Skip to main content
Log in

Working memory is not a natural kind and cannot explain central cognition

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Working memory is a foundational construct of cognitive psychology, where it is thought to be a capacity that enables us to keep information in mind and to use that information to support goal directed behavior. Philosophers have recently employed working memory to explain central cognitive processes, from consciousness to reasoning. In this paper, I show that working memory cannot meet even a minimal account of natural kindhood, as the functions of maintenance and manipulation of information that tie working memory models and theories together do not have a coherent or univocal realizer in the brain. As such, working memory cannot explain central cognition. Rather, I argue that working memory merely redescribes its target phenomenon, and in doing so it obfuscates relevant distinctions amongst the many ways that brains like ours retain and transform information in the service of cognition. While this project ultimately erodes the explanatory role that working memory has played in our understanding of cognition, it simultaneously prompts us to evaluate the function of natural kinds within cognitive science, and signals the need for a productive pessimism to frame our future study of cognitive categories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As a cursory gloss, both of these projects aim to identify fundamental properties characteristic of thought, where Fodor’s isotropy describes the possibility that the content of any one thought might be relevant to any other, and Evan’s constraint details how any number of properties might be predicated to any object of thought. As Carruthers (2014) makes explicit, the possible multiplicity of relations that thoughts and their properties can bear to one other can be captured by the structure of a multimodal mental workspace, which he identifies as working memory (144). Thanks to a reviewer for prompting this clarification.

  2. This is, of course, only a subset of positions in the philosophical literature that plausibly rely on features predicated of working memory. As an anonymous reviewer has pointed out, scholars who use the notion of a “specious presence” or a “circuit of consciousness” may be reliant on something that more closely resembles the modern psychological formulation of working memory (e.g., Ladd 1887; James 1890; Husserl 1964; Bergson 1990), and, reviewing this correspondence is merited in future work. However, by focusing on the authors above, we can showcase the breath of possible theories that make use of a unified, domain-general mental workspace that enables flexible thought. Finally, while it seems odd to suggest that Aristotle employs something like working memory in his description of the phantasia, the connection and striking parallels between the two concepts merits considered exploration, as both are said to retain perceptual information, are crucial to the process of long-term memory formation, and integral to every instance of deliberative thought.

  3. Cf. Carruthers’ (chp. 8, 2015) excellent review of avian proception, and Godfrey-Smith’s compelling account of cephalopod intelligence (2016).

  4. Although whether a robust homeostasis, such as an equilibrium, is a necessary feature of HPC natural kinds has been debated (cf. Craver 2009).

  5. Both surveys naturally tend to favor Cowan’s own “generic” or “long-term working memory” view.

  6. Here, I am following in the rhetorical footsteps of Michaelian (2011) who arguably had a more difficult task in charitably characterizing most other types of memory using the template of the multiple memory systems hypothesis.

  7. At the urging of a reviewer, though at the risk of preempting the conclusions reached in section 4.4, I’d like to make clear that the explanatory flaws to be identified are the functional decomposition of working memory into the maintenance and manipulation of information, alongside its wide purview over most cognitive activity.

  8. Rather, Cherniak is largely pulling from textbook and reference sources, including Klatzky (1975).

  9. Specifically, during the delay period common to working memory task paradigms. In most working memory tasks, a target is presented to be maintained or manipulated, followed by a delay period in which the target disappears, and during which time distractors may be introduced. Afterwards, an additional target or response probe is introduced.

  10. I’d like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to expand on this point.

  11. Here, the monkeys were shown a piece of fruit that was placed in one of three locations, they had to retain that information while a screen was lowered, and only after a delay were they tasked with indicating the location of the fruit (Kubota and Niki 1971, 338).

  12. As a caveat, these are very rudimentary tasks, often only requiring the maintenance of three or four stimuli, and other deficits, particularly in monitoring the task, were correlated with prefrontal damage; however, the tasks are identical to those that established the prefrontal dogma of maintenance-c.

  13. The jadeite/nephrite example is a classic case of the same phenomenon in action (Hacking 2007).

  14. Recall that D’Esposito and Postle’s (1999) earlier work debunking the prefrontal dogma of working memory featured similar paradigms in humans.

  15. And it appears that Chimpanzees are also capable of successfully negotiating dual-task conditions (consult Völter et al. 2019, especially experiment 2).

