Skip to main content
Log in

Musical Types and Musical Flexibility

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A central motivation for the type-token model of music works is its ability to explain musical multiplicity—the fact that musical works are capable of having multiple performances through which they can be experienced and which cannot be individually identified with the works themselves. The type-token model explains multiplicity by identifying musical works with structural types and taking performances to be tokens of those types. In this paper, I argue that musical works are flexible in ways which permit performances which are tokens of distinct structural types to be performances of the same musical work. And I argue that various attempts to reconcile the type-token model with musical flexibility are ultimately unsuccessful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There may also be other physical objects in which a work is in some sense “embodied” but through which the work cannot be experienced. For example, although a musical work may be embodied in (a copy of) a musical score, most of us at least cannot experience the work by means of reading the score.

  2. Musical multiplicity, as formulated, presupposes the identification of musical works with musical compositions. In certain genres, however, this presupposition is contentious. It has been argued, for example, that in rock music works should instead be identified with recordings (Kania, 2006); and it has been argued that in jazz they should be identified with performances (Alperson, 1984). And, if this is right, even if jazz and rock compositions are multiple in the relevant sense, jazz and rock works might not be. Nevertheless, in this paper, I will follow the convention of formulating the issue in terms of works.

  3. It is worth noting, however, that Friedell (2018) defends an account of musical flexibility according to which musical works can undergo change only in their extrinsic properties.

  4. It is, of course, true that some performances might be considered aesthetically inferior to others. But it does not follow from the fact that a performance is aesthetically flawed in some respect that it is incorrect in the sense of being an improperly formed instance of a musical work.

  5. One might object that as long as the duration during which a particular structural type is the value of the function in question is long enough, the type-token relation can contribute to the explanation of musical multiplicity even if it cannot provide a complete explanation of the phenomenon. This seems right, but it is worth noting that the view that musical works are functions from times to structural types still runs afoul of performance flexibility.

  6. This objection is due to an anonymous referee for Acta Analytica.

  7. Strictly speaking, Dodd’s concern here is with the temporal flexibility rather than performance flexibility, but presumably his response would be the same.

  8. This suggestion comes from an anonymous referee for Acta Analytica.

  9. For more substantial discussions of the type-token model and musical audibility see Davies (2009) and Alward (2020).

  10. As should be clear, this counts as a variant of the continuant-stage model discussed above. As a result, one might identify musical works themselves with fusions or networks of appropriately related performances, or perhaps, take them to be higher-order entities dependent on but distinct from such performances.

  11. See Alward (2020) for a more fully developed version of this view.

References

  • Abraham, G. (1979). The concise Oxford history of music. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alperson, P. (1984). On musical improvisation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 43(1), 17–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alward, P. (2004). The spoken work. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(4), 331–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alward, P. (2020). Multiplicity, Audibility, and Musical Continuity. Dialogue 59 (1):101–21.

  • Caplan, B., & Matheson, C. (2006). Defending musical perdurantism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 46, 59–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, D. (2004). Art as performance. Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, D. (2009). Dodd on the ‘audibility’ of musical works. British Journal of Aesthetics, 49(2), 98–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, S. (2003). Ontology of art. In J. Levinson (Ed.), Oxford Companion to Aesthetics (pp. 155–180). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2002). Defending musical platonism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 42, 380–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2004). Types, continuants, and the ontology of music. British Journal of Aesthetics, 44, 342–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2007). Works of music: An essay in ontology. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, J. (2008). Musical works: Ontology and meta-ontology. Philosophy Compass, 3(6), 1113–1134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1978). Can there be vague objects? Analysis, 38(4), 208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evnine, S. (2009). Constitution and qua objects in the ontology of music. British Journal of Aesthetics, 49(3), 203–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedell, D. (2018). Why can’t I change Bruckner’s Eighth Symphony? Philosophical Studies, 177, 805–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goehr, L. (1994). The imaginary museum of musical works. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kania, A. (2006). Making tracks: The ontology of rock music. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 64(4), 401–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, P. (1983). Platonism in music: A kind of defense. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 19, 109–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (1980). What a musical work is. The Journal of Philosophy, 77, 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moruzzi, C. (2018). Every performance is a stage: Musical stage theory as a novel account for the ontology of musical works. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 76(3), 341–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohrbaugh, G. (2003). Artworks as historical individuals. European Journal of Philosophy, 11, 177–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1998). Nonexistence. Nous, 32(3), 277–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tillman, C. (2011). Musical materialism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 51, 13–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Alward.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alward, P. Musical Types and Musical Flexibility. Acta Anal 38, 355–369 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00518-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00518-z

Keywords

Navigation