to view the analogy between the two theories as coming from the choice of an interpretation of stochasticity. The second choice of where to locate stochasticity leads to another clear analogy, namely between the variety of approaches termed stochastic dynamics in statistical mechanics and the variety of collapse theories in quantum mechanics. The third choice leads to what I have been calling the stochastic observables interpretation. Although the link of this interpretation with well-established approaches in statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics is less developed, I believe that Gibbsian statistical mechanics and orthodox quantum mechanics serve ably as suggestive, albeit under-developed, examples. Serious interpretive work is required for this suggestion to be realized and adequately justified however.

4 Primitive ontology

The framework for connecting interpretations of quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics with one another which I developed in the previous section makes it possible to see how interpretive problems and solutions can be portable from one theory to the other. In this section and the next, I give two explicit examples where this may be done. In this section I export the present debate concerning “primitive ontology” in quantum mechanics (Belot 2011; Ney and Phillips 2013; Allori et al. 2014; Esfeld 2014) to classical statistical mechanics. A detailed discussion of this debate and its importation into statistical mechanics would be a topic in its own right; my aim is not to survey the entirety of this debate or press for one view or another. It is to show how substantially the same issue concerning primitive ontology arises in statistical mechanics, once one recognizes that similar kinds of interpretation are available there as in quantum mechanics—due to the interpretational analogies I have developed.

To this end I focus only on two specific problems related to primitive ontology raised by Belot (2011): what he calls the “macro object problem” and what I will call the “extra ontology problem”. An interpretation of quantum mechanics that specifies properties possessed by regions of spacetime has come to be called a primitive ontology. The version of Bohmian mechanics described above, according to which the material ontology of a quantum system consists in particles (Esfeld et al. 2014), has a primitive ontology, as do collapse interpretations (Maudlin 2007a) that include an ontology of “flashes” (Esfeld and Gisin 2014) or “matter densities” (Egg and Esfeld 2015). If one supposes that quantum physics provides a fundamental description of reality, then, according to proponents of a primitive ontology, it should describe a world of stuff and things moving around in space and time. Interpretations of quantum mechanics that suppose that the basic quantum description of the world is in terms of the quantum state (perhaps out of which macroscopic reality emerges) lack a primitive ontology. Among these views are wave function realism (Albert 2013; North 2013) and spacetime state realism (Wallace and Timpson 2010).

That there has been no such analogous discussion in statistical mechanics is presumably owed to the issue being regarded as long settled. Insofar as one demands a realist interpretation of statistical mechanics, its ontology is thought to consist of one class of entity: classical entities like particles (which evolve deterministically). I have argued, however, that the different interpretations of stochasticity imply that there are interpretations of statistical mechanics analogous to the interpretations of quantum mechanics, ones which indeed may not reduce to this specific ontology. One can therefore ask what the ontology of these former interpretations is, as well as how the ontologies of the two theories, statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics, relate.

Now to the two problems mentioned above. First, Belot’s “macro object problem” poses the challenge of explaining how quantum mechanics provides truth conditions for the assignment of properties to ordinary macroscopic objects. If macroscopic objects are simply composed of microscopic objects and their properties are entirely reducible to the properties of the latter, then interpretations which adopt a primitive ontology, like Bohmian mechanics, would seem to have an important advantage in solving the macro object problem. The specification of microscopic properties in spacetime, after all, is (in the best case) just one relation away from specifying macroscopic properties in spacetime. Interpretations of quantum mechanics without a primitive ontology, by contrast, must furnish an evidently more complicated story for how macroscopic objects possess the properties that they appear to possess.

Let us try to pose a macro object problem in classical statistical mechanics. How does this theory provide truth conditions for the assignment of properties to ordinary macroscopic objects? The usual answer is that macroscopic objects (boxes of gas) are simply composed of microscopic classical mechanical objects (molecules of gas, say) and their properties are entirely reducible to the latter. To give this answer, however, one must supplement the statistical state with an actual microstate. Just as collapse interpretations and Bohmian mechanics possess a primitive ontology in quantum mechanics which can address the macro object problem, so too, it seems, can stochastic dynamics and Boltzmannian approaches be described as having a primitive ontology, one which makes a significant start towards addressing the macro object problem in this context. Evidently, other interpretations of statistical mechanics without a primitive ontology will have to furnish a more complicated story in order to address the problem. That is not to say, of course, that some such story cannot be given, just as it is not to say so in quantum mechanics.