  16. Cf. Hume’s distinction of the force and vivacity brought on by impressions versus ideas for a similar intuition.

  17. In fact, this is made explicit by Postle (2016) who stipulates that working memory must require prefrontal control, and so tasks that fail to recruit the prefrontal cortex should not count as proper working memory tasks (45).

  18. I’d like to thank a reviewer for persuading me to reflect on these issues.

  19. That is, it’s not clear that these are treated as natural kinds or natural kind candidates, though they might be thought of as property clusters anchored by representational (e.g., by using primarily analog or iconic representations: Quilty-Dunn 2019), computational (e.g., by featuring aspects of modularity: Firestone and Scholl 2016), or behavioral (e.g., by reverse-engineering the paradigms and tasks used to test perceptual capacities in a similar way to Buckner’s 2015 treatment of cognition) features

  20. And, conversely, that artificially restricting working memory to a post hoc subset of tasks (e.g., manipulation tasks) will leave it unable to project to the broader class of central cognitions that it is thought to support.

  21. At the same time, the explanatory landscape pictured above should help identify other cognitive categories, particularly attention, intention, and executive function, which share working memory’s position in the ‘explanatory stack’ and may be subject to a similar argumentative strategy.

  22. Again, thanks to a reviewer for raising this concern.

  23. As I envision it, this project would build upon and extend a useful heuristic that I’ve come to half-jokingly term the second paragraph rule. Most empirical papers on working memory begin with a formulaic description of working memory as the capacity that enables us to maintain and manipulate information, etc., before citing Baddeley’s or Cowan’s or another popular model. Afterwards, and sometimes as soon as the second paragraph, the authors make clear the specific iteration of maintenance or manipulation under investigation. Consult Zanto et al. 2011 paper for an excellent example of this heuristic in action, where their focus is, in fact, understanding how impacts to top down activity projected on visual cortices affects selective attention and recognition. This process, under the productive pessimism that I’m advocating, would be a candidate description for how we maintain information. Ideally, much of the work of perusing the literature could be managed using machine learning or natural language processing, quickly yielding a trove of similar candidate descriptions.

References

  • Adams, E.J., A.T. Nguyen, and N. Cowan. 2018. Theories of working memory: Differences in definition, degree of modularity, role of attention, and purpose. Language, Speech, and Hearing Services in Schools 49: 340–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C. 2017. On (not) defining cognition. Synthese 194: 4233–4249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle & Hamlyn, D. W. (1993). De Anima: Books II and III. New York: Oxford University.

  • Atkinson, R.C. & Shiffrin, R. M. (1971). The control processes of short term memory (Report No. 173). Institute for Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences: Stanford: USA.

  • Baddeley, A. 1996. Exploring the central executive. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 49 (A): 5–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. 2007. Working memory, Thought, and Action. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. 2010. Working Memory. Current Biology 20: R136–R140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A., and G. Hitch. 1974. Working memory. Psychology of learning and motivation 8: 47–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A., and R.H. Logie. 1999. Working Memory: The multiple-component model. In Models of Working Memory, ed. A. Miyake and P. Shah. New York: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H.C. (1990). Matter and Memory (N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer, Trans.), Princeton: Zone Books.

