Skip to main content
Log in

Technical Artefact Theories: A Comparative Study and a New Empirical Approach

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Embracing an inter-disciplinary approach grounded on Gärdenfors’ theory of conceptual spaces, we introduce a formal framework to analyse and compare selected theories about technical artefacts present in the literature. Our focus is on design-oriented approaches where both designing and manufacturing activities play a crucial role. Intentional theories, like Kroes’ dual nature thesis, are able to solve disparate problems concerning artefacts but they face both the philosophical challenge of clarifying the ontological nature of intentional properties, and the empirical challenge of testing the attribution of such intentional properties to artefacts. To avoid these issues, we propose an approach that, by identifying different modalities to characterise artefact types, does not commit to intentional qualities and is able to empirically ground compliance tests.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is a hot philosophical debate on whether artefacts are part of the fundamental structure of reality or whether they are the result of how humans conceptualise reality (Lowe 2014; Thomasson 2007; Hilpinen 1993; Franseen et al. 2014a).

  2. A similar work has been done for functions (Borgo et al. 2011; Garbacz et al. 2011).

  3. Some qualities may have a complex nature. For instance, colours can be defined in terms of hue, brightness, and saturation. We do not consider this aspect in the paper.

  4. Correlations can hold between qualities belonging to different domains, cf. Section 2.2.

  5. Gärdenfors assumes that in different contexts the salience of a given property or domain for a concept can change. For simplicity, we do not consider this aspect here.

  6. Formulas prefixed by f are used for examples or constraints that are not in our theory.

  7. Ontologically, subsumption can be intended as a genus-species relation or, more specifically, as a determinable-determinate relation, see Sanford (2013).

  8. Some correlations can universally hold. For instance, Einstein’s mass-energy equivalence links energy and mass through the constant c2, i.e., every individual with a given energy has a given mass and vice versa.

  9. We focus hereby on correlations that link only two different domains.

  10. We do not discuss quality domains characterising processes. The reader can refer to Masolo et al. (2003) for an ontological proposal that distinguishes the qualities of processes from the ones of objects, and to Warglien et al. (2012) and Gärdenfors (2014) for the representation of events and actions in conceptual spaces.

  11. It is possible to take into account procedures to transform the chaotic collection of raw data into a dataset consistent with the knowledge at stake (Masolo et al. 2018).

  12. We refrain from introducing a formal definition for this notion of classification, which is possible in FOL but requires several additional primitives.

  13. This approach matches well with the idea in Guarino and Stufano Melone (2015) where designers, during the development of a new type, think in terms of prototypes.

  14. Decock and Douven (2011) introduce a fuzzy classification in conceptual spaces.

  15. Recall that neither empirical nor direct classification under a quality guarantees the object to (ontologically) instantiate such quality; measurement only supports this instantiation.

  16. Gärdenfors (2000) proposes to analyze functional properties in terms of affordances.

  17. The distinction between layout and non-layout qualities is similar to the one between characteristics and properties in Weber (2014).

  18. Axioms (a16) and (a17) do not guarantee that the specification satisfies the requirement; the framework may lack correlations about what layout qualities are necessary to exhibit some properties in the requirement.

  19. As noted in Section 2.4, the notion of tolerance is more complex. For instance, while in the qualities , , and are equally judged, expresses a preference for the quality .

  20. For a philosophical analysis of manufacturing plans see Houkes and Vermaas (2014).

  21. Garbacz (2013) considers additional steps that would constitute an interesting extension of our proposal.

  22. Section 4.2 will make explicit the difference with respect to the dual theory of artefacts (Kroes 2012).

  23. Gärdenfors (2000, ch.4) discusses alternative models for combining concepts. See also Hampton and Winter (2017) for a recent discussion on concepts composition.

  24. We did not introduce an explicit identity criterion for types, therefore the unicity of the compound cannot be guaranteed. In addition, (d16) makes sense only when coherence axioms hold.

  25. According to Borgo and Vieu (2009), an artefact (as intentionally selected object) might lack some of the attributed capacities, e.g., it may malfunction. This would mean that the attributed capacities are not selected (by the creator) among the ones that the artefact’s constituent exhibits.

  26. Salience-dependent classifications allow for an additional notion of malfunctioning. The lack of some (combinations of) qualities present in the specification, lack that is tolerated by graded classifications, could cause the object to clash with some requirements. In an engineering perspective, this scenario is realistic when the full check of the specification is time or resource consuming.

  27. Gärdenfors (2014) only briefly discusses relational concepts concerning roles in events.

  28. The ICE-function theory is also based on use-plans, which are not considered here.

  29. As said, designers may also assume that requirements are not all equally important, hence, they may distinguish soft requirements from hard ones (salience weights are useful for this purpose) tolerating discrepancies between the specifications and the requirements.

