Skip to main content
Log in

Two-dimensionalism and the “Knowing Which” Requirement

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Two-dimensional semantics aims to eliminate the puzzle of necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori truths. Recently many argue that even assuming two-dimensional semantics we are left with the puzzle of necessary and a posteriori propositions. Stephen Yablo (Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 81, 98–122, 2000) and Penelope Mackie (Analysis, 62(3), 225–236, 2002) argue that a plausible sense of “knowing which” lets us know the object of such a proposition, and yet its necessity is “hidden” and thus a posteriori. This paper answers this objection; I argue that given two-dimensional semantics you cannot know a necessary proposition without knowing that it is true.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kripke’s argument is in his (1980). Pavel Tichy suggests this figurative way of dissolving the puzzle (1983). Other versions of the solution are found in Davies and Humberstone (1980), Chalmers (1996), and Jackson (1998).

  2. Davies and Humberstone (1980: 10, 20), Stalnaker (2001), Baldwin (2001).

  3. The bearers of the properties of necessity/contingency and a priority/a posteriority are primarily propositions, and only derivatively – the sentences that express them.

  4. Evans (1982), McDowell (1984), and Wiggins (2001), accept that requirement.

  5. The use of “water” there is similar to our use of “Jade,” though much more heterogeneous.

  6. There are two other strategies: The failure of transmission (Davies 2000), and the denial that the conclusion is puzzling. I believe, though, that these strategies are criticized successfully. For such criticism see Brewer 2000.

  7. The puzzle threatens anyone who rejects the cognitive requirement. If knowing which thing water is affects one's cognitive standing, as follows from the cognitive requirement, then Sally does not know the C-proposition by reflection alone. To know her own thoughts, she needs to grasp their content, and to do that she must reflect on her environment. This does not mean that Sally needs a basis for her knowledge of her thoughts; but it does mean that the very idea of grasping an externalist thought depends also on reflection on the world.

References

  • Baldwin, T. (2001). On considering a possible world as actual. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl., 75, 157–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2000). Externalism and a priori knowledge of empirical facts. In P. Boghossian, & C. Peacocke (Eds.) New essays on the a priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2004). Anti-individualism and knowledge. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). On sense and intension. Philosophical Perspectives, 16.

  • Davies, M. (2000). Externalism and a priori knowledge. In P. Boghossian, & C. Peacocke (Eds.) New essays on the a priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., & Humberstone, L. (1980). Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies, 38, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes for Kaplan. Oxford University Press, 1989.

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, P. (2002). Deep contingency and necessary a posteriori truth. Analysis, 62(3), 225–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1984). De re senses. In Meaning, knowledge, and reality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Pryor, J. (2007). Externalism about content and McKinsey-style reasoning. In S. Goldberg (Ed.) Internalism and externalism in semantics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning.”. In H. Putnam (Ed.) Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (vol. II (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2001). On considering a possible world as actual. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl., 75, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichy, P. (1983). Kripke on necessity a posteriori. Philosophical Studies, 43, 225–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1999). Self-knowledge and semantic luck: What the externalist can know a priori. In Philosophical Issues, 9, 219–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2000). Textbook Kripkeanism and the open texture of concepts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 814, 98–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (2001). Sameness and substance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hagit Benbaji.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Benbaji, H. Two-dimensionalism and the “Knowing Which” Requirement. Acta Anal 23, 55–67 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-008-0022-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-008-0022-4

Keywords

Navigation