Skip to main content
Log in

Phenomenally Mine: In Search of the Subjective Character of Consciousness

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It’s a familiar fact that there is something it is like to see red, eat chocolate or feel pain. More recently philosophers have insisted that in addition to this objectual phenomenology there is something it is like for me to eat chocolate, and this for-me-ness is no less there than the chocolatishness. Recognizing this subjective feature of consciousness helps shape certain theories of consciousness, introspection and the self. Though it does this heavy philosophical work, and it is supposed to be relatively obvious to anyone who introspects, it is rather difficult to see just what this phenomenal me-ness is supposed to be; indeed, many philosophers deny it exists. In this paper we try to provide a clear sense of what phenomenal me-ness involves, and then then consider some arguments for the existence of phenomenal me-ness experience as well as some accounts of what gives rise to it. In the end, we argue that the plausible senses of me-ness are a good deal thinner than what often seems to be claimed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This phenomenal me-ness, or something like it, goes by many different names—for-me-ness, subjective character, phenomenal me-ness, experiential subjectivity, etc. For simplicity’s sake we stick with Phenomenal Me-ness, but we acknowledge—and indeed believe—that many different things are meant at different times.

  2. Kriegel (2009) p. 375 claims that this me-ness is not introspectible, though it is phenomenologically apparent. On some level we find this unintelligible, unless a particular model of introspection is presupposed. All we mean by introspection here is the way we know our own experiences and no-one else’s, and on that reading it is difficult to see how anything could be phenomenologically manifest that is not introspectible.

  3. We assume here that it would not make much sense to identify PM with a bare particular (that differs between Sally and Sally*), since its bareness would seem to rule out its making a phenomenal/qualitative contribution.

  4. And we note again that if someone wants to call one of these proposals phenomenal me-ness they should feel free. But the discussion will be advanced if authors make clear that they do not intend something that meets our conditions.

  5. Kriegel (2009)

  6. This seems to be the view of Williford (forthcoming a).

  7. We thank an anonymous referee for putting the view this way and forcing us to face it more squarely.

  8. This gets us into debates about the viability of the self-representational theory of consciousness that deserve (and have received) discussion beyond what we can give them here. See Kriegel and Williford (2006).

  9. It is worth noting that Sartre, averse as he is to positing non-conscious governors of our mental lives, will automatically assume that the irresistible impulse to self-ascribe conscious states is grounded in a conscious, phenomenologically salient feature of those states. Since almost no one nowadays shares (or should share, in any case) this aversion, we shouldn’t make his same assumptions. For an excellent discussion that develops the Sartrean view discussed here, see Williford (forthcoming b).

  10. For a thorough discussion of the varieties and approaches to them, see Gertler (2010).

  11. Not only does phenomenological reflection fail to support the unreflective PM theses, it also can’t support the singular PM theses. How could it establish that my me-ness is different from everyone else’s when I only have access to my own?

  12. We limit ourselves to the peculiarities of self-reference mentioned in Grünbaum (2012) as it is his argument we will consider, but one can easily imagine making a similar argument from the phenomenon of Immunity to Error through Misidentification (Shoemaker 1968). It should be clear to those familiar with that status that our response here would apply to that argument as well. See also Howell (2006) for other reasons to doubt that IEM would require something like PM.

  13. It should be noted that Grünbaum (2012) does not explicitly endorse our necessary conditions for PM. He does seem to intend his description of “minimal self-consciousness” to be an example of what we have called PM, and he cites a similar literature. In any case, his argument is still a strong and interesting contender for establishing what we are calling PM.

  14. This is a simplification of the argument made by (Grünbaum 2012: 275).

  15. See Perry (1979), (1990), (1997), (2001) and Crimmins and Perry (1989).

  16. Some theorists, for example Russell (1914); Peacocke (1983), (2014); Martens (1989), and Howell (2006) are explicit about accepting premise one, and others such as Castaneda et al. (1999), and O’Brien, Lucy (2007) seem sympathetic. Grünbaum supports his claims in Grünbaum, Thor (2012: 288–290)

  17. This objection applies to a related argument by Zahavi and Kriegel (forthcoming) in which they claim “One straightforward explanation of the intuitiveness of the claim that all conscious states are states we are aware of is that every conscious state has a for-me-ness built into its very phenomenal character.” Again, this just pushes the question back—why are we aware of this for-me-ness? It’s not clear how a phenomenal characteristic can explain consciousness if our awareness of it must itself be conscious.

  18. To be fair, Grünbaum’s argument isn’t trying to establish what we are calling PM. His own view seems to involve a “me-ish” mode of apprehending content, which would seem consistent with the anonymity of what is apprehended. We are, in fact, sympathetic with something like this view. See Howell (2006) for a view in this ballpark.