Second, Belot challenges primitive ontologists in quantum mechanics to make sense (ontologically speaking) of the quantum state. He claims that their interpretations are dualistic insofar as their ontologies apparently have two kinds of entity: the primitive ontology of particles (or what have you) and the quantum state (or wave function). Interpretations of quantum mechanics without a primitive ontology do not have this dualism; therefore, they might seem to have an important advantage over those interpretations which adopt a primitive ontology in addressing this challenge, the extra ontology problem.

This problem can also be (and in a way has been) raised in classical statistical mechanics. Recall that the empirical content of the theories I have been discussing, formally and epistemically-speaking, requires only a set of observables, a physical state in the form of a probability measure, and a dynamics for that state. In quantum mechanics this state is the quantum state and in statistical mechanics it is the statistical state. Whether one opts for a primitive ontology or not, interpreters of statistical mechanics should be able to answer the same challenge: how can one make sense of the statistical state? Indeed, I already showed how one is led directly to this problem in the Boltzmannian and Bohmian interpretations by assuming a primitive ontology from the start. This problem is intimately related to the previously mentioned paradox of deterministic probabilities (Loewer 2001; Winsberg 2008; Lyon 2011)

Let us now proceed a bit further and examine briefly how one might go about solving the extra ontology problem for the evidently dualistic default interpretation of statistical mechanics, the Boltzmannian interpretation. I will simply follow Belot’s approach here. Belot says that there are a few possibilities for interpreting the wave function: it is a field (of sorts), a law (of sorts), or a property (of sorts). Let us suppose that a statistical state in statistical mechanics could be interpretable in the same ways and look at them in turn.

If one thinks of the probability distribution ρ as a field, then it must be a field defined on some abstract space (e.g., phase space), making a connection to three-dimensional reality difficult. This is also a problem raised against the wave function in quantum mechanics. However, it seems to be even more of a problem in statistical mechanics, since—on the Boltzmannian primitive ontology picture—it is clear that ρ plays no role in the dynamics of the physical particles, unlike in Bohmian mechanics where it “guides” the particles.

If one thinks of the statistical state as instead encoding nomological facts, in analogy to interpretations that take the wave function to do so (Callender 2015), then in the first place it is not so clear what nomological facts it is encoding. In the second, the main complaint against conceiving of the wave function as a nomological entity in quantum mechanics also carries over directly to classical statistical mechanics. That complaint is that wave functions are contingent, since the theory allows that there could be different initial wave functions and since wave functions also evolve in time. This is unlike legitimate laws which hold with physical necessity, such as Hamilton’s equation or the Schrödinger equation (Brown and Wallace 2005; Belot 2011). As initial statistical states are plainly contingent in the same way and for the same reasons, it does not seem that they can be nomological in nature.

Finally, if one thinks of the statistical state as encoding dispositional properties of a primitive ontology, then one cannot believe this in the Boltzmannian interpretation, for in this case the microscopic physics is deterministic and not dispositional. This is an important difference in comparison to Bohmian quantum mechanics, where the relevant dispositional properties are said to be the velocities of the particles (the wave function is responsible for determining them via the guidance equation). In Boltzmannian statistical mechanics, however, the particles already possess determined velocities by the microscopic dynamics.

Therefore, in all three cases it seems that the extra ontology problem poses a significant problem for the conventional interpretation of statistical mechanics, and this point has not been sufficiently appreciated in the literature. Is it problematic enough to consider alternative interpretations than those that presuppose a primitive ontology?

