Skip to main content
Log in

Deep Brain Stimulation, Self and Relational Autonomy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Questions about the nature of self and self-consciousness are closely aligned with questions about the nature of autonomy. These concepts have deep roots in traditional philosophical discussions that concern metaphysics, epistemology and ethics. They also have direct relevance to practical considerations about informed consent in medical contexts. In this paper, with reference to understanding specific side effects of deep brain stimulation (DBS) treatment in cases of, for example, Parkinson’s Disease, Obsessive Compulsive Disorder, and Major Depressive Disorder, I’ll argue that it is best to frame discussions of informed consent in terms of relational autonomy and a pattern theory of self.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although Kyselo cites De Haan [70] in this respect, De Haan, even in arguing that the self is relational, does not deny its bodily nature or posit a tension between the bodily and the social character of the self.

  2. It is simply not the case that, “there is nothing social about the organismic or the moving body per se” ([66], [4]). Rather, as Marcel Mauss [71] suggested, “there is simply no such thing as a ‘natural’ way of walking that may be prescribed independently of the diverse circumstances in which human beings grow up and live their lives” (quoted in [72], 335).

  3. One of the reviewers asked me to flesh out this idea further especially in relation to the four dimensions of affordances that de Haan et al. [67] define (in Fig. 1), i.e., range, temporal proximity, salience, and affective allure. I’m suggesting that the relation between self-pattern and affordances is directly relevant to the question of autonomy – the greater number of affordances (i.e., range and temporal proximity) and the quality of the affordances (i.e., salience and affective allure) the more autonomy, which relates directly to one’s sense of agency. How this landscape of affordances might relate to the self-pattern more generally depends in some regard on the kinds of affordances in question. The four dimensions don’t specify whether the affordances are physical, social or cultural affordances, intellectual or cognitive affordances. So in part the question depends on how one categorizes affordances. Clearly, for example, social affordances (number and quality) will relate directly to the intersubjective aspect of the self-pattern. If, as the result of depression, my intersubjective relations shrink or become impoverished, both the number and the quality (especially affective allure) of my social affordances will decrease. Likewise, physical affordances will depend on my bodily condition (any particular condition may rule out some and create others); cultural affordances may depend on my prior history, as well as my learned values, which reflect extended and normative factors in the self-pattern. Cognitive affordances will relate directly to cognitive aspects of the self-pattern – my skills and capacities for memory, imagination, etc. We can complicate the story by considering that salience and affective allure cuts across any affordance in the same way that the affective aspect dynamically relates to all other aspects of the self-pattern.

References

  1. Schüpbach, M., M. Gargiulo, M.L. Welter, C. Mallet, C. Béhar, and J.L. Houeto. 2006. Neurosurgery in Parkinson disease: A distressed mind in a repaired body? Neurology 66: 1811–1816. https://doi.org/10.1212/01.wnl.0000234880.51322.16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Agid, Y., M. Schüpbach, M. Gargiulo, et al. 2006. Neurosurgery in Parkinson’s disease: The doctor is happy, the patient less so? In Parkinson’s disease and related disorders, 409–414. Vienna: Springer.

  3. Christen, M., M. Bittlinger, H. Walter, P. Brugger, and S. Müller. 2012. Dealing with side effects of deep brain stimulation: Lessons learned from stimulating the STN. American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 3 (1): 37–43.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Appleby, B.S., P.S. Duggan, A. Regenberg, and P.V. Rabins. 2007. Psychiatric and neuropsychiatric adverse events associated with deep brain stimulation: A meta-analysis of ten years' experience. Movement Disorders 22 (12): 1722–1728. https://doi.org/10.1002/mds.21551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bronstein, J.M., M. Tagliati, R.L. Alterman, et al. 2011. Deep brain stimulation for Parkinson disease: An expert consensus and review of key issues. Archives of Neurology 68 (2): 165–165. https://doi.org/10.1001/archneurol.2010.260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Burdick, A.P., K.D. Foote, S. Wu, D. Bowers, P. Zeilman, C.E. Jacobson, H.E. Ward, and M.S. Okun. 2011. Do patient's get angrier following STN, GPi, and thalamic deep brain stimulation. NeuroImage 54: S227–S232.