  30. Houkes and Vermaas (2014) have a similar position towards the specification, i.e., they assume that the checks of the qualities in the specification are part of the manufacturing process. In this case, one could think that the designers intend the specification more than the requirement. See below for more details on this point.

  31. By understanding these checks as the physical embodiments of the goals of the production process, it is possible to establish a link with the previously discussed approaches in Houkes and Vermaas (2014), Kassel (2010), and Kitamura and Mizoguchi (2010).

  32. This relation can be modified following what done in Section 2.4 to take into account the salience of qualities. In this case the manufacturing process could lack some low-salient (tests of) qualities.

  33. Note that (d24) does not constrain the persistence of v and u. After the end of the checking phase, one could assume that v goes out of existence or that both u and v persist by being physically coincident (but historically different).

  34. This information is explicitly encoded using standardised languages in the documentation that supports the designing process and has a high degree of sharability, i.e., the choices of designers are not private as intentional qualities are, they are publicly available.

  35. According to Houkes and Vermaas (2014), the layout qualities must be satisfied only at the end of the production process, but the artefacts may loose some physical qualities while keeping their identity.

References

  • Baker, LR. 1995. Explaining attitudes: A practical approach to the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. 1996. Intention, history, and artifact concepts. Cognition 60(1): 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgo, S, and L Vieu. 2009. Artefacts in formal ontology. Handbook of philosophy of technology and engineering sciences, chapter 9, ed. Meijers A, 273–308. Elsevier.

  • Borgo, S, M Carrara, P Garbacz, and PE Vermaas. 2011. A formalization of functions as operations on flows. J Comput Inf Sci Eng 11(3): 031007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgo, S, M Franssen, P Garbacz, Y Kitamura, R Mizoguchi, and PE Vermaas. 2014. Technical artifacts: an integrated perspective. Appl Ontol 9 (3-4): 217–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrara, M, and D Mingardo. 2013. Artifact categorization. trends and problems. Rev Philos Psychol 4(3): 351–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrara, M, and PE Vermaas. 2009. The fine-grained metaphysics of artifactual and biological functional kinds. Synthese 169(1): 125–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R, and A Varzi. 1999. Parts and Places: The Structures of Spatial Representation. cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R, and A Varzi. 2015. Events. In: Zalta, EN, editor, The Stan- ford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, winter 2015 edition.

  • Chisholm, R M. 1982. Converse intentional properties. J Philos 79(10): 537–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decock, L, and I Douven. 2011. Similarity after goodman. Rev Philos Psychol 2(1): 61–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dym, C, and P Little. 2005. Engineering design: A material and processing approach. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, W, and S Hosnedl. 2008. Design Engineering: A Manual for Enhanced Creativity. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiorini Rama, S, and M Abel. 2013. Part-whole relations as products of metric spaces. 2013 IEEE 25th International Conference on Tools with Artificial Intelligence (ICTAI), 55–62.

  • Fiorini Rama, S, P Gȧrdenfors, and M Abel. 2014. Representing part-whole relations in conceptual spaces. Cogn Process 15(2): 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franseen, M, P Kroes, T Reydon, and P Vermaas, (eds). 2014a. Artefact Kinds. Ontology and the Human-Made World. Berlin, Springer.

  • Franssen, M, and P Kroes. 2014b. Artefact kinds, ontological criteria and forms of mind-dependence. In: Franseen, M, Kroes, P, Reydon, T, and Vermaas, P, editors, Artefact Kinds. Ontology and the Human Made World, 63–83: Springer, Berlin.

  • Galle, P. 1998. Design as intentional action: a conceptual analysis. Des Stud 20(1): 57–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galle, P. 2008. Candidate worldviews for design theory. Des Stud 29(3): 267–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garbacz, P, S Borgo, M Carrara, and PE Vermaas. 2011. Two ontology-driven formalisations of functions and their comparison. J Eng Des 22 (11-12): 733–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garbacz, P. 2013. Artefacts and family resemblance. Rev Philos Psychol 4 (3): 419–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. 2000. Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. 2014. The geometry of meaning: Semantics based on conceptual spaces. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Groover, MP. 2007. Fundamentals of modern manufacturing: materials processes, and systems. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, N, and M Stufano Melone. 2015. On the ontological status of design objects. In: Lisi, F, Borgo, S, editors, Proceedings of the 1st Workshop on Artificial Intelligence & Design (AIDE), vol 1473, pp 27–32. CEUR.

  • Hampton, JA, and Y Winter. 2017. Compositionality and concepts in linguistics and psychology. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. 1993. Authors and artifacts. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (vol 93, 155–178). JSTOR.