  19. Because they think “for-me-ness” accompanies all consciousness, Zahavi and Kriegel cannot use these cases of pathological consciousness to defend for-me-ness. They explicitly deny that these cases lack for-me-ness in Zahavi and Kriegel (forthcoming).

  20. Billon’s own proposal is that inserted thoughts are not phenomenally conscious. This proposal deserves further discussion, but it doesn’t seem to fit with the reports by patients who say things like “He treats my mind like a screen and flashes his thoughts onto it like you flash a picture.” (Mellor 1970: 10) It is worth mentioning, though, that those who tie PM to the existence of consciousness like Kriegel (2009) and others who are inclined towards self representational approaches to consciousness (Kriegel and Williford 2006) will have to adopt Billon’s extreme approach if they think thought insertion indicates a lack of PM.

  21. See, for example, Ellis et al. (1997); Hirstein and Ramachandran (1997), and Morris et al. (2008).

  22. For a discussion of various accounts of delusion and difficulties that beset them, see Bortolotti (2009).

  23. The locus classici for these sorts of views are Armstrong and David (1968); Lycan and William (1996) and Rosenthal (1986, 1993, 2005).

  24. O’Brien (2007) builds a sophisticated account of self-reference and basic self-knowledge around this idea.

  25. Indeed, the whole of Sartre’s most accessible work, The Transcendence of the Ego, could be read as a development of this basic picture.

  26. Block 2001. Schear 2009 suggests something similar in criticizing arguments by Zahavi 2005.

References

  • Albahari, Miri. 2010. Nirvana and Ownerless Consciousness. In In Self, No Self?: Perspectives From Analytical, Phenomenological, and Indian Traditions, ed. Siderits Mark. Oup Oxford: Evan Thompson, and Dan Zahavi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1975. “The First Person.” In Mind and Language, edited by Samuel D. Guttenplan, 45–65. Oxford University Press.

  • Armstrong, David M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge.

  • Bermudez, Jose Luis. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. MIT Press.

  • Billon, Alexandre. 2011. Does Consciousness Entail Subjectivity? The Puzzle of Thought Insertion. Philosophical Psychology 26(2): 291–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, Ned. 2001. Paradox and cross purposes in recent work on consciousness. Cognition 79(1–2): 197–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, Lisa. 2009. Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs. Oxford University Press.

  • Castaneda, H.N., J.G. Hart, and T. Kapitan. 1999. The Phenomeno-Logic of the I: Essays on Self-Consciousness. Indiana University Press.

  • Chisholm, Roderick. 1981. The First Person: An Essay on Reference and Intentionality. University of Minnesota Press.

  • Collins, Steven. 1982. Selfless Persons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crimmins, Mark, and John Perry. 1989. The Prince and the Phone Booth: Reporting Puzzling Beliefs. Journal of Philosophy 86(12): 685–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, Antonio R. 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. Putnam.

  • Damasio, Antonio R. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. Harcourt Brace and Co.

  • Davies, Martin, Max Coltheart, Robyn Langdon, and N. Breen. 2001. Monothematic Delusions: Towards a Two-Factor Account. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 8(2–3): 133–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. MIT Press.

  • Ellis, H.D., A.W. Young, A.H. Quayle, and K.W. DePauw. 1997. Reduced autonomic responses to faces in Capgras delusion. Proceedings of the Royal Society London Biological Sciences 264: 1085–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Gareth. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. 137. Oxford University Press.

  • Feit, Neil. 2008. Belief About the Self: A Defense of the Property Theory of Content. Oxford University Press.

  • Flanagan, Owen. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. MIT Press.

  • Frege, Gottlob. 1956. The Thought: A Logical Inquiry. MIND 65: 289–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C.D. 1992. The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2000. Self-reference and schizophrenia: a cognitive model of immunity to error through misidentification.” In Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-Experience, edited by Dan Zahavi, 203–39. John Benjamins.

  • Gerrans, Philip. 2002. A One-Stage Explanation of the Cotard Delusion. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 9(1): 47–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, Brie. 2010. Self-Knowledge. Routledge.

  • Gibson, James J. 1979. The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.

  • Graham, George. 2010. The disordered mind: an introduction to philosophy of mind and mental illness. Routledge.

  • Grünbaum, Thor. 2012. First Person and Minimal Self-Consciousness.” In Consciousness and Subjectivity, edited by Miguens and Preyer, 47–273. Ontos Verlag.

  • Harman, Gilbert. 1990. The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1982. The basic problems of phenomenology. Trans. Hofstadter, Albert. Indiana University Press: Bloomington.