  • Bogdanov, M., and L. Schwabe. 2017. Transcranial stimulation of the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex prevents stress-induced working memory deficits. Journal of Neuroscience 36: 1429–1437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. 1999. Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In Species: New interdisciplinary essays, ed. R.A. Wilson. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. 2001. Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. 2015. A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology 28: 307–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2014. On Central Cognition. Philosophical Studies 170: 143–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2015. The Centered Mind: What the Science of Working Memory Shows Us About the Nature of Human Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, S., and M. Werning. 2016. What is episodic memory if it is a natural kind? Synthese 193 (5): 1345–1385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherniak, C. 1986. Minimal Rationality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christophel, T.B., P.C. Klink, B. Spitzer, P.R. Roelfsema, and J.D. Haynes. 2017. The distributed nature of working memory. TRENDS in Cognitive Science 21 (2): 111–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, N. 1988. Evolving conceptions of memory storage, selective attention, and their mutual constraints within the human information processing system. Psychological Bulletin 104: 163–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, N. 2008. What are the differences between long-term, short-term, and working memory? Progress in Brain Research 169: 323–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, N. 2017. The many faces of working memory and short-term storage. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 24: 1158–1170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craik, F.I.M., and B.A. Levy. 1976. The concept of primary memory. In Handbook of Learning and Cognitive Processes, Volume 4, ed. W.K. Estes, 133–175. New York: John Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. 2009. Mechanisms as natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology 22: 575–594.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Esposito, M., B.R. Postle, D. Ballard, and J. Lease. 1999. Maintenance versus manipulation of information held in working memory: An event-related fMRI study. Brain and Cognition 41: 66–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. 2014. Consciousness and the Brain: Deciphering how the Brain Codes our Thoughts. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Esposito, M., and B.R. Postle. 1999. The dependence of span and delayed-response performance on prefrontal cortex. Neuropsychologia 37: 1303–1315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dragoi, G., K.D. Harris, and G. Buzsáki. 2003. Place representation within hippocampal networks is modified by long-term potentiation. Neuron 39: 843–853.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engle, R.W. 2002. Working memory capacity as executive attention. Current Directions in Psychological Science 11: 19–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J.S.B., and K.E. Stanovich. 2013. Dual process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science 8: 223–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, J. 2019. Memory: A Self-Referential Account. New York: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Firestone, C., and B.J. Scholl. 2016. Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for ‘top-down’ effects. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funahashi, S., C.J. Bruce, and P. Goldman-Rakic. 1989. Mnemonic coding of visual space in the monkey’s dorsolateral prefrontal cortex. Journal of Neurophysiology 61: 331–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuster, J.M., and G.E. Alexander. 1971. Neuron activity related to short-term memory. Science 173 (3997): 652–654.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M.S., R.B. Ivry, and G.R. Mangun. 2009. Cognitive Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerstner, W., A.K. Kreiter, H. Markram, and A.V.M. Herz. 1997. Neural codes: Firing rates and beyond. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 94: 12740–12741.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gevins, A., M.E. Smith, L. McEvoy, and D. Yu. 1997. High-resolution EEG mapping of cortical activation related to working memory: Effects of task difficulty, type of processing, and practice. Cerebral Cortex 7: 374–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2016. Other Minds. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman-Rakic, P.S. 1995. Cellular basis of working memory. Neuron 14 (3): 477–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomez-Lavin, J. (2017) The centered mind: What the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought. Philosophical Psychology 30(5):685–688.

  • Hacking, I. 2007. The contingencies of ambiguity. Analysis 67: 269–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1965). The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness (J.S. Churchill, Trans.; M. Heidegger, Ed.), Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

  • Ikkai, A., and C. Curtis. 2011. Common neural mechanisms supporting spatial working memory, attention and motor intention. Neuropsychologia 49: 1428–1434.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology. Vol. 1. New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerde, T.A., E.P. Merriam, A.C. Riggall, J.H. Hedges, and C.E. Curtis. 2012. Prioritized maps of space in human frontoparietal cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 32 (48): 17382–17390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiruska, P., J. Csicsvari, A.D. Powell, et al. 2010. High-frequency network activity, global increase in neuronal activity, and synchrony expansion precede epileptic seizures in vitro. Journal of Neuroscience 30: 5690–5701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonides, J., and D.E. Nee. 2006. Brain mechanisms of proactive interference in working memory. Neuroscience 139 (1): 181–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M.A. 2013. Natural Categories and Human Kinds. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2015). Natural kinds as nodes in casual networks. Synthese, Special issue: Metaphysics and Causation (online).

  • Klatzky, R. 1975. Human Memory: Structures and Processes. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B. 2015. What memory is. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 6 (1): 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C.M. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kubota, K., and H. Niki. 1971. Prefrontal cortical unit activity and delayed alternation performance in monkeys. Journal of Neurophysiology 34 (3): 337–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladd, G.T. 1887. Elements of Physiological Psychology. London: Longmans, Green & Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • LaRocque, J.J., J.A. Lewis-Peacock, and B.R. Postle. 2014. Multiple neural states of representation in short-term memory? It's a matter of attention. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8 (5): 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaRocque, J. J., Eichenbaum, N. S., Starrett, M. J., Rose, N. S., Emrich, S. M., & Postle, B. R. (2015). The short- and long-term fate of memory items retained outside the focus of attention. Special Issue on Working Memory] Memory & Cognition 43 (3), 453–468.