  • Houkes, W, and A Meijers. 2006. The ontology of artefacts: the hard problem. Stud History Philos Sci Part A 37(1): 118–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W, and PE Vermaas. 2010. Technical functions: On the use and design of artefacts. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W, and PE Vermaas. 2013. Pluralism on artefact categories: a philosophical defence. Rev Philos Psychol 4(3): 543–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes, W, and PE Vermaas. 2014. On what is made: instruments, products and natural kinds of artefacts. In: Franssen, MPK, Reydon, T, Vermaas, P, editors, Artefact Kinds: Ontology and the Human-Made World, 167–190. Springer.

  • Kassel, G. 2010. A formal ontology of artefacts. Appl Ontol 5(3-4): 223–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitamura, Y, and R Mizoguchi. 2010. Characterizing functions based on ontological models from an engineering. In Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the Sixth International Conference (FOIS 2010), 301. IOS Press.

  • Kroes, P. 2006. Coherence of structural and functional descriptions of technical artefacts. Stud History Philos Sci Part A 37(1): 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroes, P. 2012. The dual nature of technical artefacts: Creations of Mind and Matter. A Philosophy of Engineering Design. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, R, and M Fink. 2006. The case against evidence-based principles in psychiatry. Med Hypothes 67: 401–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. 2014. How real are artefacts and artefact kinds? In: Franseen, M, Kroes, P, Reydon, T, Vermaas, P, editors, Artefact Kinds. Ontology and the Human-Made World, 17–26. Springer.

  • Malt, B C, S A Sloman, S Gennari, M Shi, and Y Wang. 1999. Knowing versus naming: Similarity and the linguistic categorization of artifacts. J Memory Lang 40(2): 230–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, JM. 2004. The foundations of mind: Origins of conceptual thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, C, S Borgo, A Gangemi, N Guarino, and A Oltramari. 2003. Wonderweb deliverable d18. Technical report, CNR.

  • Masolo, C, L Vieu, E Bottazzi, C Catenacci, R Ferrario, A Gangemi, and N Guarino. 2004. Social roles and their descriptions. In: Dubois, D, Welty, C, Williams, M, editors, Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 267–277. AAAI Press.

  • Masolo, C, and D Porello. 2016. Understanding predication in conceptual spaces. In: Ferrario, R, Kuhn, W, editors, Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the 9th International Conference (FOIS 2016), 139–152. IOS Press.

  • Masolo, C, A B Benevides, and D Porello. 2018. The interplay between models and observations. Appl Ontol 13: 41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S, and RL Anjum. 2013. Causation: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K. 1996. Language in cognitive development: The emergence of the mediated mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, TA. 2014. Metaphysical and epistemological approaches to developing a theory of artifact kinds. In Franssen, MPK, Reydon, T, Vermaas, P, editors, Artefact Kinds: Ontology and the Human-Made World, 125–144. Springer.

  • Romero Subirón, F, P Rosado Castellano, G Bruscas Bellido, and S Benavent Nácher. 2018. Feature-based framework for inspection process planning. Materials 11(9): 1504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. 1978. Principles of categorization. In: Rosch, E, Lloyd, BB, editors, Cognition and categorization, 27–48. Lawrence Erlbaum.

  • Rouse, I. 1960. The classification of artifacts in archaeology. Amer Antiq 25 (3): 313–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanfilippo, E M, L Jeanson, F Belkadi, F Laroche, and A Bernard. 2018. A foundational view on nominal and actual qualities in engineering. In: FOIS, 149–156.

  • Sanford, DH. 2013. Determinates vs. determinables. In: Zalta, EN, editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Smith, E E, D N Osherson, L J Rips, and M Keane. 1988. Combining prototypes: a selective modification model. Cogn Sci 12(4): 485–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. 2007. Artifacts and human concepts. In: Margolis, E, Laurence, S, editors, Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, 52–73. Oxford University Press.

  • Tversky, A. 1977. Features of similarity. Psychol Rev 84(4): 327–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaccari, A. 2013. Artifact dualism, materiality, and the hard problem of ontology: Some critical remarks on the dual nature of technical artifacts program. Philos Technol 26(1): 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaesen, K. 2011. The functional bias of the dual nature of technical artefacts program. Stud History Philos Sci Part A 42(1): 190–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warglien, M, P Gärdenfors, and M Westera. 2012. Event structure, conceptual spaces and the semantics of verbs. Theor Linguist 3-4(38): 159–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, C. 2014. Modelling products and product development based on characteristics and properties. In: Chakrabarti, A, Blessing, L, editors, An Anthology of Theories and Models of Design. Philosophy, Approaches and Empirical Explorations, 327–352. Springer.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudio Masolo.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Masolo, C., Sanfilippo, E.M. Technical Artefact Theories: A Comparative Study and a New Empirical Approach. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 831–858 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00475-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00475-9

Keywords

Navigation