Skip to main content
Log in

Perspective and Epistemic State Ascriptions

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article explores whether perspective taking has an impact on the ascription of epistemic states. To do so, a new method is introduced which incites participants to imagine themselves in the position of the protagonist of a short vignette and to judge from her perspective. In a series of experiments (total N=1980), perspective proves to have a significant impact on belief ascriptions, but not on knowledge ascriptions. For belief, perspective is further found to moderate the epistemic side-effect effect significantly. It is hypothesized that the surprising findings are driven by the special epistemic authority we enjoy in assessing our own belief states, which does not extend to the assessment of our own knowledge states.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the similarities and differences of guilty mind ascriptions in moral judgment and criminal jurisprudence, cf. Duff (1989) and Moore (2011).

  2. The effect has been widely replicated (Knobe 2003a, b, 2004b; Mele and Cushman 2007). It holds across cultures (Knobe and Burra 2006) and ages (Leslie et al. 2006), and is just as robust for professional lawyers and judges as for laymen (Kneer and Bourgeois-Gironde 2017a, forthcoming, 2017b). For a brief overview, see Feltz (2007) as well as Cova (2016). Cova and Naar (2012) report an asymmetry in intentionality ascriptions without relying on side-effect scenarios.

  3. Whether the side-effects in Knobe’s scenarios should indeed be understood as knowingly incurred is by now a topic of controversy, because a similar asymmetry arises in epistemic state ascriptions for the same scenarios (cf. Beebe and Buckwalter 2010; Beebe and Jensen 2012). More on this below.

  4. Only a few are quoted here, though Alfano and colleagues defend similar heuristics for desiring p, being in favour of p, advocating p and other attitudes that have been shown to be susceptible to the Knobe effect.

  5. The content of the various doxastic heuristics does not require belief as a necessary condition for the target mental states. A strong, yet defeasible relationship holding for ordinary cases is sufficient. The agents, of course, need not to be explicitly aware of the heuristics.

  6. What constitutes responsible priming is a matter of extensive debate. Suffice it to say for now that in the experiments below the topic is addressed in detail. As will be shown, providing participants in the observer conditions with a third-person POVAP analogue does not alter the results.

  7. Beebe (2013), cf. also Sverdlik (2004).

  8. Colaço, Kneer, Alexander & Machery, On second thought: A refutation of the reflection defense (ms.) employ a number of manipulations used in social psychology and experimental economics to increase deliberation. In a series of five experiments testing classic philosophical thought-experiments, not a single manipulation had a significant impact on judgment. Similarly, studies by Schwitzgebel and Cushman (2012, 2015) find that the judgments of laymen and trained philosophers, with their penchant for careful and extensive deliberation, manifest very little difference. For further discussion of reflective judgment, cf. Alexander and Weinberg (2007), Weinberg et al. (2012).

  9. Note that blame ascriptions differed significantly across conditions for all three scenarios, which suggests that the normative differences were indeed salient to the participants. There was no significant difference for blame ascriptions across perspectives, which blocks a defence of Alfano et al.’s account according to which the actor perspective reduces the salience of norm-violation (cf. for instance, Robinson et al. 2015) .

  10. Cf. Malle et al. (2007).

  11. The term actor/observer asymmetry should be used with care, as it was originally intended to refer to the difference in explanation types regarding the behaviour of oneself v. others (cf. Jones and Nisbett 1971), rather than perspective effects broadly conceived.

  12. In fact, our results are broadly consistent with such an unorthodox view of epistemology: For half of the four conditions of the sales experiment, and all of the four conditions of the chairman and movies experiments, mean knowledge ascriptions significantly exceed mean belief ascriptions.

  13. For an interesting discussion of the results of Myers-Schulz and Schwitzgebel, see Rose and Schaffer (2013) and Buckwalter et al. (2015).

References

  • Alexander, J., and J.M. Weinberg. 2007. Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass 2 (1): 56–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano, M., J.R. Beebe, and B. Robinson. 2012. The centrality of belief and reflection in Knobe-effect cases: A unified account of the data. The Monist 95 (2): 264–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C.D., J.H. Eklund, V.L. Chermok, J.L. Hoyt, and B.G. Ortiz. 2007. An additional antecedent of empathic concern: Valuing the welfare of the person in need. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93 (1): 65–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R. 2013. A Knobe effect for belief ascriptions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4 (2): 235–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R. 2016. Evaluative effects on knowledge attributions. In A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, ed. J. Sytsma and W. Buckwalter. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.

  • Beebe, J.R., and W. Buckwalter. 2010. The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind & Language 25 (4): 474–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R., and M. Jensen. 2012. Surprising connections between knowledge and action: The robustness of the epistemic side-effect effect. Philosophical Psychology 25 (5): 689–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J.R., and J. Shea. 2013. Gettierized Knobe Effects. Episteme 10 (3): 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaine, B., and J. Crocker. 1993. Self-esteem and self-serving biases in reactions to positive and negative events: An integrative review. In Self-esteem: The Puzzle of low Self-regard, ed. R. Baumeister, 55–85. New York: Springer.