    Google Scholar 

  7. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2015. Effects of deep brain stimulation on the lived experience of obsessive-compulsive disorder patients: In-depth interviews with 18 patients. PLoS One 10 (8): e0135524. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0135524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. de Koning, P.P., M. Figee, P. Van den Munckhof, R. Schuurman, and D. Denys. 2011. Current status of deep brain stimulation for obsessive-compulsive disorder: A clinical review of different targets. Current Psychiatry Reports 13 (4): 274–282. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11920-011-0200-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Denys, D., M. Mantione, M. Figee, P. van den Munckhof, F. Koerselman, H. Westenberg, A. Bosch, and R. Schuurman. 2010. Deep brain stimulation of the nucleus accumbens for treatment-refractory obsessive-compulsive disorder. Archives of General Psychiatry 67 (10): 1061–1068. https://doi.org/10.1001/archgenpsychiatry.2010.122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Goodman, W.K., and R.L. Alterman. 2012. Deep brain stimulation for intractable psychiatric disorders. Annual Review of Medicine 63: 511–524. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-med-052209-100401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Morishita, T., S.M. Fayad, M.A. Higuchi, K.A. Nestor, and K.D. Foote. 2014. Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant depression: Systematic review of clinical outcomes. Neurotherapeutics 11 (3): 475–484. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13311-014-0282-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Müller, S., and M. Christen. 2011. Deep brain stimulation in parkinsonian patients—Ethical evaluation of cognitive, affective, and behavioral sequelae. American Journal of Behavioral Neuroscience 2 (1): 3–13.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Okun, M.S., G. Mann, K.D. Foote, et al. 2007. Deep brain stimulation in the internal capsule and nucleus accumbens region: Responses observed during active and sham programming. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry 78 (3): 310–314. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp.2006.095315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Okun, M.S., B.V. Gallo, G. Mandybur, et al. 2012. Subthalamic deep brain stimulation with a constant-current device in Parkinson's disease: An open-label randomised controlled trial. The Lancet Neurology 11 (2): 140–149. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1474-4422(11)70308-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Synofzik, M. 2013. Functional neurosurgery and deep brain stimulation. In Neuroethics in practice, ed. A. Chatterjee and M.J. Farah, 189–208. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Alonso, P., D. Cuadras, L. Gabriels, et al. 2015. Deep brain stimulation for obsessive-compulsive disorder: A meta-analysis of treatment outcome and predictors of response. PLoS One 10 (7): e0133591.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Greenberg, B., D. Malone, G. Friehs, et al. 2006. Three-year outcomes in deep brain stimulation for highly resistant obsessive–compulsive disorder. Neuropsychopharmacology 31: 2384–2393. https://doi.org/10.1038/sj.npp.1301165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Ooms, P., M. Mantione, M. Figee, et al. 2014. Deep brain stimulation for obsessive-compulsive disorders: Long-term analysis of quality of life. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry 85: 153–158. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp-2012-302550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Baylis, F. 2013. ‘I am who I am’: On the perceived threats to personal identity from deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics 6: 513–526. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9137-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Glannon, W. 2009. Stimulating brains, altering minds. Journal of Medical Ethics 35: 289–292. https://doi.org/10.1136/jme.2008.027789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Kraemer, F. 2013. Me, myself and my brain implant: Deep brain stimulation raises questions of personal authenticity and alienation. Neuroethics 6: 483–497. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9115-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Schermer, M. 2009. Changes in the self: The need for conceptual research next to empirical research. The American Journal of Bioethics 9 (5): 45–47 doi.org/10.1080/15265160902788744.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Witt, K., J. Kuhn, L. Timmermann, M. Zurowski, and C. Woopen. 2013. Deep brain stimulation and the search for identity. Neuroethics 6: 499–511. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9100-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Klaming, L., and P. Haselager. 2013. Did my brain implant make me do it? Questions raised by DBS regarding psychological continuity, responsibility for action and mental competence. Neuroethics 6: 527–539. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9093-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Leentjens, A.F.G., V. Visser-vandewalle, Y. Temel, and F.R.J. Verhey. 2004. Manipuleerbare wilsbekwaamheid: Een ethisch probleem bij elektrostimulatie van de nucleus subthalamicus voor ernstige ziekte van Parkinson. [Manipulation of mental competence: An ethical problem in case of electrical stimulation of the subthalamic nucleus for severe Parkinson's disease]. Nederlands Tijdschrift Geneeskunde 148 (28): 1394–1398.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Johansson, V., M. Garwicz, M. Kanje, L. Halldenius, and J. Schouenborg. 2014. Thinking ahead on deep brain stimulation: An analysis of the ethical implications of a developing technology. AJOB Neuroscience 5 (1): 24–33. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2013.863243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. De Ridder, D., S. Vanneste, G. Gillett, P. Manning, P. Glue, and B. Langguth. 2016. Psychosurgery reduces uncertainty and increases free will? A review. Neuromodulation 19: 239–248. https://doi.org/10.1111/ner.12405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Mathews, D.J. 2011. Deep brain stimulation, personal identity and policy. International Review of Psychiatry 23 (5): 486–492. https://doi.org/10.3109/09540261.2011.632624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Christman, J. 2018. Autonomy in moral and political philosophy. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E. N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/autonomy-moral/.

