Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Is War in Our Nature?

What Is Right and What Is Wrong about the Seville Statement on Violence

  • Published:
Human Nature Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Seville Statement on Violence rejected the view that violence and war were in any way rooted in human nature and proclaimed that they were merely a cultural artifact. This paper points out both the valid and invalid parts of the statement. It concludes that the potential for both war and peace is embedded in us. The human behavioral toolkit comprises a number of major tools, respectively geared for violent conflict, peaceful competition, or cooperation, depending on people’s assessment of what will serve them best in any given circumstance. Conflict is only one tool—the hammer—in our diverse behavioral toolkit. However, all three behavioral strategies are not purely learned cultural forms. This naive nature/nurture dichotomy overlooks the heavy and complex biological machinery that is necessary for the working of each of them and the interplay between them. They are all very close under our skin and readily activated because they have all been very handy during our long evolutionary past. At the same time, they are variably calibrated to particular conditions through social learning, which means that their relative use may fluctuate widely. Thus, state authority has tilted the menu of human choices in the direction of the peaceful options in the domestic arena, and changing economic, social, and political conditions may be generating a similar effect in the international arena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This article was originally the keynote address for the 2017 WESIPS Conference.

  2. The former error seems to be the motivation for Fry’s works. Unfortunately, the latter position is at least implied by leading evolutionist biologist E. O. Wilson (2012).

  3. These statistics agree remarkably with Ember’s earlier survey of hunter-gatherers (1978).

References

  • Ardrey, R. (1966). The territorial imperative: A personal inquiry into the animal origins of property and nations. New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beroldi, G. (1994). Critique of the Seville statement on violence. American Psychologist, 49(10), 847–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, C. (2013). The biocultural evolution of conflict resolution between groups. In D. Fry (Ed.), War, peace, and human nature: The convergence of evolutionary and cultural views (pp. 315–340). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burch, E. (2005). Alliance and conflict: The world system of the Inupiaq Eskimos. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ember, C. (1978). Myths about hunter-gatherers. Ethnology, 17, 439–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1920). Beyond the pleasure principle. (Reprinted in The complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, 1953–1974, London: Hogarth, vol. 18, pp. 7–64.)

  • Freud, S. (1923). The ego and the id. (Reprinted in The complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, 1953–1974, London: Hogarth, vol. 19, pp. 12–66.)

  • Freud, S. (1930). Civilization and its discontents. (Reprinted in The complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, 1953–1974, London: Hogarth, vol. 21, pp. 57–45.)

  • Freud, S. (1933a). New introductory lectures on psychoanalysis. (Reprinted in The complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, 1953–1974, London: Hogarth, vol. 22, pp. 5–182.)

  • Freud, S. (1933b). Why war? (Reprinted in The complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, 1953–1974, London: Hogarth, vol. 22, pp. 203–215.)

  • Fry, D. (2006). The human potential for peace. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fry, D. (Ed.). (2013). War, peace, and human nature: The convergence of evolutionary and cultural views. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fry, D., & Söderberg, P. (2013). Lethal aggression in mobile forager bands and implications for the origins of war. Science, 341, 270–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gat, A. (1999). The pattern of fighting in simple, small-scale, pre-state societies. Journal of Anthropological Research, 55, 563–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gat, A. (2000). The human motivational complex: Evolutionary theory and the causes of hunter-gatherer fighting. Anthropological Quarterly, 73(1), 20–34; 73(2), 74–88; 73(3), 165–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gat, A. (2006). War in human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gat, A. (2015). Proving communal warfare among hunter-gatherers: The quasi-Rousseauan error. Evolutionary Anthropology, 24, 111–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gat, A. (2017). The causes of war and the spread of peace: But will war rebound? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, J. (2011). Winning the war on war: The decline of armed conflict worldwide. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guilaine, J., & Zammit, J. (2005). The origins of war: Violence in prehistory. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keely, L. (1996). War before civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, R. (2013). From the peaceful to the warlike: Ethnographic and archaeological insights into hunter-gatherer warfare and homicide. In D. Fry (Ed.), War, peace, and human nature: The convergence of evolutionary and cultural views (pp. 151–167). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • LeBlanc, S., & Register, K. (2003). Constant battles: The myth of the peaceful noble savage. New York: St. Martin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1966). On aggression. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manson, J. H., & Wrangham, R. W. (1987). Is human aggression nonbiological? Problems with the statement on violence. Human Ethnology Newsletter, 5(2), 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, M. (1940). Warfare is only an invention—not a biological necessity. Asia, 40(8), 402–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (1967). The naked ape: A zoologist’s study of the human animal. London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, I. (2014). War: What is it good for? New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: Why violence has declined. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, G. (1955). Conflict: The web of group affiliations. Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNESCO. 1986. The Seville Statement. Paris: UNESCO. http://www.culture-of-peace.info/vita/2011/seville2011.pdf. Accessed 21 Feb 2019.

  • Walker, P. (2001). A bioarchaeological perspective on the history of violence. Annual Review of Anthropology, 30, 573–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (2012). Is war inevitable? Discover, June 12. (Excerpted from The social conquest of Earth, New York: Norton, 2012).

  • Wrangham, R., Wilson, M., & Muller, M. (2006). Comparative rates of violence in chimpanzees and humans. Primates, 47, 14–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Azar Gat.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gat, A. Is War in Our Nature?. Hum Nat 30, 149–154 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-019-09342-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-019-09342-8

Keywords

Navigation