  • BonJour, L. 2009. Epistemology: Classic Problems and Contemporary Responses. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

  • Buckwalter, W. 2012. Non-traditional factors in judgments about knowledge. Philosophy Compass 7 (4): 278–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. 2014. Gettier made ESEE. Philosophical Psychology 27 (3): 368–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., D. Rose, and J. Turri. 2015. Belief through thick and thin. Noûs 49 (4): 748–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. 2005. Introspection. Philosophical Topics 33 (1): 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. 2011. Knowing that I am thinking. In Self-knowledge, ed. A. Hatzimoysis, 105–124. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. 1997. Self and World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. 2011. Knowing what you believe. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 111, part 1: 1–23.

  • Cassam, Q. 2014. Self-knowledge for Humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, R.B., S.L. Brown, B.P. Lewis, C. Luce, and S.L. Neuberg. 1997. Reinterpreting the empathy–altruism relationship: When one into one equals oneness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73 (3): 481–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. 2013. Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cova, F. 2016. The folk concept of intentional action. In A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, eds. J. Sytsma and W. Buckwalter. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.

  • Cova, F., and H. Naar. 2012. Side-effect effect without side effects: The pervasive impact of moral considerations on judgments of intentionality. Philosophical Psychology 25 (6): 837–854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalbauer, N., and A. Hergovich. 2013. Is what is worse more likely?—The probabilistic explanation of the epistemic side-effect effect. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4 (4): 639–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1994. Introspection. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94: 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, A. 1980. Intention, Mens Rea and the law commission report. Criminal Law Review: 147–160.

  • Duff, A. 1982. Intention, responsibility and double effect. The Philosophical Quarterly 32: 1–16.

  • Duff, A. 1989. Intentions legal and philosophical. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 9: 76–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epley, N., E. Caruso, and M.H. Bazerman. 2006. When perspective taking increases taking: Reactive egoism in social interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 91 (5): 872–889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faul, F., E. Erdfelder, A. Buchner, and A.-G. Lang. 2009. Statistical power analyses using G* power 3.1: Tests for correlation and regression analyses. Behavior Research Methods 41 (4): 1149–1160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. 2006. Epistemology. London: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A. 2007. The Knobe effect: A brief overview. Journal of Mind and Behavior 28 (3/4): 265–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., M. Harris, and A. Perez. 2012. Perspective in intentional action attribution. Philosophical Psychology 25 (5): 673–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez-Duque, D., and T. Wifall. 2007. Actor/observer asymmetry in risky decision making. Judgment and Decision making 2 (1): 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky, A.D., and G.B. Moskowitz. 2000. Perspective-taking: Decreasing stereotype expression, stereotype accessibility, and in-group favoritism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 78 (4): 708–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky, A.D., G. Ku, and C.S. Wang. 2005. Perspective-taking and self-other overlap: Fostering social bonds and facilitating social coordination. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations 8 (2): 109–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky, A.D., W.W. Maddux, D. Gilin, and J.B. White. 2008. Why it pays to get inside the head of your opponent: The differential effects of perspective taking and empathy in negotiations. Psychological Science 19 (4): 378–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. 2010. Self-knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1976. Practical reasoning. The Review of Metaphysics 29 (3): 431–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, R. 2010. Norms and the Knobe effect. Analysis 70 (3): 417–424.

  • Jones, E.E., and R.E. Nisbett. 1971. The actor and the observer: Divergent perceptions of the causes of behavior. In Attribution: Perceiving the Causes of Behavior, eds. E.E. Jones et al. Morristown: General Learning Press.

  • Kauppinen, A. 2007. The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10 (2): 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kneer, M., and S. Bourgeois-Gironde. 2017a. Attribution de mens rea: Données empiriques. In Causalité, Responsabilité et Contribution à la Dette, eds. S. Ferrey and F. G'Sell. Brussels: Editions Bruylant. (Forthcoming).

  • Kneer, M., and S. Bourgeois-Gironde, S. 2017b. Mens rea ascriptions, expertise and outcome effects: Professional judges surveyed. Cognition 169: 139–146.

  • Knobe, J. 2003a. Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63 (3): 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2003b. Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology 16 (2): 309–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2004a. Folk psychology and folk morality: Response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 270–279.