  30. Beahrs, J.O., and T.G. Gutheil. 2001. Informed consent in psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychiatry 158 (1): 4–10.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Billings, J.A., and E.L. Krakauer. 2011. On patient autonomy and physician responsibility in end-of-life care. Archives of Internal Medicine 171 (9): 49–853. https://doi.org/10.1001/archinternmed.2011.180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Browner, C.H. 1995. Risk, autonomy, and responsibility: Informed consent for prenatal testing. The Hastings Center Report 25 (3): S9–S12. https://doi.org/10.2307/3562123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Jones, C.J. 1990. Autonomy and informed consent in medical decision-making: Toward a new self-fulfilling prophecy. Washington & Lee Law Rev 47: 379.

    Google Scholar 

  34. King, J.S., and B.W. Moulton. 2006. Rethinking informed consent: The case for shared medical decision-making. American Journal of Law & Medicine 32 (4): 429–501.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Levy, N. 2012. Autonomy, responsibility and the oscillation of preference. In Addiction Neuroethics: The promises and perils of neuroscience research on addiction, ed. A. Carter and W. Hall, 139–151. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Tauber, A.I. 2005. Patient autonomy and the ethics of responsibility. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Metzinger, T. 2004. Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Dennett, D.C. 1991. Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co..

    Google Scholar 

  39. Synofzik, M., and T.E. Schlaepfer. 2008. Stimulating personality: Ethical criteria for deep brain stimulation in psychiatric patients and for enhancement purposes. Biotechnological Journal 3: 1511–1520.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Schechtman, M. 2010. Philosophical reflections on narrative and deep brain stimulation. The Journal of Clinical Ethics 21 (2): 133–139.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Müller, O., U. Bittner, and H. Krug. 2010. Narrative Identität bei Therapie mit ‘Hirnschrittmacher. Ethik in der Medizin 22 (4): 303–315.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Schermer, M. 2011. Ethical issues in deep brain stimulation. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 1–5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnint.2011.00017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Goddard, E. 2017. Deep brain stimulation through the “lens of agency”: Clarifying threats to personal identity from neurological intervention. Neuroethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-016-9297-0.

  44. Lipsman, N.I.R., and W. Glannon. 2013. Brain, mind and machine: What are the implications of deep brain stimulation for perceptions of personal identity, agency and free will? Bioethics 27 (9): 465–470. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2012.01978.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2013. The phenomenology of deep brain stimulation–induced changes in OCD: An enactive affordance-based model. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7: 653. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Dings, R., and L. de Bruin. 2016. Situating the self: Understanding the effects of deep brain stimulation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (2): 151–165.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Gallagher, S. 2013. A pattern theory of self. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7 (443): 1–7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Gallagher, S. 2012. Multiple aspects of agency. New Ideas in Psychology 30: 15–31.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Rochat, P. 2011. What is it like to be a newborn? In The Oxford handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 357–379. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Newen, A., A. Welpinghus, and G. Juckel. 2015. Emotion recognition as pattern recognition: The relevance of perception. Mind and Language 30 (2): 187–208.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Mead, G.H. 1913. The social self. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 10 (14): 374–380.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Gallup, G.G., J.R. Anderson, and S.M. Platek. 2011. Self-recognition. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher, 80–110. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Gallese, V. 2014. Bodily selves in relation: Embodied simulation as second-person perspective on intersubjectivity. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 369 (1644): 20130177. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2013.0177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Shoemaker, S. 2011. On what we are. In The Oxford handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 352–371. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Frankfurt, H.G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Schechtman, M. 2011. The narrative self. In The Oxford handbook of the self, ed. S. Gallagher, 394–417. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  58. James, W. 1890. Principles of psychology. Vol. 2. New York: Basic Books 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Hutto, D., and S. Gallagher. 2017. Re-authoring narrative therapy: Opening the way for future developments. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 24 (2): 157–167.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Gallagher, S. 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (1): 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Bramley, N., and V. Eatough. 2005. The experience of living with Parkinson's disease: An interpretative phenomenological analysis case study. Psychology & Health 20 (2): 223–235.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Moore, J.W., S.A. Schneider, P. Schwingenschuh, G. Moretto, K.P. Bhatia, and P. Haggard. 2010. Dopaminergic medication boosts action–effect binding in Parkinson's disease. Neuropsychologia 48 (4): 1125–1132.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Slaby, J., A. Paskaleva, and A. Stephan. 2013. Enactive emotion and impaired agency in depression. Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (7–8): 33–55.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Gentsch, A., S. Schütz-Bosbach, T. Endrass, and N. Kathmann. 2012. Dysfunctional forward model mechanisms and aberrant sense of agency in obsessive-compulsive disorder. Biological Psychiatry 71 (7): 652–659.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Oren, E., N. Friedmann, and R. Dar. 2016. Things happen: Individuals with high obsessive-compulsive tendencies omit agency in their spoken language. Consciousness and Cognition 42: 125–134. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.03.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Kyselo, M. 2014. The body social: An enactive approach to the self. Frontiers in Psychology 5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00986.