I happen to believe so. Even if not and these problems can be resolved, it would seem worth at least exploring the interpretive options available. Why not ask, for example, which interpretations are committed to a primitive ontology and which are not? Recall the discussion from the previous section: If one opts for the initial chances approach, then one can (and arguably must) posit a primitive ontology with deterministic dynamics. This is the paradigmatic case which leads to difficulties with the extra ontology problem, as we just saw. If one opts instead for the stochastic dynamics approach, then one can also posit a primitive ontology (although one need not). Unlike the initial chances approach, though, observe that it is possible to characterize the statistical state as encoding dispositional properties, since the microdynamics would not be always deterministic. Perhaps this should be seen as an advantage of this approach. Finally, if one opts for the stochastic observables approach, then one can directly characterize the statistical state as encoding dispositional properties of the macroscopic ontology. It therefore does not face the extra ontology problem (although clearly it does face the challenge of the macro object problem, as does the stochastic dynamics approach without a primitive ontology).

Obviously, there is much more that can and should be said about this cluster of issues. Here is not the place for a lengthy investigation, for my aim has merely been to show the applicability of this typology of interpretations and the analogies between them for linking an important interpretive issue across theories. And so it does: it helpfully reveals how primitive ontology, probability, and determinism become entangled not only in quantum mechanics but in statistical mechanics as well.

5 The measurement problem

The second interpretive issue that I wish to consider is the quantum mechanical measurement problem. Just as I claimed that the macro object and extra ontology problems can be posed in statistical mechanics, I claim that a kind of “measurement problem” can be seen to arise in statistical mechanics. I will suggest a reading of the measurement problem in quantum mechanics according to which it is a problem about how to interpret the stochasticity of the theory—in which case it should be no surprise that there is an analogous problem in statistical mechanics, for statistical mechanics is a theory which requires an interpretation of stochasticity as well. By suggesting this reading, however, I certainly do not mean to claim that there is nothing more to the quantum measurement problem than a problem of interpreting probabilities in the theory.Footnote 25 Rather, it seems to me that bringing this aspect of the problem to light allows one to be clearer about what distinctively quantum aspects of the problem are actually at issue in quantum mechanics.

Although there are more sophisticated ways one could make the point, I will make use of the simple, well-known presentation of the measurement problem found in Maudlin (1995), specifically what Maudlin calls the “problem of outcomes.” He argues that the following three seemingly plausible statements are inconsistent in quantum mechanics:

  1. 1.

    The quantum state of a system is complete; that is, it is sufficient for specifying all of the physical properties of a system.

  2. 2.

    The quantum state always evolves in accord with a deterministic equation, namely the Schrödinger equation.

  3. 3.

    Measurements of observable properties have determinate outcomes; that is, measurements reveal that the system possesses definite properties.

The argument for the inconsistency of these claims is familiar. A generic quantum state is a superposition. Assuming 1 and 2, it follows that a system in a superposition will not in general have determinate outcomes. Assuming 1 and 3, it follows that the system in a superposition cannot have evolved deterministically for it to have determinate properties. Assuming 2 and 3, it follows that the system’s state must be supplemented, for something must specify which outcomes obtain in a superposition. According to Maudlin, rejecting 1 leads one to Bohmian mechanics; rejecting 2 leads one to collapse interpretations; rejecting 3 leads one to the many worlds interpretation.

We can contrive a very similar argument in the context of statistical mechanics. I claim that the following three statements are inconsistent:

  1. 1.

    The statistical state of a system is complete; that is, it is sufficient for specifying all of the physical properties of a system.

  2. 2.

    The statistical state always evolves in accord with a deterministic equation, for example the Liouville equation.

  3. 3.

    Measurements of observable properties have determinate outcomes; that is, measurements reveal that the system possesses definite properties.

A generic statistical state is essentially a classical superposition. Assuming 1 and 2, it follows that a system in such a state cannot have determinate outcomes, for a system in such a superposition does not have determinate properties. Assuming 1 and 3, it follows that the system cannot have evolved deterministically for it to have determinate outcomes. Assuming 2 and 3, it follows that the system’s state must be supplemented by something that specifies the outcomes that actually obtain in the superposition. According to the typology of interpretations of this paper, and in analogy to the quantum mechanical argument, rejecting 1 will lead to some kind of initial chance account, rejecting 2 will lead to some kind of stochastic dynamics account; rejecting 3 will lead to some kind of stochastic observables account.