  • Lewis-Peacock, J.A., A.T. Drysdale, and B.R. Postle. 2015. Neural evidence for the flexible control of mental representations. Cerebral Cortex 25 (10): 3303–3313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis-Peacock, J.A., A.T. Drysdale, K. Oberauer, and B.R. Postle. 2012. Neural evidence for a distinction between short-term memory and the focus of attention. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 24 (1): 61–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. 2011. Is memory a natural kind? Memory Studies 4 (2): 170–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. 2015. Opening the doors of memory: Is declarative memory a natural kind? Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 6 (6): 475–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G., E. Galanter, and K.H. Pribram. 1960. Plans and the Structure of Behavior. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyake, A., and P. Shah. 1999. Models of Working Memory. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., and H.A. Simon. 1956. A logic theory machine and a complex information processing system. Santa Monica, California: The RAND Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrides, M. 2000. The role of the mid-dorsolateral prefrontal cortex in working memory. Experimental Brain Research 133: 44–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polonsky, A., R. Blake, J. Braun, and D.J. Heeger. 2000. Neuronal activity in human primary visual cortex correlates with perception during binocular rivalry. Nature Neuroscience 3: 1153–1159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postle, B.R. 2006. Working Memory as an emergent property of the mind and brain. Neuroscience 139 (1): 23–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postle, B.R. 2016. Neural bases of the short-term retention of visual information. In Mechanisms of Sensory Working Memory: Attention and Performance XXV, ed. P. Jolicoeur, C. Lefebvre, and J. Martinez-Trujillo, 43–58. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postle, B.R., F. Ferrarelli, M. Hamidi, E. Feredoes, Peterson M. Massimini, A. Alexander, and G. Tononi. 2006. Repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation dissociates working memory manipulation from retention functions in prefrontal, but not posterior parietal, cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 18: 1712–1722.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2012. The Conscious Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. 2019. Is iconic memory iconic? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12625.

  • Ramsey, W. 2017. Must cognition be representational? Synthese 194: 4197–4214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Repovš, G., and A. Baddeley. 2006. The multi-component model of working memory: Explorations in experimental cognitive psychology. Neuroscience 139: 5–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rottschy, C., R. Langer, I. Dogan, K. Reetz, A.R. Laird, J.B. Schulz, P.T. Fox, and S.B. Eickhoff. 2012. Modelling neural correlates of working memory: A coordinate-based meta-analysis. NeuroImage 60 (1): 830–846.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shallice, T., and E.K. Warrington. 1970. Independent functioning of verbal memory stores: A neuropsychological study. The Quarterly journal of experimental psychology 22 (2): 261–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, R.N., and J. Metzler. 1971. Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science 171: 701–703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprauge, T.C., E.F. Ester, and J.T. Serences. 2016. Representing latent visual working memory representations in human cortex. Neuron 91: 694–707.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, M.G. 2015. ‘Activity-silent’ working memory in prefrontal cortex: A dynamic coding framework. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 19 (7): 394–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Völter, C. J, Mundry, R., Call J., & Seed, A. M. (2019). Chimpanzees flexible update working memory contents and show susceptibility to distraction in the self-order search task. Proceedings of the Royal Society, 286(B), (online).

  • Wang, K.S., D.V. Smith, and M.R. Delgado. 2016. Using fMRI to study reward processing in humans: Past, present, and future. Journal of Neurophysiology 115: 1664–1678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanto, T.P., M.T. Rubens, A. Thangavel, and A. Gazzaley. 2011. Causal role of the prefrontal cortex in top-down modulation of visual processing and working memory. Nature Neuroscience 14: 656–661.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This project could not have been realized without the continued support and feedback from friends and colleagues, and a number of helpful audiences from the ESPP in 2015, the SSPP in 2018, the Neural Mechanisms Online Webconference in 2018, and the 2019 Workshop on Natural Kinds and Cognitive Science hosted by York University. I am especially grateful to Lisa Miracchi and the MIRA group at the University of Pennsylvania, to David Rosenthal and the CUNY Cognitive Science Speakers Series, and to Michael Pauen and his group at the Berlin School of Mind and Brain, for allowing me to workshop iterations of this paper. I am also indebted to Matthew Rachar, Tyler Brooke-Wilson, Jesse Prinz, John Greenwood, Felipe de Brigard, Shaun Nichols, Eric Mandelbaum, and a slew of anonymous reviewers for their invaluable comments on earlier drafts. Finally, I am particularly grateful for the support of some of my earliest mentors, including Carol Seger and especially Whit Schonbein, for persuading me to look critically at working memory and for their immense help throughout this long process.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier Gomez-Lavin.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gomez-Lavin, J. Working memory is not a natural kind and cannot explain central cognition. Rev.Phil.Psych. 12, 199–225 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00507-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00507-4

Navigation