Skip to main content
Log in

Innate Mind Need Not Be Within

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is a widely accepted thesis in the cognitive sciences and in naturalistic philosophy of mind that the contents of at least some mental representations are innate. A question that has popped up in discussions concerning innate mental representations is this. Are externalist theories of mental content applicable to the content of innate representations? Views on the matter vary and sometimes conflict. To date, there has been no comprehensive assessment of the relationship between content externalism and content innateness. The aim of this paper is to provide such an assessment. I focus on the notions of innateness that are employed in innateness hypotheses within the cognitive sciences and adjacent fields of philosophy, and on causal externalist theories of content. I distinguish between three accounts of what being innate might amount to in innateness hypotheses within the cognitive sciences, and between three types of causal externalism. I explain what the possibility of innate externalistically individuated representations depends upon given all nine combinations. I explain why causal externalism can be true of innate mental representations, given but one of these combinations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Following the tradition, I use capital letters to denote representations.

  2. Pitt also argues that if externalism cannot be true of innate representations, then it cannot be true of any representations. He thus sees well-evidenced empirical nativist hypotheses about representational content as evidence against content externalism tout court.

  3. Existing discussions that have touched upon the relationship between representational nativism and content externalism have also focused on causal externalist theories. In addition, Rupert (2009) discusses the relationship between psychological nativism and extended, embedded, and enactivist accounts of representational states.

  4. My discussion is indifferent to what constitutes these symbols, i.e., the vehicles of representational content.

  5. There is some ambiguity in philosophical and psychological discussions regarding what precisely would have to be possessed in order to possess a representation (see Rey 2014). The discussion at hand is compatible with different ways of disambiguating this.

  6. According to one popular approach, R is acquired psychologically if, in the current psychological sciences, there is no correct theory that can explain how R is acquired (e.g., Samuels 2002). On this epistemic reading, the predicate “is innate” merely marks the explanatory limits of the current psychological science. As such, it would have no direct metaphysical implications. Therefore, in this paper, P-innateness interests us only given that there is some motivated substantive interpretation of “psychological”.

  7. Sometimes psychological acquisition and learning qua hypothesis testing are treated as synonyms and, consequently, being innate and not being learned by hypothesis testing are treated as synonyms. For example, Fodor’s (1975, 1981) paradigm-shaping thesis that most lexical concepts are innate boils down to the thesis that most lexical concepts cannot be acquired through learning qua hypothesis testing.

  8. Susan Carey, a leading figure in nativist debates, vacillates between P-innateness and D-innateness. Sometimes she says that a representation is innate if it is not learned (e.g., Carey (2009), p.11), and in other places, that a representation is innate if it is not acquired by a domain-general learning mechanism (e.g., Carey (2011), p.115, footnote 7).

  9. For instance, conceding to considerations like these, Fodor (2008) is willing to backlau away from his earlier identification of innateness with not being learned (2008, e.g., p. 147).

  10. I use “environmental stimulus” to denote any such feature of an environment that has causally impact on an organism.

  11. What “extrinsic” amounts to in the context of content externalism is a point of disagreement (see e.g., Farkas 2003; Gertler 2012). Here I will assume that the border between what is intrinsic and what is extrinsic coincides with the skin of the organism.

  12. Sustaining mechanisms could also be embedded in an organism’s physical or social environment (e.g., Rupert 2001, p. 29, footnote 7). On different sustaining mechanisms: (Cowie 1999, pp. 132–135; Fodor 2008, pp. 142–143; Margolis 1998, pp. 256–259; Sarnecki 2006).

  13. Sterelny (1989) thinks that these considerations show that Fodor’s view that all concepts are innate is not compatible with his causal externalism about conceptual content. However, so reasoning, Sterelny wrongly assumes that Fodor is committed to AE, the view that the content of a concept is individuated by what causes its acquisition. Fodor does not support AE but, instead, NCE (Fodor 1987, 1990). And according to NCE, what causes an organism to acquire a concept is not what individuates its content. Thus, whether a brute-causal mechanism of concept acquisition is capable of fixing the content of a concept is beside the point regarding whether Fodor’s commitment to externalism is compatible with his commitment to radical concept nativism. Cowie (1999, pp. 116-120) discusses Sterelny’s equivocation between AE and NCE in more detail.

  14. Cowie overlooks this distinction, and thus the distinction between HCE and AE, when she argues that representational nativism is incompatible with all historical theories of content, i.e., theories according to which the content of representations depends upon actual past causal interaction with the environment (Cowie 1999, p. 120).

  15. Usher’s (2001) statistical account of reference and the historical asymmetric dependence theory discussed by Fodor (1990) would also serve as examples.

