Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Evolutionary transitions in heritability and individuality

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Theory in Biosciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

With a few exceptions, the literature on evolutionary transitions in individuality (ETIs) has mostly focused on the relationships between lower-level (particle-level) and higher-level (collective-level) selection, leaving aside the question of the relationship between particle-level and collective-level inheritance. Yet, without an account of this relationship, our hope to fully understand the evolutionary mechanisms underlying ETIs is impeded. To that effect, I present a highly idealized model to study the relationship between particle-level and collective-level heritability both when a collective-level trait is a linear function and when it is a nonlinear function of a particle-level trait. I first show that when a collective trait is a linear function of a particle-level trait, collective-level heritability is a by-product of particle-level heritability. It is equal to particle-level heritability, whether the particles interact randomly or not to form collectives. Second, I show that one effect of population structure is the reduction in variance in offspring collective-level character for a given parental collective. I propose that this reduction in variance is one dimension of individuality. Third, I show that even in the simple case of a nonlinear collective-level character, collective-level heritability is not only weak but also highly dependent on the frequency of the different types of particles in the global population. Finally, I show that population structure, because one of its effects is to reduce the variance in offspring collective-level character, allows not only for an increase in collective-level character but renders it less context dependent. This in turn permits a stable collective-level response to selection. The upshot is that population structure is a driver for ETIs. These results are particularly significant in that the relationship between population structure and collective-level heritability has, to my knowledge, not been previously explored in the context of ETIs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a recent update of the view developed in Maynard Smith and Szathmary (1995), see Szathmary (2015).

  2. Note that because I am interested in the evolutionary origins of individuality, by ‘individual’ I will mean throughout ‘evolutionary’ or ‘Darwinian individual.’ For other definitions of individuality and organismality, see Pepper and Herron (2008), Gilbert et al. (2012), Lidgard and Nyhart (2017a), Godfrey-Smith (2013). Note also that there is some tension with the view that a unit of selection can be equated with Darwinian individuality. In fact, one might consider that individuality ‘emerges’ at one level when not one but a large number of traits at that level exhibit differences in fitness and heritability, while Lewontin’s conditions are trait specific. I will put these problems to the side here and consider the two as synonymous.

  3. Note that the conditions require nevertheless to be slightly amended to fit the specificities of different levels of organization in the context of ETIs. For attempts to amend them, see for instance De Monte and Rainey (2014), Bourrat (2014), Bourrat (2015a), Griesemer (2000).

  4. The notion of context dependence is notoriously ambiguous (Godfrey-Smith 1992; Lloyd 1988, p. 69; Sober and Wilson 1994, p. 539). By ‘context dependence’ in this article, I will mean ‘independent from the particle-type frequencies in the global population.’

  5. For a similar approach to mine, in which the authors analyze the heritability of ‘heterozygosity’ in the context of diploid sexual species in which variation in the environment is not considered, see Nietlisbach et al. (2016).

  6. Recall that I assume that all particles produce the same number of offspring at each generation in an infinitely large population, so that I keep both selection (i.e., difference in fitness associated with differences in phenotype) and drift out of the picture here.

  7. For the difference between the binomial and hypergeometric distributions, see Wroughton and Cole (2013).

  8. For a model based on the ‘wrinkly spreader’ strain of Pseudomonas fluorescens (see Rainey and Rainey 2003; Hammerschmidt et al. 2014), in which a fitness trade-off between collective viability and fecundity is considered, see Rainey and Kerr (2010). The sort of trade-off I have in mind here is slightly different as it concerns fidelity of transmission and fertility.

  9. The notion of allele used here is similar to the one presented in Lu and Bourrat (2018), that is following an evolutionary conception of the gene, not a molecular one.

  10. Thanks to Jonathan Hodge for pointing out this reference to me.

References

  • Black AJ, Bourrat P, Rainey PB (forthcoming) Ecological scaffolding and the evolution of individuality during the transition from cells to multicellular life

  • Bouchard F, Huneman P (eds) (2013) From groups to individuals: evolution and emerging individuality. Vienna series in theoretical biology. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2014) From survivors to replicators: evolution by natural selection revisited. Biol Philos 29(4):517–538

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2015a) How to read ‘Heritability’ in the recipe approach to natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 66(4):883–903

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2015b) Levels of selection are artefacts of different fitness temporal measures. Ratio 28(1):40–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2015c) Levels, time and fitness in evolutionary transitions in individuality. Philos Theory Biol 7:1–17. https://doi.org/10.3998/ptb.6959004.0007.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2016) Generalizing contextual analysis. Acta Biotheor 64(2):197–217

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P, Griffiths PE (2018) Multispecies individuals. Hist Philos Life Sci 40(2)

  • Bourrat P, Lu Q (2017) Dissolving the missing heritability problem. Philos Sci 84(5):1055–1067

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P, Lu Q, Jablonka E (2017) Why the missing heritability might not be in the DNA. BioEssays 39(7):1700067

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss LW (1983) Evolution, development, and the units of selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci 80(5):1387–1391

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Buss LW (1987) The evolution of individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B, Sterelny K (eds) (2011) The major transitions in evolution revisited. Vienna series in theoretical biology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2010) The problem of biological individuality. Biol Theory 5(4):312–325

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2013) The multiple realizability of biological individuals. J Philos 110(8):413–435

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2016a) A levels-of-selection approach to evolutionary individuality. Biol Philos 31(6):893–911

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2016b) Levels of selection in biofilms: multispecies biofilms are not evolutionary individuals. Biol Philos 31(2):191–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Damuth J, Heisler IL (1988) Alternative formulations of multilevel selection. Biol Philos 3(4):407–430

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype: the long reach of the gene. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • De Monte S, Rainey PB (2014) Nascent multicellular life and the emergence of individuality. J Biosci 39(2):237–248

