Skip to main content
Log in

The Conception of Life in Synthetic Biology

  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The phrase ‘synthetic biology’ is used to describe a set of different scientific and technological disciplines, which share the objective to design and produce new life forms. This essay addresses the following questions: What conception of life stands behind this ambitious objective? In what relation does this conception of life stand to that of traditional biology and biotechnology? And, could such a conception of life raise ethical concerns? Three different observations that provide useful indications for the conception of life in synthetic biology will be discussed in detail: 1. Synthetic biologists focus on different features of living organisms in order to design new life forms, 2. Synthetic biologists want to contribute to the understanding of life, and 3. Synthetic biologists want to modify life through a rational design, which implies the notions of utilising, minimising/optimising, varying and overcoming life. These observations indicate a tight connection between science and technology, a focus on selected aspects of life, a production-oriented approach to life, and a design-oriented understanding of life. It will be argued that through this conception of life synthetic biologists present life in a different light. This conception of life will be illustrated by the metaphor of a toolbox. According to the notion of life as a toolbox, the different features of living organisms are perceived as various rationally designed instruments that can be used for the production of the living organism itself or secondary products made by the organism. According to certain ethical positions this conception of life might raise ethical concerns related to the status of the organism, the motives of the scientists and the role of technology in our society.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In biology “markers” indicate certain biological objects or properties. Genetic markers are for instance used to follow chromosomes or traits over generations.

  2. Some comments on features 2 and 7 on my list: Feature 2: The term “autopoiesis” has been introduced by the Chilean Biologists H. Maturana and F. Varela as the only necessary and sufficient feature to describe and explain life (Maturana and Varela 1980). I apply the term here not to refer to the complete theory of autopoiesis but to summarize the features of self-maintenance, self-production and an external boundary, which in different wordings occur on most of the quoted lists.

    Feature 7: Of the four lists quoted here, “active response to the environment” only appears on E. Mayr’s list as “capacity for response to stimuli from the environment”. However, this feature is also extensively discussed by biologists for instance in context of biosemiotics (Kull et al. 2009) or modern interpretations of the autopoiesis theory (Bitbol and Luisi 2004).

  3. In contrast to the discipline ALife (artificial life), which develops computer programs that reproduce and evolve themselves, the idea with the computer simulations in in silico synthetic biology is that they represent processes, which could be integrated into material living organisms.

  4. Rational design in the unnatural molecular biology approach could for instance be applied for the development of alternative genetic codes, to design HNA or GNA nucleotides (Schmidt 2010) or alternative nucleobases (Benner and Sismour 2005).

  5. Some synthetic biologists increasingly apply directed evolution as a non-rational designing aid (Dougherty and Arnold 2009). This constitutes an interesting withdrawal from the machine-analogy. One could argue that the application of directed evolution that might indicate that in the end, the rational design of a living organism might be beyond human capacities.

  6. As described above, “growth” is a direct consequence of feature 1. constant transformation. “Reproduction” has been mentioned as part of feature 6. evolution related to the capacity of living organisms to form lineages that can evolve.

  7. “Natural” is understood here as “not intended by a human design”.

  8. In this context, synthetic biologists use the term “orthogonality”: orthogonal systems are characterised by their ability to process information independently from natural systems, without crosstalk between the natural and the synthetic systems. At the moment, such orthogonal systems are introduced into organisms that still rely on the natural coding system (Neumann et al. 2010). However, one could imagine that eventually living organisms may be produced, which are based exclusively on the alternative information system.

  9. “Overcoming” is understood here in the sense of overcoming obstacles, problems or limits.

  10. According to certain definitions of machines living organisms would not be part of this group at all, see for instance Oxford English Dictionary Definition II, Machine: “A material structure designed for a specific purpose, and related uses.”.

  11. Except of those bioegineers who explicitly want to overcome evolution and those who apply directed evolution as a designing aid, most synthetic biologists just accept evolution as an aspect of their products, which seems not to be of too much interest.

  12. See foonote 6.

  13. See footnote 5 .

  14. A related dual role of life as producer and as product has been highlighted by the autopoiesis theory but without reference to human involvement or purposes.

References

  • Andrianantoandro, E., Basu, S., Karig, D. K., & Weiss, R. (2006). Synthetic biology: new engineering rules for an emerging discipline. Molecular Systems Biology, 2, 1–14. doi:10.1038/msb4100073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anonymous (2006). Life 2.0. The Economist, August, 67–69.