  67. de Haan, S., E. Rietveld, M. Stokhof, and D. Denys. 2017. Becoming more oneself? Changes in personality following DBS treatment for psychiatric disorders: Experiences of OCD patients and general considerations. PLoS One 12 (4): e0175748.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Frith, C., and S. Gallagher. 2002. Models of the pathological mind: An interview with Christopher Frith. Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (4): 57–80.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Fingelkurts, A.A., and A.A. Fingelkurts. 2017. Three-dimensional components of selfhood in treatment-naive patients with major depressive disorder: A resting-state qEEG imaging study. Neuropsychologia 99: 30–36.

    Google Scholar 

  70. de Haan, S. 2010. Comment: The minimal self is a social self. In The embodied self, ed. T. Fuchs, H.C. Sattel, and P. Henningsen, 12–17. Stuttgart: Schattauer.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Mauss, M. 1979. Sociology and psychology: Essays. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ingold, T. 2004. Culture on the ground: The world perceived through the feet. Journal of Material Culture 9 (3): 315–340.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Gallagher, S. 2017. The struggle for recognition and the return of primary intersubjectivity. In Phenomenology and the primacy of the political, ed. V. Fóti and P. Kontos, 3–14. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  74. De Jaegher, H., E. Di Paolo, and S. Gallagher. 2010. Does social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (10): 441–447.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Velleman, J.D. 2007. Self to self: Selected essays. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Velleman, J.D. 2005. Self as narrator. In Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism: New essays, ed. J. Christman and J. Anderson, 56–76. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Bruner, J.S. 1996. The culture of education. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Bruner, J.S. 1990. Acts of meaning. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Nelson, K. 2003. Narrative and the emergence of a consciousness of self. In Narrative and consciousness, ed. G.D. Fireman, T.E.J. McVay, and O. Flanagan, 17–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Reddy, V. 2008. How infants know minds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Reddy, V. 2012. Moving others matters. In Moving ourselves, moving others: Motion and emotion in intersubjectivity, consciousness and language, ed. A. Foolen, U.M. Lüdtke, T.P. Racine, and J. Zlatev, 139–163. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Trevarthen, C. 2013. Born for art, and the joyful companionship of fiction. In Evolution, early experience and human development: From research to practice and policy, ed. D. Narvaez, J. Panksepp, A. Schore, and T. Gleason, 202–218. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Christman, J. 2004. Relational autonomy, liberal individualism, and the social constitution of selves. Philosophical Studies 117 (1): 143–164.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Christman, J. 2009. The politics of persons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Mackenzie, C., and N. Stoljar. 2000. Introduction: Autonomy refigured. In Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on automony, agency, and the social self, ed. C. Mackenzie and N. Stoljar, 3–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Frank, M.J., J. Samanta, A.A. Moustafa, and S.J. Sherman. 2007. Hold your horses: Impulsivity, deep brain stimulation, and medication in parkinsonism. Science 318: 1309–1312.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Chatterjee, A., and M.J. Farah, eds. 2013. Neuroethics in practice: Medicine, mind and society. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Fins, J.J. 2015. Rights come to mind: Brain injury, ethics, and the struggle for consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Gallagher, S. 2007. Moral agency, self-consciousness, and practical wisdom. Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (5-6): 199-223.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author thanks the Humboldt Foundation’s Anneliese Maier Research Award (2012-18) for support of this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shaun Gallagher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gallagher, S. Deep Brain Stimulation, Self and Relational Autonomy. Neuroethics 14, 31–43 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9355-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9355-x

Keywords

Navigation