  • Knobe, J. 2004b. Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64 (2): 181–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and A. Burra. 2006. The folk concepts of intention and intentional action: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1): 113–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and B.F. Malle. 2002. Self and other in the explanation of behavior: 30 Years later. Psychologica Belgica 42 (1/2): 113–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and G.S. Mendlow. 2004. The good, the bad and the blameworthy: Understanding the role of evaluative reasoning in folk psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 252–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurent, S.M., and M.W. Myers. 2011. I know you're me, but who am I? Perspective taking and seeing the other in the self. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 47 (6): 1316–1319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. 2015. Theory of knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M., J. Knobe, and A. Cohen. 2006. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect theory of mind and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17 (5): 421–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T., and K. Uttich. 2010. Putting normativity in its proper place. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4): 344–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. 2007. The epistemology of thought experiments: First person versus third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31 (1): 128–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B.F. 2006. The actor-observer asymmetry in attribution: A (surprising) meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 132 (6): 895–919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B.F., J.M. Knobe, and S.E. Nelson. 2007. Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93 (4): 491–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maner, J.K., C.L. Luce, S.L. Neuberg, R.B. Cialdini, S. Brown, and B.J. Sagarin. 2002. The effects of perspective taking on motivations for helping: Still no evidence for altruism. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 28 (11): 1601–1610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCullough, M.E., E.L. Worthington Jr., and K.C. Rachal. 1997. Interpersonal forgiving in close relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73 (2): 321–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A.R., and F. Cushman. 2007. Intentional action, folk judgments, and stories: Sorting things out. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31 (1): 184–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mezulis, A.H., L.Y. Abramson, J.S. Hyde, and B.L. Hankin. 2004. Is there a universal positivity bias in attributions? A meta-analytic review of individual, developmental, and cultural differences in the self-serving attributional bias. Psychological Bulletin 130 (5): 711–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M.S. 2011. Intention as a marker of moral culpability and legal punishability. In Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law, eds. A. Duff and S.P. Green. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., J. Sytsma, and J. Livengood. 2013. God knows (but does god believe?). Philosophical Studies 166 (1): 83–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers-Schulz, B., and E. Schwitzgebel. 2013. Knowing that P without believing that P. Noûs 47 (2): 371–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T., and A. Feltz. 2008. The actor–observer bias and moral intuitions: Adding fuel to Sinnott-Armstrong’s fire. Neuroethics 1 (2): 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, S.K., and C.M. Axtell. 2001. Seeing another viewpoint: Antecedents and outcomes of employee perspective taking. Academy of Management Journal 44 (6): 1085–1100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelan, M.T., and H. Sarkissian. 2008. The folk strike back; or, why you didn’t do it intentionally, though it was bad and you knew it. Philosophical Studies 138 (2): 291–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollai, M., and E. Kirchler. 2012. Differences in risk-defusing behavior in deciding for oneself versus deciding for other people. Acta Psychologica 139 (1): 239–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, B., P. Stey, and M. Alfano. 2015. Reversing the side-effect effect: The power of salient norms. Philosophical Studies 172 (1): 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., and J. Schaffer. 2013. Knowledge entails dispositional belief. Philosophical Studies 166 (1): 19–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., and F. Cushman. 2012. Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind & Language 27 (2): 135–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., and F. Cushman. 2015. Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise and reflection. Cognition 141: 127–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. 2012. On the phenomenology of introspection. In Introspection and Consciousness, eds. D. Smithies and D. Stoljar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Smith, A. 1790/2002. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sverdlik, S. 2004. Intentionality and moral judgments in commonsense thought about action. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 224–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takaku, S., B. Weiner, and K.-I. Ohbuchi. 2001. A cross-cultural examination of the effects of apology and perspective taking on forgiveness. Journal of Language and Social Psychology 20 (1–2): 144–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. 2014. The problem of ESEE knowledge. Ergo 1 (4): 101–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. 2016. Knowledge judgments in “Gettier” cases. In A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, eds. J. Sytsma and W. Buckwalter, 335–348. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.

  • Uttich, K., and T. Lombrozo. 2010. Norms inform mental state ascriptions: A rational explanation for the side-effect effect. Cognition 116 (1): 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weijers, D. 2014. Nozick's Experience machine is dead, long live the experience machine! Philosophical Psychology 27 (4): 513–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J.M., J. Alexander, C. Gonnerman, and S. Reuter. 2012. Restrictionism and reflection: Challenge deflected, or simply redirected? The Monist 95 (2): 200–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2002. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Mark Alfano, James Beebe, Wesley Buckwalter, Quassim Cassam, Florian Cova, Simon Cullen, Stefanie Kneer, Edouard Machery, Barry Maguire, Blake Myers-Schulz, Obioma Ofoego, Brian Robinson, David Rose, John Turri and three anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments. I am particularly grateful to Joshua Knobe and Brent Strickland for very helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus Kneer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kneer, M. Perspective and Epistemic State Ascriptions. Rev.Phil.Psych. 9, 313–341 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0361-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0361-4

Navigation