  • Attfield, R. (1998). Intrinsic value and transgenic animals. In A. Holland & A. Johnson (Eds.), Animal biotechnology and ethics (pp. 172–189). London: Chapman & Hall.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, D., Church, G., Collins, J., Endy, D., Jacobson, J., Keasling, J., et al. (2006). Engineering life: Building a FAB for biology (pp. 44–51). USA: Scientific American.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner, S. A. (2004). Understanding nucleic acids using synthetic chemistry. Accounts of Chemical Research, 37(10), 784–797. doi:10.1021/ar040004z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benner, S. A., & Sismour, A. M. (2005). Synthetic biology. Nature Reviews Genetics, 6(7), 533–543. doi:10.1038/nrg1637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom, D. E. (2009). Unnatural nucleosides with unusual base pairing properties. Curr Protoc Nucleic Acid Chem, Chapter 1, Unit 1 4, doi:10.1002/0471142700.nc0104s37.

  • Bitbol, M., & Luisi, P. L. (2004). Autopoiesis with or without cognition: defining life at its edge. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 1(1), 99–107. doi:10.1098/rsif.2004.0012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boldt, J., & Muller, O. (2008). Newtons of the leaves of grass. Nature Biotechnology, 26(4), 387–389. doi:10.1038/nbt0408-387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boldt, J., Müller, O., & Maio, G. (2009). Synthetische Biologie Eine ethisch-philosophische Analyse. Bern: BBL (Bundesamt für Bauten und Logistik).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, P. A., & Church, G. M. (2009). Genome engineering. Nature Biotechnology, 27(12), 1151–1162. doi:10.1038/nbt.1590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cho, M. K., Magnus, D., Caplan, A. L., & McGee, D. (1999). Policy forum: genetics. Ethical considerations in synthesizing a minimal genome. Science, 286(5447), 2087, 2089–2090.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deamer, D. (2010). Special collection of essays: What is life? Introduction. Astrobiology, 10(10), 1001–1002. doi:10.1089/ast.2010.0569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deplazes, A. (2009). Piecing together a puzzle. An exposition of synthetic biology. EMBO Reports, 10(5), 428–432. doi:10.1038/embor.2009.76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deplazes, A., & Huppenbauer, M. (2009). Synthetic organisms and living machines: Positioning the products of synthetic biology at the borderline between living and non-living matter. Systems and Synthetic Biology, 3(1–4), 55–63. doi:10.1007/s11693-009-9029-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1985–1988). Discourse on the method. In Cottingham J., Soothoff R., & Murdoch D. (Eds.), The philosophical writings of descartes 3 vol (Vol. 1, pp. 109–177). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Dougherty, M. J., & Arnold, F. H. (2009). Directed evolution: New parts and optimized function. Current Opinion in Biotechnology, 20(4), 486–491. doi:10.1016/j.copbio.2009.08.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drubin, D. A., Way, J. C., & Silver, P. A. (2007). Designing biological systems. Genes and Development, 21(3), 242–254. doi:10.1101/gad.1507207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Endy, D. (2005). Foundations for engineering biology. Nature, 438(7067), 449–453. doi:10.1038/nature04342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (2003). The principles of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glass, J. I., Assad-Garcia, N., Alperovich, N., Yooseph, S., Lewis, M. R., Maruf, M., et al. (2006). Essential genes of a minimal bacterium. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 103(2), 425–430. doi:10.1073/pnas.0510013103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology and other essays (W. Lovitt, Trans.). New York: Harper Torchbooks.

  • Heinemann, M., & Panke, S. (2006). Synthetic biology-putting engineering into biology. Bioinformatics, 22(22), 2790–2799. doi:10.1093/bioinformatics/btl469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hold, C., & Panke, S. (2009). Towards the engineering of in vitro systems. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 6, 507–521. doi:10.1098/rsif.2009.0110.focus.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, R. A. (2008). Synthetic genomes brought closer to life. Nature Biotechnology, 26(3), 296–297. doi:10.1038/nbt0308-296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2007). Virtue Ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/.

  • iGEM (2007). About iGEM. http://parts.mit.edu/wiki/index.php/About_iGEM.