  16. Indeed, Dretske reserves a different account of content for innate qua unlearned representations.

References

  • Adamson, N. (2001) Concepts and nativism. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal.

  • Atran, S., & Medin, D. (2008). The native mind and the cultural construction of nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, H. C., & Broesch, J. (2012). Prepared social learning about dangerous animals in children. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33(5), 499–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2009). Irretrievably confused? Innateness in explanatory context. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40(4), 296–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2011). Précis of the origin of concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(3), 113–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowie, F. (1999). What’s within? Nativism reconsidered. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1997). The lot of the causal theory of mental content. Journal of Philosophy, 94(10), 535–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M., & Sterelny, K. (1987). Language and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of language. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, R., & Carey, S. (1986). Why faces are and are not special: an effect of expertise. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 115(2), 107–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2003). What is externalism? Philosophical Studies, 112(3), 187–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Representations (pp. 257–316). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: the problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990). A theory of content II. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2008). Lot 2: the language of thought revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (2000). The replacement of general-purpose learning models with adaptively specialized learning modules. In M. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The new cognitive neurosciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. (2012). Understanding the internalism-externalism debate: what is the boundary of the thinker? Philosophical Perspectives, 26, 51–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. (2002). What is innateness? The Monist, 85(1), 70–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind & Language, 24(5), 605–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, S., & Rey, G. (2012). Innateness. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. R. (1996). The role of contrast in causal and explanatory claims. Synthese, 107, 395–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. (2002). Nature and nurture in cognition. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53(2), 251–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2007). Innate cognitive capacities. Mind & Language, 22(1), 92–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, J. & Deutsch, M. (2019). Externalism about mental content. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/content-externalism/>.Accessed 7 July 2020.

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts and cognitive science. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (Eds.), Concepts: core readings (pp. 3–81). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linquist, S. (2018). The conceptual critique of innateness. Philosophy Compass, 13, e12492. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (1991). Can we explain intentionality? In G. Rey & B. Loewer (Eds.), Meaning in mind (pp. 119–136). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. C. (1994). Content: covariation, control and contingency. Synthese, 100(2), 241–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M., & Bateson, P. (2006). Innateness and the sciences. Biology and Philosophy, 21(2), 155–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. Mind & Language, 13(3), 347–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2011). Learning matters: the role of learning in concept acquisition. Mind & Language, 26(5), 507–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2013). In defense of nativism. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 693–718.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northcott, R. (2008). Causation and contrast classes. Philosophical Studies, 139, 111–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northcott, R. (2012). Genetic traits and causal explanation. In K. Plaisance & T. Reydon (Eds.), Philosophy of behavioral biology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 282 (pp. 65–82). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northcott, R., & Piccinini, G. (2018). Conceived this way: innateness defended. Philosopher’s Imprint, 18(18).

  • O’Neill, E. (2015). Relativizing innateness: innateness as the insensitivity of the appearance of a trait with respect to specified environmental variation. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 211–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2000). Nativism and the theory of content. ProtoSociology, 14, 222–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Furnishing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (2014). Innate and learned: Carey, mad dog nativism, and the poverty of stimuli and analogies (yet again). Mind & Language, 29(2), 109–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (1999). The best test theory of extension: first principle(S). Mind & Language, 14(3), 321–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2001). Coining terms in the language of thought. Journal of Philosophy, 98(10), 499–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2009). Innateness and the situated mind. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 96–116). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, D. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: a theory of mental representation. Mind & Language, 19(2), 211–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind & Language, 17(3), 233–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarnecki, J. (2006). Retracing our steps: Fodor’s new old way with concept acquisition. Acta Analytica, 21(40), 41–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2011). Acquiring a new concept is not explicable-by-content. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(3), 148–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14(1), 29–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1989). Fodor’s nativism. Philosophical Studies, 55(2), 119–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Usher, M. (2001). A statistical referential theory of content: using information theory to account for misrepresentation. Mind & Language, 16(3), 331–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Ofxord University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by the Estonian Ministry of Education and Research (Funder ID: https://doi.org/10.13039/501100003510, Projects PRG462 “Philosophical analysis of interdisciplinary research practices”, IUT20-5 “Disagreements: Philosophical Analysis“), and the Estonian Research Competency Council (Funder ID: https://doi.org/10.13039/501100005189, Grant Number: SHVHV16145T (TK145) “Centre of Excellence in Estonia”).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Riin Kõiv.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that she has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kõiv, R. Innate Mind Need Not Be Within. Acta Anal 36, 101–121 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-020-00441-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-020-00441-1

Navigation