Skip to main content
Log in

The Phenomenal Quality of Complex Experiences

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper makes and defends four interrelated claims. First: most conscious experiences are complex in the sense that they have discernible constituent structure with discernible parts that can feature as parts of other experiences, and might occur as standalone experiences. Second: complex experiences have simple constituents that have no further discernible parts. Third: the phenomenal quality of having a complex experience is jointly determined by the phenomenal quality of its simple constituents plus the phenomenal structure simple constituents are organised into. And fourth: physical descriptions can convey all the relevant information about the discernible phenomenal structure of conscious experiences. The combination of these four claims tells us that there is no further explanatory gap related to the phenomenal quality of complex experiences given that one is familiar with the phenomenal qualities of the simple parts constituting the complex experience in question, and that it is possible to acquire knowledge about the phenomenal quality of yet unexperienced complex experiences on the basis of previous acquaintances with constituent parts plus structural information. That is, the paper argues for a ‘summation’ model of phenomenal qualities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This paper focuses on the unity of consciousness from the perspective that there is something it is like (Nagel 1974) for a subject to have a total experience that has different aspects or constituent parts.

  2. Bayne and Chalmers (2003) and Bayne (2008, 2010) are often interpreted as arguing for conjoint phenomenology, i.e. the claim that the phenomenal quality of a unified experience consists in more than the sum of the phenomenal qualities of the experiences that are unified. See e.g. Macpherson (2011) and also Tye (2003).

  3. It is an intricate and much debated issue whether components of experiences can themselves be thought of as experiences on their own right (see e.g. Tye 2003). In this paper I use terms like ‘component experience’ in an innocent way that tries to stay neutral with regard to this issue—see Fn. 10 for more clarification.

  4. Recently, Fiona Macpherson has provided reasons for favouring such a model in the multi-modal case (Macpherson 2011, pp. 454–462).

  5. For example, such a holistic view with respect to complex experiences (claiming that the complexity of an experience cannot be reduced to its elements) is often attributed to Gestalt approaches to perception (see e.g. Wertheimer 1958). See §3.1 and §3.3 for a detailed discussion of Gestalt effects.

  6. Though see Held et al. (2011) showing that the newly sighted fail to match seen with felt.

  7. The relevant concepts in question, of course, are phenomenal concepts, not ordinary language colour concepts (see Loar 1990, Papineau 2002, Fazekas and Jakab 2016).

  8. See §2.5 for a detailed discussion of why this is so.

  9. On how ‘parts’ of an experience might best be conceived of, see, for example, Lee (2014).

  10. See, for example, Prinz (2002) for a detailed discussion of the perceptual basis of concepts.

  11. Hue, saturation and brightness are discernible properties of unique hue experiences, but they themselves have no further discernible parts and they cannot occur as stand-alone experiences (one cannot have an experience of saturation without also experiencing some hue and lightness values as well; see Fazekas and Jakab 2016). They might be combined in novel ways in imagination, resulting in novel experiences like previously never seen darker or lighter varieties of a certain hue.

  12. Or their vibrations (see Turin 2006).

  13. See Jakab (2003, 2006) who argues that shape experiences are revelatory in a sense in which colour experiences are not.

  14. This moral applies mainly to visual and to a lesser degree also to haptic and auditory cases, where spatial relationships structure the experiences. In auditory experiences, spatial structure is very limited (e.g. being heard from somewhere close on the left or from far behind), and in olfaction even more so. In taste perception, the kind of physical structure that occurs in phenomenal descriptions (e.g. experiencing a certain taste on the back of the tongue) is detached from the physical structure of the objects of taste perception and is more related to the physical positions of the relevant receptors—and thus it is not revelatory in the sense discussed in the main text.

  15. See e.g. Chalmers (1996), and Fazekas and Jakab (2016).

  16. This claim about the complexity and structure of certain experiences is compatible with such structure being dynamic (Metzinger 1995).

  17. See Dainton (2000, 2008) for more examples of simple (unstructured) stand-alone experiences.

  18. Other examples, involving only basic shapes, might be the illusion or the Poggendorff illusion (Zöllner 1860).

  19. In the case of the Hermann-grid, see Baumgartner (1960) and Schiller and Carvey (2005) for explaining the mechanisms underlying the perceived illusion.

  20. See how the notion of ‘physical description’ is utilised in the literature on phenomenal concepts (e.g. Papineau 2002, 2007, Loar 1990, Balog 2009, 2012,  Fazekas and Jakab 2016). Accounting for ‘physical structure’, thus, does not give rise to any kind of epistemic—e.g. explanatory—gap (Chalmers 2003, 1996).

References

  • Aydede, M., and G. Güzeldere. 2005. Cognitive Architecture, Concepts, and Introspection: An Information-Theoretic Solution to the Problem of Phenomenal Consciousness. Nous 39: 197–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. 2009. Phenomenal Concepts. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, ed. B.P. Mclaughlin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. 2012. In Defense of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84: 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, G. 1960. Indirekte Größenbestimmung der rezeptiven Felder der Retina beim Menschen mittels der Hermannschen Gittertäuschung. Pflügers Archiv Für Die Gesamte Physiologie 272: 21–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. 2008. The Unity of Consciousness and the Split-Brain Syndrome. The Journal of Philosophy 105: 277–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. 2010. The Unity of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., and D. Chalmers. 2003. What is the unity of consciousness. In The unity of consciousness: Binding, integration, and dissociation, ed. A. Cleeremans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boynton, R. 1997. Insights gained from naming the OSA colours. In Colour categories in thought and language, ed. C. Hardin and L. Maffi. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 2003. Consciousness and its place in nature. In Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind, ed. S. Stich and T. Warfield. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. 2000. Stream of Consciousness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. 2008. The Phenomenal Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D.C. 1991. Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fazekas, P., and G. Zemplen. 2005. Molyneux’s Questions: from the Philosophical Problem of Representation to Cross-Modal Transfer (in Hungarian). Hungarian Psychological Review 60: 527–552.