  • Jonas, H. (1985). The imperative of responsibility in search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago (Ill.): The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koshland, D. E., Jr. (2002). Special essay. The seven pillars of life. Science, 295(5563), 2215–2216. doi:10.1126/science.1068489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K., Deacon, T., Emmeche, C., Hoffmeyer, J., & Frederik, S. (2009). Theses on biosemiotics: Prolegomena to a theoretical biology. Biological Theory, 4(2), 167–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • La Mettrie, J. O. (1996). Machine man. In A. Thomsom (Ed.), Machine man and other writings (pp. 1–41). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P. L. (2002). Toward the engineering of minimal living cells. Anatomical Record, 268(3), 208–214. doi:10.1002/ar.10155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P. L. (2003). Autopoiesis: A review and a reappraisal. Naturwissenschaften, 90(2), 49–59. doi:10.1007/s00114-002-0389-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P. L. (2006). The emergence of life, from chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. H., Nielsen, D. R., Solomon, K. V., & Prather, K. L. (2009). Synthetic metabolism: Engineering biology at the protein and pathway scales. Chemistry and Biology, 16(3), 277–286. doi:10.1016/j.chembiol.2009.01.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1997). This is biology: The science of the living world. Cambridge: Harward University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M. (2009). A new revolution? The place of systems biology and synthetic biology in the history of biology. EMBO Reports, 10(Suppl 1), S50–S53. doi:10.1038/embor.2009.156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moya, A., Krasnogor, N., Pereto, J., & Latorre, A. (2009). Goethe’s dream. Challenges and opportunities for synthetic biology. EMBO Reports, 10, 28–32. doi:10.1038/embor.2009.120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, H., Wang, K., Davis, L., Garcia-Alai, M., & Chin, J. W. (2010). Encoding multiple unnatural amino acids via evolution of a quadruplet-decoding ribosome. Nature, 464(7287), 441–444. doi:10.1038/nature08817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M. A., Powell, A., Davies, J. F., & Calvert, J. (2008). Knowledge-making distinctions in synthetic biology. Bioessays, 30(1), 57–65. doi:10.1002/bies.20664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purnick, P. E., & Weiss, R. (2009). The second wave of synthetic biology: from modules to systems. Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology, 10(6), 410–422. doi:10.1038/nrm2698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riskin, J. (2003). The defecating duck, or, the ambiguous origins of artificial life. Critical Inquiry, 29(4), 599–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M. (2010). Xenobiology: A new form of life as the ultimate biosafety tool. Bioessays, 32(4), 322–331. doi:10.1002/bies.200900147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulze-Makuch, D., & Irwin, L. N. (2006). The prospect of alien life in exotic forms on other worlds. Naturwissenschaften, 93(4), 155–172. doi:10.1007/s00114-005-0078-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, M. L. (2006). Cell-free synthetic biology: A bottom-up approach to discovery by design. Molecular Systems Biology, 2, 69. doi:10.1038/msb4100104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stano, P., & Luisi, P. L. (2010). Achievements and open questions in the self-reproduction of vesicles and synthetic minimal cells. Chemical Communications (Camb), 46(21), 3639–3653. doi:10.1039/b913997d.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmary, E. (2003). Why are there four letters in the genetic alphabet? Nature Reviews Genetics, 4(12), 995–1001. doi:10.1038/nrg1231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, P. W. (1986). Respect for nature a theory of environmental ethics. Princeton (NJ): Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vriend, H.d. (2006). Constructing life early social reflections on the emerging field of synthetic biology. De Hague, Netherlands: Rathenau Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, L., Xie, J., & Schultz, P. G. (2006). Expanding the genetic code. Annual Review of Biophysics and Biomolecular Structure, 35, 225–249. doi:10.1146/annurev.biophys.35.101105.121507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, E., Mueller, S., Tumpey, T. M., & Taubenberger, J. K. (2009). Synthetic viruses: a new opportunity to understand and prevent viral disease. Nature Biotechnology, 27(12), 1163–1172. doi:10.1038/nbt.1593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Christoph Rehmann-Sutter, Agomoni Ganguli-Mitra and Lothar Deplazes for helpful comments on this article. Moreover, I thank the members of the workshop “The Definition of Life in Times of its Technical Producibility: Ethical, Legal and Social Challenges of Synthetic Biology” that has been organised by Peter Dabrock and collaborators, for their suggestions, and three anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of the manuscript. This work was supported by the URPP (University Research Priority Programme) Ethics of the University of Zurich and by a grant from the European Commission’s 7th framework programme in the category “Science in Society” for the project “SYBHEL: Synthetic Biology for Human Health: Ethical and Legal Issues”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anna Deplazes-Zemp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Deplazes-Zemp, A. The Conception of Life in Synthetic Biology. Sci Eng Ethics 18, 757–774 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9269-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9269-z

Keywords

Navigation