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Downes SM (2009) Heritability. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/heredity/

  • Ereshefsky M, Pedroso M (2013) Biological individuality: the case of biofilms. Biol Philos 28(2):331–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Falconer TE (1996) Introduction to quantitative genetics, 4th edn. Longman, Essex

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Sapp J, Tauber AI (2012) A symbiotic view of life: we have never been individuals. Q Rev Biol 87(4):325–341

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1992) Additivity and the units of selection. In: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol 1992, pp 315–328. https://doi.org/10.2307/192764

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2007) Conditions for evolution by natural selection. J Philos 104:489

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2008) Varieties of population structure and the levels of selection. Br J Philos Sci 59(1):25–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2013) Darwinian individuals. In: Bouchard F, Huneman P (eds) From groups to individuals: evolution and emerging individuality. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 17–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2015) Reproduction, symbiosis, and the eukaryotic cell. Proc Natl Acad Sci 112(33):10,120–10,125

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight CJ (1988) Epistasis and the effect of founder events on the additive genetic variance. Evolution 42(3):441–454

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer J (2000) The units of evolutionary transition. Selection 1(1–3):67–80. https://doi.org/10.1556/Select.1.2000.1-3.7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammerschmidt K, Rose CJ, Kerr B, Rainey PB (2014) Life cycles, fitness decoupling and the evolution of multicellularity

  • Herron MD (2017) Cells, colonies, and clones: individuality in the volvocine algae. In: Lidgard S, Nyhart LK (eds) Biological individuality: integrating scientific, philosophical, and historical perspectives. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 63–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Herron MD, Zamani-Dahaj SA, Ratcliff WC (2018) Trait heritability in major transitions. BMC Biol 16(1):145

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Holtfrerich M, Haughn J (2006) College algebra. Thomson Brooks/Cole, Belmont

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley J (1912) The individual in the animal kingdom. University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacquard A (1983) Heritability: one word, three concepts. Biometrics 39:465–477

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1(1):1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Lidgard S, Nyhart LK (eds) (2017a) Biological individuality: integrating scientific, philosophical, and historical perspectives. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lidgard S, Nyhart LK (2017b) The work of biological individuality: concepts and contexts. In: Lidgard S, Nyhart LK (eds) Biological individuality: integrating scientific, philosophical, and historical perspectives. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 17–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Greenwood Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu Q, Bourrat P (2018) The evolutionary gene and the extended evolutionary synthesis. Br J Philos Sci 69(3):775–800. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axw035

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch KE, Bourrat P (2017) Interpreting heritability causally. Philos Sci 84(1):14–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackay TFC (2014) Epistasis and quantitative traits: using model organisms to study gene-gene interactions. Nat Rev Genet 15(1):22–33

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1987) How to model evolution. In: Dupré J (ed) The latest on the best: essays on evolution and optimality. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 119–131

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1987b) Reply to sober. In: Dupré J (ed) The latest on the best: essays on evolution and optimality, vol 11. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 147–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmary E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. OUP Oxford, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE (1999) Darwinian dynamics. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietlisbach P, Keller LF, Postma E (2016) Genetic variance components and heritability of multiallelic heterozygosity under inbreeding. Heredity 116(1):1–11

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2009) Causality: models, reasoning, and inference, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper JW, Herron MD (2008) Does biology need an organism concept? Biol Rev 83(4):621–627

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–21

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1972) Extension of covariance selection mathematics. Ann Hum Genet 35:485–490

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1997) Cooperators since life began. Q Rev Biol 72(2):184–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainey PB, Kerr B (2010) Cheats as first propagules: a new hypothesis for the evolution of individuality during the transition from single cells to multicellularity. BioEssays 32(10):872–880

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rainey PB, Rainey K (2003) Evolution of cooperation and conflict in experimental bacterial populations. Nature 425:72–74

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (1998) Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sesardic N (2005) Making sense of heritability. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Skillings D (2016) Holobionts and the ecology of organisms: multi-species communities or integrated individuals? Biol Philos 31(6):875–892

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1987) Comment’s on Maynard Smith’s “How to model evolution”. In: Dupré J (ed) The latest on the best: Essays on evolution and optimality, vol 11. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 133–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1994) A critical review of philosophical work on the units of selection problem. Philos Sci 61(4):534–555

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior, vol 218. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Szathmary E (2015) Toward major evolutionary transitions theory 2.0. Proc Natl Acad Sci 112(33):10104–10111

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Tal O (2009) From heritability to probability. Biol Philos 24(1):81–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Tal O (2012) The impact of gene-environment interaction and correlation on the interpretation of heritability. Acta Biotheor 60(3):225–237

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ (2016) Adaptation in metapopulations: how interaction changes evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Weir BS, Cockerham CC (1984) Estimating F-statistics for the analysis of population structure. Evolution 38(6):1358–1370

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection: a critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (1975) A theory of group selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci 72(1):143–146

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1931) Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics 16(2):97–159

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1949) The genetical structure of populations. Ann Eugen 15(1):323–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Wroughton J, Cole T (2013) Distinguishing between binomial, hypergeometric and negative binomial distributions. J Stat Educ 21(1):1–16

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am thankful to Matthew Herron, Michael Bentley, and two anonymous reviewers who provided useful feedback on previous versions of this manuscript. I am also thankful to the Theory and Method in Biosciences group at the University of Sydney and more particularly Stefan Gawronski who proofread the final manuscript. This research was supported by a Macquarie University Research Fellowship and a Large Grant from the John Templeton Foundation (Grant ID 60811).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierrick Bourrat.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bourrat, P. Evolutionary transitions in heritability and individuality. Theory Biosci. 138, 305–323 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-019-00294-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-019-00294-2

Keywords

Navigation