  • Fazekas, P.., and Z.. Jakab. 2016. The sensory basis of the epistemic gap: an alternative to phenomenal concepts. Philosophical Studies 173 (8): 2105–2124. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0599-6.

  • Hardin, C. 1988. Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, R., Ostrovsky, Y., Degelder, B., Gandhi, T., Ganesh, S., Mathur, U. and Sinha, P. 2011: The newly sighted fail to match seen with felt. Nature Neuroscience, published online 10 April 2011.

  • Hermann, L. 1870. Eine Erscheinung simultanen Contrastes. Pflügers Archiv Für Die Gesamte Physiologie 3: 13–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1982. Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1986. What Mary Didn’t Know. The Journal of Philosophy 83: 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jakab, Z. 2003. Phenomenal Projection. Psyche 9: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakab, Z. 2006. Revelation and Normativity in Visual Experience. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 25–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1890/1983: The Principles of Psychology. Boston: Harvard University Press.

  • James, W. 1892. Psychology. New York: Universit of Notre Dame Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. 2008. Content and Constancy: Phenomenology, Psychology, and the Content of Perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76: 682–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. 2004. Isomorphism in Information Carrying Systems. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85: 380–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. 2005. Perceptual Content, Information, and the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction. Philosophical Studies 122: 103–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, G. 2014. Experiences and their Parts. In Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness, ed. D. Bennett and C. Hill, 287–322. Boston: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. 1983. Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 354–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. 1993. On leaving out what it’s like. In Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays, ed. M. Davies and G. Humphreys. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. 1990. Phenomenal States. In Philosophical Perspectives, ed. J. Tomberlin. Northridge: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1690/1987: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lycan, W. 2008: Representational Theories of Consciousness. In Zalta, E. N. (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition).

  • Macpherson, F. 2011. Cross-Modal Experiences. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111: 429–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M.G.F. 2002. The Transparency of Experience. Mind & Language 17: 376–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, W. 1930. Optische Untersuchungen am Ganzfeld. Psychologische Forschung 13: 6–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. 1995. Faster than Thought: Holism, Homogeneity and Temporal Coding. In Conscious Experience, ed. T. Metzinger. Imprint Academic: Thorverton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T., and B. Walde. 2000. Commentary on Jakab’s “Ineffability of Qualia.” Consciousness and Cognition 9: 352–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 4: 81–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. 2010. Attention and perceptual content. Analysis 70: 263–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. 2011. Ambiguous figures, attention and perceptual content. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10: 557–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. 2012. The philosophical implications of the Perky experiments. Analysis 72: 439–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noordhof, P. 2002. Imagining Objects and Imagining Experiences. Mind & Language 17: 426–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. 2002. Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. 2007. Phenomenal and Perceptual Concepts. In Phenomenal Knowledge and Phenomenal Concepts, ed. T. Alter and S. Walter. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perky, C.W. 1910. An Experimental Study of Imagination. American Journal of Psychology 21: 422–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2002. Furnishing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, P.H., and C.E. Carvey. 2005. The Hermann grid illusion revisited. Perception 34: 1375–1397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, S.J. 1972. Assimilation of a stimulus in the construction of an image: the Perky effect revisited. In The Function and Nature of Imagery, ed. P. Sheehan. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. 2010. Attention and Intentionalism. Philosophical Quarterly 60: 325–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stazicker, J. 2011. Attention, Visual Consciousness and Indeterminacy. Mind & Language 26: 156–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 2000. Comparative Color Vision: Quality Space and Visual Ecology. In Color Perception: Philosophical, Psychological, Artistic and Computational Perspectives, ed. S. Davis. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turin, L. 2006. The Secret of Scent: Adventures in Perfume and the Science of Smell. London: Ecco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 2003. Consciousness and Persons: Unity and Identity. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. 1958. Principles of perceptual organization. In Readings in perception, ed. D.C. Beardslee and M. Wertheimer. Princeton: Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeshurun, Y., and M. Carrasco. 1998. Attention improves or impairs visual performance by enhancing spatial resolution. Nature 396: 72–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zöllner, F. 1860. Ueber eine neue Art von Pseudoskopie und ihre Beziehungen zu den von Plateau und Oppel beschrieben Bewegungsphaenomenen. Annalen Der Physik 186: 500–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Bence Nanay, Jacob Berger, Andy Clark, Jesper Kallestrup, Mark Sprevak and Jonas Christensen for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Funding

Supported by the Research Foundation – Flanders (FWO 12B3918N) and an AIAS Fellowship by the EU’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement No 754513 and The Aarhus University Research Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Fazekas.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest/Competing interests

None.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fazekas, P. The Phenomenal Quality of Complex Experiences. Rev.Phil.Psych. (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-023-00676-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-023-00676-y

Navigation