Presented this way, the manifest issue behind these two measurement problems is how one interprets the stochasticity of a theory of statistical physics. Although there is no doubt that quantum mechanics brings with it distinctive interpretive issues, Maudlin’s “problem of outcomes” does not appear to be one of them, for the states of statistical mechanics suffer from the same indeterminateness as quantum states, and the possible solutions to the two problems follow essentially the same lines.

Now, I suppose that some will be little impressed with the revelation of these analogous measurement problems. They will say that this “analogy” is trivial and was already obvious (although one looks in vain for someone making it explicit!) and so too the solution. The very success of statistical mechanics, they might say, demonstrates that the systems it treats are composed of microscopic entities and, indeed, bears out the “atomic hypothesis”. There is no question, then, that one should reject the first statement, since systems certainly do possess microscopic states and properties, namely those of atoms and molecules, which can be described in classical mechanics. Unfortunately this popular story is far too sanguine, and in several respects. One is that there are various alternative interpretations available that deserve a fair evaluation and may on balance be preferable to the old story. Two, even if there was no reason to question the ontological presuppositions of classical statistical mechanics in the distant past, surely the acceptance of quantum mechanics as our best microscopic physics should lead us to reconsider what the microscopic entities of classical statistical mechanics really are. It is by no means sure that they are best understood as classical entities. Three, exploring alternative interpretations may suggest novel approaches, techniques, and hypotheses in classical statistical mechanics that would be entirely overlooked by presupposing a resolution to this classical measurement problem.

Finally, it may be of some interest to consider as well how these parallel measurement problems may be solved together, at one stroke, as it were. Although it is possible that one might favor differing solutions for the two theories, it does seem natural to prefer common solutions to both problems, for philosophical reasons or otherwise. Indeed, the Boltzmann-Bohmians see it as an advantage of their position that they have a common primitive ontology in their favored interpretations; it might be seen as an additional virtue that they solve the measurement problems in a consistent way. If it is good wisdom to pursue parallel solutions, then the collapse theorist might look to stochastic dynamics approaches in statistical mechanics, and perhaps doing so might give a useful perspective on the quantum to classical limit.Footnote 26 The same may hold as well for the stochastic observables approaches, perhaps by developing links between Gibbsian statistical mechanics and some kind of Everettian interpretation.Footnote 27

6 Conclusion

I have drawn attention to analogies between interpretations of classical statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics centered on an important issue, which I suggest is at the heart of these analogies: the interpretation of stochasticity in the two theories. Rather than discuss probability in all its many traditional interpretations, I focused on realist, ontic interpretations of probability, where probabilities are understood to be related to some kind of fundamental randomness in the world. With this interpretive stance, answering the question of what probability does in statistical theories comes down to locating a source of stochasticity in the theory. I cast statistical mechanics and quantum mechanics in a common abstract form, starting from the epistemically significant empirical content of the theories, the statistics of observables. Stochasticity, I argued, could be associated with three aspects of the theories: its initial conditions, its dynamics, or its observable properties. As it turns out, the usual “realist” interpretations of the two theories can be seen to line up closely with these choices. The most well-known analogy, that between Boltzmannian statistical mechanics and Bohmian quantum mechanics, takes the first option; stochastic dynamics approaches in statistical mechanics and collapse interpretations in quantum mechanics take the second; the third option is unusual in that it has been for the most part overlooked in interpretational work, although I suggested that Gibbsian statistical mechanics and many worlds quantum mechanics might be understood to take this option, were one to give their probabilities some sort of ontic interpretation.

To show that this way of thinking about the two theories is fertile, I discussed its consequences for two major interpretive issues in quantum mechanics: primitive ontology and the measurement problem. I argued that debates about these issues could be reprised in the context of statistical mechanics. Moving the debate about primitive ontology into statistical mechanics puts to question, for example, the nature of a statistical state: is it an object, a law, a property? I also argued that at least one popular rendering of the quantum measurement problem translates directly into statistical mechanics, which I took to reveal that to some extent what is called the quantum measurement problem involves a problem of making sense of its probabilities. I showed that analogous interpretations of the two theories solve the two measurement problem in much the same way, which draws further attention to the generally overlooked intertheoretical relation between quantum mechanics and statistical mechanics (instead of that between quantum mechanics and classical mechanics).