  • Hill, Christopher S. 2009. Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hirstein, W., and V.S. Ramachandran. 1997. Cagras Syndrome: A novel probe for understanding the neural representation of the identity and familiarity of persons. Proceedings Biological Sciences 264: 437–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howell, Robert J. 2006. Self-Knowledge and Self-Reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72(1): 44–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howell, Robert J. 2013. Perception from the First-Person Perspective.” European Journal of Philosophy, 23 (4).

  • Hume, David. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford University Press.

  • Husserl, E. 1952. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution, Edited by M. Biemel. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff; English translation: Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Second Book. Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution, Translated by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989.

  • Kind, Amy. 2003. What’s so transparent about transparency? Philosophical Studies 115(3):225–244.

  • Kriegel, Uriah, and Kenneth Williford. 2006. Self-representational approaches to consciousness. MIT Press.

  • Kriegel, Uriah. 2009. _Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory_. Oxford University Press.

  • Levine, Joseph. 2001. Purple haze: the puzzle of conscious experience. Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, David. 1979. Attitudes de Dicto and de Se. Philosophical Review 88(4): 513–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, William G. 1996. Consciousness and experience. MIT Press.

  • Martens, David Brian. 1989. Some descriptional theories of first-person thoughts. Brown University Dissertation.

  • Mellor, C. 1970. First rank symptoms of schizophrenia: 1. The frequnncy in schizophrenics on admission to hospital; 2. Differences between individual first rank symptoms. British Journal of Psychiatry 117: 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1994. The Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1965. The Refutation of Idealism.” In Philosophical Studies, 1–30. Littlefield: Adams & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, A.L., A.M. Cleary, and M.L. Still. 2008. The role of autonomic arousal in feelings of familiarity. Conscoius Cognition 17: 1378–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, Lucy. 2007. Self-knowing agents. Oxford University Press.

  • Peacocke, Christopher. 1983. Sense and content: experience, thought, and their relations. Oxford University Press.

  • Peacocke, Christopher. 2014. The mirror of the world: subjects, consciousness, and self-consciousness. Oup Oxford.

  • Perry, J. 1979. The Essential Indexical. Noûs 13: 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, John. 1997. Indexicals and demonstratives.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, edited by Bob Hale and Crispin Wright, 486–612. Blackwell.

  • Perry, John. 2001. Knowledge, possibility, and consciousness. MIT Press.

  • Proust, Joelle. 2006. Agency in schizophrenics from a control theory viewpoint. In Disorders of volition, ed. W. Prinz and N. Sebanz, 87–118. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V.S. 2011. The Tell-Tale Brain: A Neuroscientist’s Quest for What Makes Us Human. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, David M. 1986. Two Concepts of Consciousness. Philosophical Studies 49: 329–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, David M. 2005. Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, David M. 1993. Explaining Consciousness.” In Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings, edited by David J. Chalmers, 406–21. Oup.

  • Rowlands, Mark. 2001. Consciousness and Higher-Order Thoughts. Mind and Language 16(3): 290–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1914/1971. On the nature of acquaintance,” in Robert Marsh (ed.) Logic and Knowledge. New York: Capricorn Books, 125–74.

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1957. The transcendence of the ego: an existentialist theory of consciousness. New York,Octagon Books.

  • Schear, Joseph. 2009. Experience and self-consciousness. Philosophical Studies 144: 95–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sydney. 1968. Self-Reference and Self-Awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65: 555–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sydney. 1996. The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge University Press.

  • Sierra, M. 2009. Depersonalization: a new look at a neglected syndrome. Cambridge Univ Press.

  • Stephens, G. Lynn, and George Graham. 2000. When self-consciousness breaks: alien voices and inserted thoughts. MIT Press.

  • Thompson, Brad. 2009. Senses for Senses. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87: 99–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, Michael. 2000. Consciousness, color, and content. MIT Press.

  • Williford, Ken. (forthcoming a). Representationalisms, Subjective Character and Self-Acquaintance. The MIND 20th Anniversary Collection. Eds. Metzinger, Thomas and Jennifer Windt.

  • Williford, Ken. (forthcoming b) Degrees of Self-Presence: Rehabilitating Sartre’s Accounts of Pre-Reflective Self-Consciousness and Reflection.

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. The blue and brown books. Harper and Row.

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: investigating the first-persom perspective. MIT Press.

  • Zahavi, Dan and Uriah Kriegel. (forthcoming). For Me-ness: what it is and what it is not.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert J. Howell.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Howell, R.J., Thompson, B. Phenomenally Mine: In Search of the Subjective Character of Consciousness. Rev.Phil.Psych. 8, 103–127 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-016-0309-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-016-0309-0

Keywords

Navigation